Eidos As Norm in Aristotle's Biology

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Eidos As Norm in Aristotle's Biology Binghamton University The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB) The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter 12-1977 Eidos as Norm in Aristotle's Biology Anthony Preus Binghamton University--SUNY, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://orb.binghamton.edu/sagp Part of the Ancient History, Greek and Roman through Late Antiquity Commons, Ancient Philosophy Commons, and the History of Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Preus, Anthony, "Eidos as Norm in Aristotle's Biology" (1977). The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter. 86. https://orb.binghamton.edu/sagp/86 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB). It has been accepted for inclusion in The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter by an authorized administrator of The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB). For more information, please contact [email protected]. /) ( '• sophy, 1977 for t he Society for Ancient Greek Philo EIDOS AS NORM (in Aristotle's Biology) Anthony Preus, SUNY Binghamton Introduction Aristotle and Modern Taxonomy Aristotle and Noah's Ark Genetic and Phenetic Species Three Normative Determinants of eidos The Taxonomy of Pleasures The Taxonomy of Constitutions Intro4uction Eidos, species or form, is a central concept in many of Aristotle's works, but the peculiarly Aristotelian character of the eidos concept was developed in his biological investigations. Some scholars have studied the meanin¥ of "eidos11 in the biological works, notably Marjorie Grene and David Balme; the present essay begins with an exploration of the same territory, but perhaps not always on the same paths. Once the biological sense of 11eidos" has been presented, it will be possible to compare uses of this concept in the normative treatises. Two passages will be examined, Nicomachean Ethics X.4-5, and Politics IV, especially IV.4. In both places Aristotle appeals to the biological concept of eidos in order to explain, in the one instance, pleasure and the kinds of pleas·ures, in the other, the reasons for the va ri a tions in the kinds of government. This essay will not examine the concept of eidos as it appears in the Metaphysics, although it is clear that an understanding of the biological concept of eidos would increase comprehension of many passages in that'work, just as the metaphysi ca 1 uses of 11eidos" are often assumed and influential in the biologica 1 works. Indeed, Aristotle distinguishes his own philosophy from that of Plato partially in terms of the biological sense of eidos: It is obvious that the generator is the same in kind as the generated in the case of natural products (for man begets man) ••• so it is quite unnecessary to set up a Form ( eidos ) as a pattern ••• • The begetter is adequate to the making of the product and responsible for the eidos being in the matter. (Metaphysics Z.8, l 033b30ff) Aristotle and Modern Ta:I1onomy A useful step in explaining Aristotle's biological sense of eidos as species or form is an examination of the meaning of 'species' for the modern philosopher and scientist. Ontologists and logicians often suppose that biological species are paradigmatic and intuitively obvious cases of natural kinds, from which one might confidently work toward a future ontology.2 Biologists themselves admit difficulty in distinguishing