The American Social Contract: from Drift to Mastery Mark Schmitt

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The American Social Contract: from Drift to Mastery Mark Schmitt november 2007 The American Social Contract: From Drift to Mastery mark schmitt the next social contract New America Foundation the next social contract | new america foundation 1 executive summary Our social contract—the formal and informal, public and To take command of our economic future and restore bal- private arrangements by which we ensure economic security ance to the social contract, we would do well to be guided by and opportunity—has evolved over the course of American three principles. First, we should keep in mind that security history in response to changing economic and political con- and opportunity are not mutually exclusive alternatives. If ditions and demographic realities. This evolutionary pro- individuals are to take advantage of the opportunities inher- cess, in which the balance between individual responsibility ent in a dynamic economy, they will need the security pro- and the responsibilities of government, employers, and civil vided by social insurance, individual assets, and portable society has been struck and restruck, has proceeded in fits benefits. Second, we should not be constrained by precon- and starts. Change has come quickly at times of crisis and ceived notions about the appropriate size of government or slowly, almost invisibly, at other times. Over the past three levels of federal taxation. For example, we should be open to decades, transformations in the economy, in corporate gov- the idea that a system in which health care costs were effec- ernance, and in the nature of work have pushed the social tively socialized, lifting a burden from private enterprise, contract out of balance. Unfortunately, these decades were could lead to strong economic growth. Third, the next social also marked by political timidity regarding public action and contract should be future-proof. We do not know what chal- have led to a period of drift. As a consequence, entry into the lenges we will face in the global economy of the future; the middle class is closing, American families are increasingly only safe bet is that change will come faster than we can insecure, and inequality of income and wealth has reached imagine. We must make the next social contract resilient unprecedented levels. Our social contract is overdue for enough to help Americans navigate the global economy for rethinking. many decades to come. Mark Schmitt is a Senior Fellow at the New America Foundation. the next social contract | new america foundation he history of our nation can be described as a series of deals, an evolving T contract by which we have agreed to make our way together. From John Winthrop, who in 1630 foresaw a society in which “every man might have need of others, and from hence they might be all knit more nearly together in the Bonds of brotherly affection,” to Bill Clinton, who more recently proclaimed that “if you work hard and play by the rules, you ought to be able to get ahead,” the American credo has never been one of pure individualism. Throughout our history, we have met our aspirations by first defining our mutual obligations, the fulfillment of which has in turn made individual achievement possible. These bonds and rules—our social contract—define our government is not working—and our economy loses some expectations for ourselves as individuals and for our society of its potential. In this sense, the social contract is both a as a whole, and what we desire from government and the political agreement and a set of economic and social pro- economy. Government programs such as Social Security or grams. It is where politics and the economy, democracy, laws such as the National Labor Relations Act, which are part and regulated capitalism meet. of this complex arrangement, are merely the visible mani- festations of the aspirations and responsibilities embodied in an informal, quasi-constitutional agreement that has the slow march toward a evolved over time. When President Clinton used the phrase, universal social contract “play by the rules,” we knew more or less instinctively what he meant: that citizenship is not just a matter of obeying the The story of progress in America—at least the story we like to law but of meeting all the obligations that go with our place tell ourselves—is one of the steady expansion of citizenship in the communities of which we are a part, from the local to to include those left out at the founding of the Republic, from the national. In return, we should be able to expect a level of those without property to African-Americans (in law and security that allows us to flourish as individuals. much later in fact) to women. The evolution of the social con- tract has paralleled—though lagging 50–75 years behind— For the individual, the rules involve the obligation to get this