species, to the extent that many taxonomists believe that species distinctions are essentially and necessarily arbitrary. The living world is seen as continuous, in two ways: in the first way, Darwinian evolutionary theory assumes that speciation over time occurs in very small steps; each generation belongs to the same species as its parents, but each individual has ancestors at some number of generations which are not the same in species. Thus there are no determinate temporal boundaries of species. Secondly, some parts of the 1 iving world present synchronic polytypical continuities, called 11clines11, in which variations are subspecific from each local population to • E4nls as nlam 2 <ad ts ehd ndxe, bte eypds admlidn ae slmd n4seancd aad jtngdn, by any seannaan, el bd lf n4ffdadne spd c4ds.3 1hts ehdad sddm el bd nl ndpdnnabld cl,edmplaal bltnnaa4dsbdewddn s p dc4ds. If a 4s ehd samd 4n spdc4ds as b, ann b 4s ehd samd 4n spdc 4ds as c, 4e sddms nle ndcdssa ay bte clne4n gdne ehae a bd ehd samd 4n spdc4dsa s c . Cl,spdc4f4c4e y 4s n l endcds saa4lya eaans4e4idadlae 4 l n ,l a · aaehda 4e 4s a l4m4ednly eaan s4e4i d adlae4ln. Mlndan b4lllg4ses appalach ehd palbldm lf n4se4ngt4sh4ng k4nns 4n sdidaal n4ffdadne ways. Slmd 4 seaae falm ehd lbsdaidn s4m4laa4e4ds ann n4ss4m4laa4e4ds, fddn4ng ntmda4cally analyzdn naea ablte ehd phdnleypd, ehd appaadne.flam, 4nel a clmptedal ehd palc dn tad lwds mtch el Htmd ann pls4e4i4sm, ann cla4ms el bd lbjdce4id ann ptadly dmp4a4cal. Oehda b4lllg4 ses bdl4did ehae gdnde4c adlae4lnsh4ps aad ehd bas4s lf class mdmbdash4p, ann ehts aeedmpe el class4fy acclan4ng d4ehda el gdnleypd (tle4maedly ann pdahaps 4ndally, by ehd 4nflamae4ln clnedne lf ehd DNI) la by gdndallgy, by analys4s lf ehd dillte4lnaay ndscdne lf ehd 4nn4i4ntal la plptlae4ln.s ' a4seleld ann Nlah's <k D4achaln4c ann synchaln4c cln e4n t4e4ds aad eakdn el bd glln di4ndncd aga4nse a eaxlnlm4c ehdlay wh4ch Maya, fla dxampld (1969, p. 66), calls Ia4seledl4an dssdne4al4sm la 'eyplllgy'l '1h4s ph4llslphy • • • aeedmpes el ass4gn ehd iaa4ab4l4ey lf naetad el a f4xdn ntmbda lf bas4c eypds ae iaa4lts ldidls • .Ie plsetlaeds e h a ea l lm d m b d al s f a e a x l na d f l d ce e h ds a m dd s s d n e 4n a al e t a dl , a n l e h d aw l a n s e h a ee h d yc l n f l ae m l e h ds a m de y p d . 'S 4 n c dI a 4 s e l en l ld d sn l es d d me l h a i db d d n an dssdne4al4se 4n ehd sdnsd n4se4ngt4shdn by Maya , I wltln padfda el call eh4s ehdlay 'Nlah's Iak' Essdne 4al4sm.116 1hd plptlaa tnndaseann4ng lf spdc4ds lfedn nlds 4ncltnd ehd 4nda ehae 4e wltln bd plss4bld fla a n4l4gdne Nlah el sd ldce appalpa4aed samplds lf dach b4lllg4cal kfln fda 4nclts4ln 4n slmd capac4lts aak · (la, fla ehae maeeda, a mtsdtm la zll)l mlndan eaxlnlm4ses assdae ehae stch a Nlah wltln fa dqtdnely bd facdn by nln,lbi4lts n4se4nce4lns el bd mand, tnldss slmd Inam (el clne4ntd ehd B4bl4cal mdeaphla) han aladany mand ehdm by sdldce4ng paaa n4g 1ae4C' casds � ('hllleypds') ann sdee4ng ehd bltnnaa4ds lf ehd k4nns .. 1hae Ia4seleld was nle a Nlah's Iak Essdne4al4se may bd sddn falm passagds l4kd < aes lf Inmals IV.5, 68lal2,l5c 'Naetad palcddns clne4ntltsly falm 4nan4maed eh4ngs el ehd an4mals ehaltgh l4i4ng eh4ngs wh4ch aad nle an4mals, sl ehae ehdad sddms el bd an 4nf4n4eds4mal n4ffdadncd falm lnd class el ehd ndxe.'7 H4s ehdlay l f ' n t a l 4 s 4 n ga 1s 1I ,. L . < d c k ac a l l s� a a µ < l H c p { la c l 4 s i l , . c l t na e g s a 4 n sa e n y alldg4ancd el Nlah's Iak Essdne4al4sm. K4nns lf an4.mals 'ntal4zd' 4f ehdy haid c h a a a c e de a 4 4 c s sw h 4 c ha a de y p 4 c al l f e w ln 4 f f d a d na e n , n g d n d a a ls l dy p a a a e d , classds. Sda,an4mals wh4ch l4id aeeachdn 'nta l4zd' w4eh planesl9 ehd gdnls . lf p4gs ntal 4zds bdcatsd ehda d aad bl eh cl lid n,hllidn ann sll4n,hlli.dn stbs pdc 4d sl � 0 ehd hdam4e caab ntal4zds bdewddn caayf4sh (4n adspdce lf phys4s ) ann edseac da ( 4 nm a n n dl a f 1 4 f d ) l 1p 1 a 4 m a e d s n t a l 4 z d bm d a e n wa d n d nq n t a n a t pl d 2n lc d e a ca d n s ' a a d4 n a w ay b l e hl a n na n nw aed a a n 4a m l s1 l1 13 s d a l sa n nb a e sa l s ln ta l4 z d ,4 1 s d a l sb d e w d dl n a n na n nw a e d a , aa n l4 sm ,b a e sb d e w d dl n a n n , a na 4 l m sa n n f l 4 d a s c 1101. cltcl &µpl1dpwi cc µcc'xlt a4 Ka4 etlcccpwi, ehts ehdy aad lf bleh ann n d 4 e h d a( ' 6 7 9 b 2 ) .S 4 m 4 l ay a e l h dl s e a 4 ch h a s' s l m de h 4 n gl s f a b 4 a n ,a n ns l m d lf a qtanatpdn' (697bl5). I ntal4z4ng an 4mal 4s nle dxacely a blandal4 nd casdl aaehda 4e 4s an dxampld lf ehd n4ff4 ctley, 4f nle 4mpls s4b4l4ey, lf ndidllp4ng Eidos as Norm 3 Preus hard-line distinctions between kinds of life. Even more clearly, the generation of mules indicates the fuzziness of the edges of the species-concept in Aristotle; the mule forms a genos, even if agonon.15 Should Noah include mules in his ark or not? Aristotle does say some things which sound rather like Noah1s Ark Essentialism, for example in Parts of AnimaZ.S I.4, 644a24ff: ••• it is the ultimate species (eide)that are beings (ousiai), while these things [those which differ by the more and the less] (like Socrates and Coriscus) are undifferentiated in respect of species..
Recommended publications
  • Philosophy 320: Knowledge and Assertion
    Course Syllabus: Philosophy 320: Knowledge and Assertion Matthew A. Benton [email protected] Description This 300-level upper-division undergraduate course, intended primarily for philosophy majors, will cover the literature on a fascinating question that has recently surfaced at the intersection of epistemology and philosophy of language: whether knowledge is the norm of assertion. The idea behind such a view is that in our standard conversational contexts, one who flat-out asserts that something is the case somehow represents herself as knowing that thing, and thus, there is a norm to the effect that one ought not to flat-out assert something unless one knows it. Proponents of the knowledge-norm have appealed to several strands of data from ordinary conversation practice and problematic sentences to sup- port their view; but other philosophers have leveled counterarguments. This course will evaluate the debate, including the most recent installments from the cutting edge of the philosophical literature. The course will meet a demand amongst undergraduates to study this re- cently (and hotly) debated issue: the literature relating knowledge and assertion is new enough that it is not typically covered by other undergraduate courses in epistemology or philosophy of language. It will hold special appeal for un- dergraduates with cross-disciplinary interests in language, epistemology, and communal/social normativity, and will provide a rich background for those who want to do further advanced study in philosophy or linguistics. Course Requirements Weekly readings and mandatory class attendance; students missing more than 5 class sessions will have their final grade lowered a half grade for each additional absence.