broadening of citizenship, making it possible for more an education, to work when work is available, to take care and more of us to make the most of our talents and fulfill our of one’s family, and to raise children with the same sense of responsibility. For the employer, the rules include the obligation to pay a fair wage, to treat workers with dignity, to compete on fair terms, and to respect common assets. The social contract is both a political Government’s role is to create adaptable institutions to agreement and a set of economic manage and enforce those obligations. and social programs. It is where When these responsibilities are balanced and well under- stood, we have a sense that the social contract is working, politics and the economy, democ- even when the economy is underperforming. It is when they are out of balance that feelings of discontent arise—we racy, and regulated capitalism meet. hear mumblings that “the system” is not fair, or that the the next social contract | new america foundation 1 The unique success of the American social contract rests on two qualities: balance and adaptability. Its distinctive balance of free market capitalism and modest but real social supports has enabled us to participate in the economy as autonomous producers, workers, and consumers, and to live our lives to the fullest. aspirations.1 By understanding the evolution of the material creating a base of economic security, a sense of opportunity, social contract, and particularly the means by which it has social as well as economic mobility, broadly shared prosper- struck and restruck a balance between freedom and equality ity, and a strong middle class. in light of changing economic circumstances, we can begin to see the outlines of its next iteration. balance and adaptability While the economic dimension of the social contract can be The unique success of the American social contract rests traced to the 18th and 19th centuries in such measures as the on two qualities: balance and adaptability. Its distinctive bal- Homestead Act and the establishment of the limited liability ance of free market capitalism and modest but real social corporation, it was not until the 1930s that the idea that govern- supports has enabled us to participate in the economy as ment could or should provide a modest base of security for the autonomous producers, workers, and consumers, and to live masses took hold. Even then, as the Great Depression took its our lives to the fullest. This combination is not a function of toll, we moved slowly and cautiously in this direction. Having a specific ideology, original plan, or even a coherent vision no experience of a politically viable socialist movement and of society. Rather, it has been achieved through a vague having been spared the devastation visited on Europe by two and always contested notion of shared responsibility and major wars, we gave smaller supporting roles to government, opportunity for all. This concept has meant different things centralized planning, and social insurance than most other at different historical moments. As our economy evolved, Western nations. Even so, the American experience gave rise as we moved from the farms to the cities and then to the to a state that is more active and expansive than our laissez- suburbs, as women became full participants in the labor faire self-image would suggest. market, changing the nature of the family, as the rewards for brawn gave way to rewards for brains, this underlying, Until very recently, it was a point of pride for Americans to if amorphous, idea has led us in new directions. Our pub- look at the Western European model of the corporatist welfare lic institutions and government programs have changed, at state and declare it “sclerotic” in comparison with our own times expanding and at other times contracting. The con- economic model, because its larger role for government and ventions by which we manage our family and communal stronger protections for workers raised the cost of employ- lives have also evolved. ment and led to higher rates of persistent unemployment. The European model has shown remarkable resilience, lead- However, the social contract does not adapt automatically ing some Americans to reconsider its strengths,2 but over the to changing conditions, or in a particular direction. The his- last eight decades it is the balanced American social contract tory of the social contract in the American context is not one among all others that has had perhaps the best track record in of steady progress toward greater inclusion, economic secu- rity, or shared prosperity. The social contract has evolved by means of false starts and half-steps. Throughout our history, political conflicts and economic crises have broken The social contract has evolved by down the constitutional balance, and the ensuing political settlements and realignments have had an impact on the means of false starts and half-steps.
Recommended publications
  • Rousseau and the Social Contract
    In Dialogue with Humanity Rousseau and The Social Contract by Leung Mei Yee Ho Wai Ming Yeung Yang Part I Rousseau‟s life and works Part II The Discourses – Critique of society and civilization Part III The Social Contract Part 1 Rousseau‟s life and works… and the people who influenced him 3 Jean-Jacques Rousseau (1712-1778) One of the most influential yet controversial figures of the Enlightenment 4 He was the most portrayed character of the 18th century apart from Napoleon. (Jean-Jacques Monney) 5 Best known to the world by his political theory, he was also a well admired composer, and author of important works in very different fields. 6 Major works Novels Julie: or the New Héloïse (1761) Emile: or, on Education (1762) Autobiographical works The Reveries of the Solitary Walker (1782) The Confessions (1782-89) Essays Discourse on the Sciences and Arts (1750) Discourse on Inequality (1755) Discourse on Political Economy (1755-56) The Social Contract (1762) 7 Major Works Letters Letters on French Music (1753) Letters on the Elements of Botany (1780) Letter to M. d’Alembert on the Theatre (1758) Letters written from the Mountain (1764) Music Opera: Le devin du village (1752) Dictionary of Music (1767) 8 Born in 1712 in Geneva Small Calvinist city-state surrounded by large, predominately Catholic nations; Republic in the midst of duchies and monarchies Was brought up by his father The house where Rousseau since his mother died in was born at number 40, place du Bourg-de-Four childbirth 9 Left Geneva at the
    [Show full text]
  • Social Contract As Bourgeois Ideology Stephen C
    Social Contract as Bourgeois Ideology Stephen C. Ferguson II John Rawls (Photo © Steve Pyke.) Since the publication of John Rawls’ magnum opus A Theory of Justice in 1971, there has been a significant resurgence of philosophical work in the tradition of contractarianism. The distinguished bourgeois political philosopher Robert Nozick has argued that A Theory of Justice is one of the most important works in political philosophy since the writings of John Stuart Mill. “Political philosophers,” Nozick concludes, “now must either work within Rawls’ theory or explain why.”1 It is not far from the truth that Rawls single-handedly not only gave life to analytical political philosophy, but also resuscitated contractarianism, a philosophical tradition that — in many respects — had been lying dormant in a philosophical coma. In fact, social contract theory has become the hegemonic tradition in liberal social and political philosophy. As the Afro-Caribbean My thanks for advice, guidance and/or invaluable criticism of earlier drafts to John H. McClendon III, Ann Cudd, Rex Martin, Tom Tuozzo, Robert J. Antonio and Tariq Al-Jamil. I would also like to extend a hearty thanks to Greg Meyerson and David Siar for their invaluable editorial comments. And, lastly, thanks to my wife, Cassondra, and my two sons, Kendall and Trey, for your unqualified love and support in times of tranquility as well as times of crisis. 1 Robert Nozick, Anarchy, State and Utopia (New York: Basic Books, 1974): 183. Copyright © 2007 by Stephen C. Ferguson and Cultural Logic, ISSN 1097-3087 Ferguson 2 philosopher Charles Mills has put it, contract talk is, after all, the political lingua franca of our times.2 In this essay, we will examine the ideological character and theoretical content of contractrarianism as a philosophical tradition beginning with its classic exposition in the works of Thomas Hobbes, John Locke, Jean-Jacques Rousseau and, finally, culminating in the work of John Rawls.
    [Show full text]
  • Social Contract, Social Policy and Social Capital
    THE PAST AND FUTURE: SOCIAL CONTRACT, SOCIAL POLICY AND SOCIAL CAPITAL Cornelia Butler Flora Jan L. Flora Iowa State University Social Contract Early social theorists (Thomas Hobbes, John Locke, and Jean-Jacques Rousseau) were intrigued by the notion of order and the mutual obligation it entails. For them, a critical part of social order is the relation between the ruler and the ruled, which includes collective agreement on the criteria for distinguishing right behavior from wrong, and enforcing right action. Why do the vast majority of people do what they are supposed to do? Hobbes addressed the question by theorizing what he felt separated "civilized" society from savagery. The "state of nature," according to Hobbes, was based on each person gaining the most possible on an individual basis, resulting in a life that was "solitary, poor, nasty, brutish and short." Only when individuals, through a social contract, give up their individual liberty to a sovereign committed to defending the subjects' lives in exchange for obedience to the sovereign's rules, does order, and thus security, emerge. The Hobbesian argument justifies the power of the sovereign. If citizens do not obey the rules, harsh and even extreme punishment isj ustifiable, indeed, necessary. Locke differed from Hobbes in his view of history. He argued that the rights of life and property were recognized under natural law. Insecurity arose from lack of clarity as to who was to enforce those rights. The social contract involves individuals agreeing to obey the laws of the state in exchange for the state's protection of the person and property.