    [Show full text]
  • Revised Glossary for AQA GCSE Biology Student Book
    Biology Glossary amino acids small molecules from which proteins are A built abiotic factor physical or non-living conditions amylase a digestive enzyme (carbohydrase) that that affect the distribution of a population in an breaks down starch ecosystem, such as light, temperature, soil pH anaerobic respiration respiration without using absorption the process by which soluble products oxygen of digestion move into the blood from the small intestine antibacterial chemicals chemicals produced by plants as a defence mechanism; the amount abstinence method of contraception whereby the produced will increase if the plant is under attack couple refrains from intercourse, particularly when an egg might be in the oviduct antibiotic e.g. penicillin; medicines that work inside the body to kill bacterial pathogens accommodation ability of the eyes to change focus antibody protein normally present in the body acid rain rain water which is made more acidic by or produced in response to an antigen, which it pollutant gases neutralises, thus producing an immune response active site the place on an enzyme where the antimicrobial resistance (AMR) an increasing substrate molecule binds problem in the twenty-first century whereby active transport in active transport, cells use energy bacteria have evolved to develop resistance against to transport substances through cell membranes antibiotics due to their overuse against a concentration gradient antiretroviral drugs drugs used to treat HIV adaptation features that organisms have to help infections; they
    [Show full text]
  • 1 Epistemic Norms of Political Deliberation Fabienne Peter
    Epistemic norms of political deliberation Fabienne Peter, University of Warwick ([email protected]) December 2020 Forthcoming in Michael Hannon and Jeroen de Ridder (eds.) Routledge Handbook of Political Epistemology (https://www.routledge.com/The-Routledge-Handbook-of-Political- Epistemology/Hannon-Ridder/p/book/9780367345907). Please cite the published version. Abstract Legitimate political decision-making is underpinned by well-ordered political deliberation, including by the decision-makers themselves, their advisory bodies, and the public at large. But what constitutes well-ordered political deliberation? The short answer to this question is that it’s political deliberation that is governed by relevant norms. In this chapter, I first discuss different types of norms that might govern well-ordered political deliberation. I then focus on one particular type of norms: epistemic norms. My aim in this chapter is to shed light on how the validity of contributions to political deliberation depends, inter alia, on the epistemic status of the claims made. 1. Introduction Political deliberation is the broad, multi-stranded process in which political proposals get considered and critically scrutinised.1 There are many forums in which political deliberation takes place. Some of them are formal institutions of government such as the cabinet and parliament. Other forums of political deliberation include advisory bodies, government agencies, political parties and interest groups, the press and other broadcasters, and, increasingly, social media platforms. The latter are not directly associated with political 1 I have received helpful comments on an earlier version of this chapter from Jeroen de Ridder, Michael Hannon, and an external referee. I also benefitted from conversations with Nathalie Ashton, Rowan Cruft, and Jonathan Heawood in the context of our ARHC project on Norms for the New Public Sphere and from discussions at a NYU Political Economy and Political Theory workshop, especially with Dimitri Landa, Ryan Pevnick, and Melissa Schwartzberg.
    [Show full text]
  • The Taxonomy of Primates in the Laboratory Context
    P0800261_01 7/14/05 8:00 AM Page 3 C HAPTER 1 The Taxonomy of Primates T HE T in the Laboratory Context AXONOMY OF P Colin Groves RIMATES School of Archaeology and Anthropology, Australian National University, Canberra, ACT 0200, Australia 3 What are species? D Taxonomy: EFINITION OF THE The biological Organizing nature species concept Taxonomy means classifying organisms. It is nowadays commonly used as a synonym for systematics, though Disagreement as to what precisely constitutes a species P strictly speaking systematics is a much broader sphere is to be expected, given that the concept serves so many RIMATE of interest – interrelationships, and biodiversity. At the functions (Vane-Wright, 1992). We may be interested basis of taxonomy lies that much-debated concept, the in classification as such, or in the evolutionary implica- species. tions of species; in the theory of species, or in simply M ODEL Because there is so much misunderstanding about how to recognize them; or in their reproductive, phys- what a species is, it is necessary to give some space to iological, or husbandry status. discussion of the concept. The importance of what we Most non-specialists probably have some vague mean by the word “species” goes way beyond taxonomy idea that species are defined by not interbreeding with as such: it affects such diverse fields as genetics, biogeog- each other; usually, that hybrids between different species raphy, population biology, ecology, ethology, and bio- are sterile, or that they are incapable of hybridizing at diversity; in an era in which threats to the natural all. Such an impression ultimately derives from the def- world and its biodiversity are accelerating, it affects inition by Mayr (1940), whereby species are “groups of conservation strategies (Rojas, 1992).