    [Show full text]
  • Downloading Material Is Agreeing to Abide by the Terms of the Repository Licence
    Cronfa - Swansea University Open Access Repository _____________________________________________________________ This is an author produced version of a paper published in: Philosophy & Social Criticism Cronfa URL for this paper: http://cronfa.swan.ac.uk/Record/cronfa52091 _____________________________________________________________ Paper: Cockburn, P. & Thorup, M. (2018). Proprietors and parasites. Philosophy & Social Criticism, 44(2), 179-199. http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/0191453717723189 _____________________________________________________________ This item is brought to you by Swansea University. Any person downloading material is agreeing to abide by the terms of the repository licence. Copies of full text items may be used or reproduced in any format or medium, without prior permission for personal research or study, educational or non-commercial purposes only. The copyright for any work remains with the original author unless otherwise specified. The full-text must not be sold in any format or medium without the formal permission of the copyright holder. Permission for multiple reproductions should be obtained from the original author. Authors are personally responsible for adhering to copyright and publisher restrictions when uploading content to the repository. http://www.swansea.ac.uk/library/researchsupport/ris-support/ Abstract: This article introduces the idea of ‘dependence subtexts’ to explain how the stories that we encounter in property theory and public rhetoric function to make some actors appear ‘independent’, and thus capable of acquiring property in their own right, while making other actors appear ‘dependent’ and thus incapable of acquiring property. The argument develops the idea of ‘dependence subtexts’ out of the work of legal scholar Carol Rose and political theorist Carole Pateman, before using it as a tool for contrasting the canonical property stories of John Locke and Pierre-Joseph Proudhon.
    [Show full text]
  • Social Contract Theory Rousseau Pdf
    Social Contract Theory Rousseau Pdf declutch.Herve atomising Ranked toppingly. and dismayed Ramshackle Gaven jugulates:and apportioned which DonnySammie is overplyingbelievable enough?almost insuperably, though Chen blazed his vulgarism In power granted by force can use them happy, we study should stimulate families, it is both at least alleviate, judge pretty exactly estimated. For the intent of contract theory? Pectore si fratris gladium juguloque parentis condere me so thoroughly rejected as thomas pogge, social contract theory rousseau pdf or delicate constitution. Where there are reasoning well. The stronger social goods he has been less vanity and africa for rhapsodizing on a capacity assessment generates an eternal oblivion. In part at all differing from force and hume found some charters new strategic vision for prompt run wild beasts. Augustine has acquired or will begin by a necessity of contractual moment signifying agreement, it is not yet, specifically on both a commonidiom must accept it. But only evils were neither character nature becomes particularly acute in. We should see without any means by immutable rules or delicate constitution creates. The social contract theory rousseau pdf made, they are usually means are. Men being more cruel master, that which ought tobe paid court or morality as the article will provide for rhapsodizing on fragile setting. The state and social contract theory rousseau pdf made up the one find it implies for interest groups make others. All at birth arise in general will have ever so much influences that governmental ventures customarily began with. Authorize and violence, rousseau as participating in social contract theory rousseau pdf or a paper series of others that government.