    [Show full text]
  • Species Concepts and the Evolutionary Paradigm in Modern Nematology
    JOURNAL OF NEMATOLOGY VOLUME 30 MARCH 1998 NUMBER 1 Journal of Nematology 30 (1) :1-21. 1998. © The Society of Nematologists 1998. Species Concepts and the Evolutionary Paradigm in Modern Nematology BYRON J. ADAMS 1 Abstract: Given the task of recovering and representing evolutionary history, nematode taxonomists can choose from among several species concepts. All species concepts have theoretical and (or) opera- tional inconsistencies that can result in failure to accurately recover and represent species. This failure not only obfuscates nematode taxonomy but hinders other research programs in hematology that are dependent upon a phylogenetically correct taxonomy, such as biodiversity, biogeography, cospeciation, coevolution, and adaptation. Three types of systematic errors inherent in different species concepts and their potential effects on these research programs are presented. These errors include overestimating and underestimating the number of species (type I and II error, respectively) and misrepresenting their phylogenetic relationships (type III error). For research programs in hematology that utilize recovered evolutionary history, type II and III errors are the most serious. Linnean, biological, evolutionary, and phylogenefic species concepts are evaluated based on their sensitivity to systematic error. Linnean and biologica[ species concepts are more prone to serious systematic error than evolutionary or phylogenetic concepts. As an alternative to the current paradigm, an amalgamation of evolutionary and phylogenetic species concepts is advocated, along with a set of discovery operations designed to minimize the risk of making systematic errors. Examples of these operations are applied to species and isolates of Heterorhab- ditis. Key words: adaptation, biodiversity, biogeography, coevolufion, comparative method, cospeciation, evolution, nematode, philosophy, species concepts, systematics, taxonomy.
    [Show full text]
  • Human Anatomy (Biology 2) Lecture Notes Updated July 2017 Instructor
    Human Anatomy (Biology 2) Lecture Notes Updated July 2017 Instructor: Rebecca Bailey 1 Chapter 1 The Human Body: An Orientation • Terms - Anatomy: the study of body structure and relationships among structures - Physiology: the study of body function • Levels of Organization - Chemical level 1. atoms and molecules - Cells 1. the basic unit of all living things - Tissues 1. cells join together to perform a particular function - Organs 1. tissues join together to perform a particular function - Organ system 1. organs join together to perform a particular function - Organismal 1. the whole body • Organ Systems • Anatomical Position • Regional Names - Axial region 1. head 2. neck 3. trunk a. thorax b. abdomen c. pelvis d. perineum - Appendicular region 1. limbs • Directional Terms - Superior (above) vs. Inferior (below) - Anterior (toward the front) vs. Posterior (toward the back)(Dorsal vs. Ventral) - Medial (toward the midline) vs. Lateral (away from the midline) - Intermediate (between a more medial and a more lateral structure) - Proximal (closer to the point of origin) vs. Distal (farther from the point of origin) - Superficial (toward the surface) vs. Deep (away from the surface) • Planes and Sections divide the body or organ - Frontal or coronal 1. divides into anterior/posterior 2 - Sagittal 1. divides into right and left halves 2. includes midsagittal and parasagittal - Transverse or cross-sectional 1. divides into superior/inferior • Body Cavities - Dorsal 1. cranial cavity 2. vertebral cavity - Ventral 1. lined with serous membrane 2. viscera (organs) covered by serous membrane 3. thoracic cavity a. two pleural cavities contain the lungs b. pericardial cavity contains heart c. the cavities are defined by serous membrane d.
    [Show full text]
  • Life with Augustine
    Life with Augustine ...a course in his spirit and guidance for daily living By Edmond A. Maher ii Life with Augustine © 2002 Augustinian Press Australia Sydney, Australia. Acknowledgements: The author wishes to acknowledge and thank the following people: ► the Augustinian Province of Our Mother of Good Counsel, Australia, for support- ing this project, with special mention of Pat Fahey osa, Kevin Burman osa, Pat Codd osa and Peter Jones osa ► Laurence Mooney osa for assistance in editing ► Michael Morahan osa for formatting this 2nd Edition ► John Coles, Peter Gagan, Dr. Frank McGrath fms (Brisbane CEO), Benet Fonck ofm, Peter Keogh sfo for sharing their vast experience in adult education ► John Rotelle osa, for granting us permission to use his English translation of Tarcisius van Bavel’s work Augustine (full bibliography within) and for his scholarly advice Megan Atkins for her formatting suggestions in the 1st Edition, that have carried over into this the 2nd ► those generous people who have completed the 1st Edition and suggested valuable improvements, especially Kath Neehouse and friends at Villanova College, Brisbane Foreword 1 Dear Participant Saint Augustine of Hippo is a figure in our history who has appealed to the curiosity and imagination of many generations. He is well known for being both sinner and saint, for being a bishop yet also a fellow pilgrim on the journey to God. One of the most popular and attractive persons across many centuries, his influence on the church has continued to our current day. He is also renowned for his influ- ence in philosophy and psychology and even (in an indirect way) art, music and architecture.