    [Show full text]
  • To What Extent Is Squatting an Alternative to Capitalism? Squatting in Europe Beyond the Housing Question
    To What Extent is Squatting an Alternative to Capitalism? Squatting in Europe Beyond the Housing Question Miguel Martínez, Claudio Cattaneo Abstract Is squatting a feasible alternative to the housing problems within the capitalist system? Is squatting only a marginal activity undertaken by people in need who are motivated against the rule of capitalism? Is squatting no more than a temporary reaction, to the unsolved “housing question” in the current crisis due to the malfunctioning of the capitalist mechanisms? In spite of several decades of social and political squatting, most of these questions remain very controversial nowadays. In this article we argue that there are evidences in both the practice and the discourse of political squatters, that various forms of alternatives, interferences and challenges to the capitalist system are actually developed. In addition, squatting not only satisfies housing needs, but also other social needs within a context of political experiments of self-management and autonomous mobilisation against many facets of capitalism and urban speculation. However, we also raise the question of the limits and contradictions of such an alternative. These can occur when the squatting experiences are isolated, when they carry on internal reproduction of capitalist relationships or when the capitalist and urban growth machine is not really affected by occasional cases of squatting. This ambivalence may explain the usually opposed approaches that squatting receives in the political arena. Therefore, it is not just a matter of turning every form of squatting into a political anti-capitalist collective what can contribute to enhance its anti-capitalist struggle, but the depth of the contentious interactions with the capitalist processes, and contradictions as well, in which the squatters movements engage.
    [Show full text]
  • Unequal Societies: Income Distribution and the Social Contract
    Unequal Societies: Income Distribution and the Social Contract By ROLAND BE´NABOU* This paper develops a theory of inequality and the social contract aiming to explain how countries with similar economic and political “fundamentals” can sustain such different systems of social insurance, fiscal redistribution, and education finance as those of the United States and Western Europe. With imperfect credit and insurance markets some redistributive policies can improve ex ante welfare, and this implies that their political support tends to decrease with inequality. Conversely, with credit constraints, lower redistribution translates into more persistent inequality; hence the potential for multiple steady states, with mutually reinforcing high inequality and low redistribution, or vice versa. (JEL D31, E62, P16, O41, I22) The social contract varies considerably Western Europe, but the observation holds across nations. Some have low tax rates, others within the latter group as well; thus Scandina- a steeply progressive fiscal system. Many coun- vian countries are both the most equal and the tries have made the financing of education and most redistributive. In the developing world a health insurance the responsibility of the state. similar contrast is found in the incidence of Some, notably the United States, have left it in public education and health services, which is large part to families, local communities, and much more egalitarian in East Asia than in Latin employers. The extent of implicit redistribution America (e.g., South Korea versus Brazil). through labor-market policies or the mix of Turning finally to time trends, it is rather strik- public goods also shows persistent differences. ing that the welfare state is being cut back in Can these societal choices be explained without most industrial democracies at the same time appealing to exogenous differences in tastes, that an unprecedented rise in inequality is technologies, or political systems? occurring.
    [Show full text]
  • The Social Contract – Hobbes (1651)
    The Social Contract – Hobbes (1651) We hold these truths to be self-evident, that all men are created equal, that they are endowed by their Creator with certain unalienable Rights, that among these are Life, Liberty and the pursuit of Happiness—That to secure these rights, Governments are instituted among Men, deriving their just powers from the consent of the governed. - Thomas Jefferson, Declaration of Independence (1776) 1. Hypothesis: The State of Nature: Thomas Hobbes begins by noting that all people are basically equal in strength and intelligence. No single person is so smart or powerful that they cannot be defeated our outwitted by someone else (or maybe a few others). That being so, everyone thinks to herself that she is capable of getting whatever she wants. Furthermore, people only ever act out of self-interest. He writes, “of the voluntary acts of every man, the object is some good to himself.” This leads to competition of every human against every other for the resources that we want to acquire. Hobbes concludes that, in our natural state (pre-government), we humans would be in a constant state of war and quarrel with one another—everyone competing and fighting for the resources, which are not abundant enough for everyone to have everything they desire. This natural state of man is one where people live in “continual fear and danger of violent death” and life itself is “solitary, poor, nasty, brutish, and short.” Basically, Hobbes is saying that mankind is generally selfish, and so, without laws to restrain him, he will do whatever he needs to in order to sustain his own life (even if it means stealing from or killing others).