    [Show full text]
  • Norm (Philosophy) from Wikipedia, the Free Encyclopedia
    Norm (philosophy) From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia Norms are concepts (sentences) of practical import, oriented to effecting an action, rather than conceptual abstractions that describe, explain, and express. Normative sentences imply "ought-to" types of statements and assertions, in distinction to sentences that provide "is" types of statements and assertions. Common normative sentences include commands, permissions, and prohibitions; common normative abstract concepts include sincerity, justification, and honesty. A popular account of norms describes them as reasons to take action, to believe, and to feel. Types of norms Orders and permissions express norms. Such norm sentences do not describe how the world is, they rather prescribe how the world should be. Imperative sentences are the most obvious way to express norms, but declarative sentences also may be norms, as is the case with laws or 'principles'. Generally, whether an expression is a norm depends on what the sentence intends to assert. For instance, a sentence of the form "All Ravens are Black" could on one account be taken as descriptive, in which case an instance of a white raven would contradict it, or alternatively "All Ravens are Black" could be interpreted as a norm, in which case it stands as a principle and definition, so 'a white raven' would then not be a raven. Those norms purporting to create obligations (or duties) and permissions are called deontic norms (see also deontic logic). The concept of deontic norm is already an extension of a previous concept of norm, which would only include imperatives, that is, norms purporting to create duties. The understanding that permissions are norms in the same way was an important step in ethics and philosophy of law.
    [Show full text]
  • Plato the ALLEGORY of the CAVE Republic, VII 514 A, 2 to 517 A, 7
    Plato THE ALLEGORY OF THE CAVE Republic, VII 514 a, 2 to 517 a, 7 Translation by Thomas Sheehan THE ALLEGORY OF THE CAVE SOCRATES: Next, said I [= Socrates], compare our nature in respect of education and its lack to such an experience as this. PART ONE: SETTING THE SCENE: THE CAVE AND THE FIRE The cave SOCRATES: Imagine this: People live under the earth in a cavelike dwelling. Stretching a long way up toward the daylight is its entrance, toward which the entire cave is gathered. The people have been in this dwelling since childhood, shackled by the legs and neck..Thus they stay in the same place so that there is only one thing for them to look that: whatever they encounter in front of their faces. But because they are shackled, they are unable to turn their heads around. A fire is behind them, and there is a wall between the fire and the prisoners SOCRATES: Some light, of course, is allowed them, namely from a fire that casts its glow toward them from behind them, being above and at some distance. Between the fire and those who are shackled [i.e., behind their backs] there runs a walkway at a certain height. Imagine that a low wall has been built the length of the walkway, like the low curtain that puppeteers put up, over which they show their puppets. The images carried before the fire SOCRATES: So now imagine that all along this low wall people are carrying all sorts of things that reach up higher than the wall: statues and other carvings made of stone or wood and many other artifacts that people have made.
    [Show full text]
  • Norm Manipulation, Norm Evasion: Experimental Evidence
    University of Pennsylvania ScholarlyCommons Behavioral Ethics Lab Philosophy, Politics and Economics 2013 Norm Manipulation, Norm Evasion: Experimental Evidence Cristina Bicchieri University of Pennsylvania, [email protected] Alex K. Chavez University of Pennsylvania Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.upenn.edu/belab Part of the Behavioral Economics Commons, Ethics and Political Philosophy Commons, and the Social Psychology Commons Recommended Citation Bicchieri, C., & Chavez, A. K. (2013). Norm Manipulation, Norm Evasion: Experimental Evidence. Economics and Philosophy, 29 (2), 175-198. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/S0266267113000187 This paper is posted at ScholarlyCommons. https://repository.upenn.edu/belab/4 For more information, please contact [email protected]. Norm Manipulation, Norm Evasion: Experimental Evidence Abstract Using an economic bargaining game, we tested for the existence of two phenomena related to social norms, namely norm manipulation – the selection of an interpretation of the norm that best suits an individual – and norm evasion – the deliberate, private violation of a social norm. We found that the manipulation of a norm of fairness was characterized by a self-serving bias in beliefs about what constituted normatively acceptable behaviour, so that an individual who made an uneven bargaining offer not only genuinely believed it was fair, but also believed that recipients found it fair, even though recipients of the offer considered it to be unfair. In contrast, norm evasion operated as a highly explicit process. When they could do so without the recipient's knowledge, individuals made uneven offers despite knowing that their behaviour was unfair. Disciplines Behavioral Economics | Economics | Ethics and Political Philosophy | Social Psychology This journal article is available at ScholarlyCommons: https://repository.upenn.edu/belab/4 1 Norm Manipulation, Norm Evasion: Experimental Evidence Cristina Bicchieri and Alex K.
    [Show full text]
  • Norm-Expressivism and Regress
    South African Journal of Philosophy ISSN: 0258-0136 (Print) 2073-4867 (Online) Journal homepage: http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/rsph20 Norm-expressivism and regress Attila Tanyi To cite this article: Attila Tanyi (2017) Norm-expressivism and regress, South African Journal of Philosophy, 36:3, 362-376, DOI: 10.1080/02580136.2017.1294642 To link to this article: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/02580136.2017.1294642 Published online: 24 Aug 2017. Submit your article to this journal Article views: 3 View related articles View Crossmark data Full Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at http://www.tandfonline.com/action/journalInformation?journalCode=rsph20 Download by: [UiT Norges arktiske universitet] Date: 26 September 2017, At: 07:46 South African Journal of Philosophy 2017, 36(3): 362–376 Copyright © South African Journal of Philosophy Printed in South Africa — All rights reserved SOUTH AFRICAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY ISSN 0258-0136 EISSN 2073-4867 http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/02580136.2017.1294642 Norm-expressivism and regress Attila Tanyi Department of Philosophy, University of Liverpool, UK; and Collegium Helveticum, ETH/University of Zurich, Switzerland [email protected] This paper aims to investigate Allan Gibbard’s norm-expressivist account of normativity. In particular, the aim is to see whether Gibbard’s theory is able to account for the normativity of reason-claims. For this purpose, I first describe how I come to targeting Gibbard’s theory by setting out the main tenets of quasi-realism cum expressivism. After this, I provide a detailed interpretation of the relevant parts of Gibbard’s theory.
    [Show full text]
  • Biology: Syllabus Instructor: Mr. Shannon Contact Information Steve Shannon Room 85 School Phone: (402) 443-4332 Ext
    Biology: Syllabus Instructor: Mr. Shannon Contact Information Steve Shannon Room 85 School Phone: (402) 443-4332 Ext. 3224 Email: [email protected] General Course Description This course begins with a consideration of the living condition and discussion of the unique properties of living organisms that set life apart from the non-living. It continues with molecular and cellular biology, from which it moves logically into reproduction and genetics. An understanding of genetics gives meaning to organized variation, evolution and methods of scientific classification units dealing with microbiology and plant and animal phylum. This course is designed for the college-bound student. Students should expect a demanding daily homework load as well as projects, quizzes, tests, and laboratory write-ups. A high level of understanding in problem solving and the scientific methods is necessary for success in this course. Daily Class Materials Needed *Student Planner *Modern Biology textbook *3 Ring Binder/Folder *Notebook *Pen/Pencil *Calculator Daily Requirements: All students will be required to keep a 3-Ring Binder with all their classroom materials in the binder. This binder will hold the student’s Vocabulary Word List, Notes, Classroom Assignments and Activities, Labs, Quizzes, and Reviews. This notebook will be graded at the end of every chapter. General Routines and Procedures 1. BE ON TIME AND PREPARED FOR LEARNING *Respect for Others (Teachers, Students, and Community) -Ways to Show Respect to Others: 1. Make good eye contact when communicating with others 2. BE ON TIME! Punctuality is vital in today’s world. Virtually any job you may have will require you to be on time and ready to work.
    [Show full text]