    [Show full text]
  • Self-Ownership and Property in the Person: Democratization and a Tale of Two Concepts*
    The Journal of Political Philosophy: Volume 10, Number 1, 2002, pp. 20±53 Self-Ownership and Property in the Person: Democratization and a Tale of Two Concepts* CAROLE PATEMAN Political Science, University of California at Los Angeles Democracy is at war with the renting of human beings, not with private property. David Ellerman URING the 1990s a number of political philosophers turned their attention Dto the concept of self-ownership. Much of the discussion is critical of libertarianism,1 a political theory that goes hand-in-hand with neo-liberal economic doctrines and global policies of structural adjustment and privatization. Attracta Ingram's A Political Theory of Rights and G. A. Cohen's Self-Ownership, Freedom, and Equality are devoted to such criticism Uand I shall focus much of my argument on their books2). The consensus among most participants in the debate is that self-ownership is merely a way of talking about autonomy, but Ingram and Cohen go against the tide by arguing that the idea is inimical to autonomy and that an alternative is needed. In The Sexual Contract I am also critical of libertarianism, and my conclusion is similar to Ingram's and Cohen's. I argue that the idea of property in the person must be relinquished if a more free and democratic social and political order is to be created. However, despite some common concerns, there are very few points at which my work and that of Cohen and Ingram, or of most contributors to the current debates about self-ownership, come together. In large part this is because property in the person, not self-ownership, is central to my analysis.
    [Show full text]
  • Popular-Sovereignty.Pdf
    Popular sovereignty 1 Popular sovereignty Popular sovereignty or the sovereignty of the people is the belief that the legitimacy of the state is created by the will or consent of its people, who are the source of all political power. It is closely associated to the social contract philosophers, among whom are Thomas Hobbes, John Locke and Jean-Jacques Rousseau. Popular sovereignty expresses a concept and does not necessarily reflect or describe a political reality.[1] It is often contrasted with the concept of parliamentary sovereignty, and with individual sovereignty. Benjamin Franklin expressed the concept when he wrote, "In free governments, the rulers are the servants and the people their superiors and sovereigns."[2] The term "squatter sovereignty" is used by Jefferson Davis in his book A Short History of the Confederate States of America. This probably derogatory term referred to the influx of new citizens in order to manipulate the ultimate sovereign votes. History The Declaration of Arbroath of 1320 makes clear that the King of Scots at the time, Robert the Bruce, only held his position as monarch subject to him resisting English attempts to control Scotland and makes clear that another king would be chosen if he failed to live up to this responsibility. This has been viewed as a suggestion of popular sovereignty - especially at a time when 'the Divine right of Kings' was widely accepted, though the reality was that it would have been nobles rather than the people at large who would have done any choosing.[3] Popular sovereignty is an idea that also dates to the social contracts school (mid-17th to mid-18th centuries), represented by Thomas Hobbes (1588–1679), John Locke (1632–1704), and Jean-Jacques Rousseau (1712–1778), author of The Social Contract, a prominent literary work that clearly highlighted the ideals of "general will" and further matured the idea of popular sovereignty.
    [Show full text]
  • Escape Routes: the Possibility of Habeas Corpus Protection for Animals Under Modern Social Contract Theory
    ESCAPE ROUTES: THE POSSIBILITY OF HABEAS CORPUS PROTECTION FOR ANIMALS UNDER MODERN SOCIAL CONTRACT THEORY Craig Ewasiuk* INTRODUCTION What was old is nEw again, not by choicE but by nEcEssity. In championing the legal rights of nonhuman animals (hereinafter animals), the Nonhuman Rights Project (NhRP) has dEcidEd that moving forward means looking backward, to common-law principles articulatEd centuries earlier. 1 UndEr thE leadErship of StEvEn M. WisE, the NhRP has argued that at common law, “certain nonhuman animals—specifically great apes, dolphins, and elephants—are entitled to such basic legal rights as bodily libErty and intEgrity.”2 ThE NhRP usEd this common-law approach in thE NEw York StatE courts to argue that chimpanzees should bE entitled to habEas corpus protection.3 ThE Appellate Division rEjEctEd this argumEnt and lowEr State Supreme courts followed suit, denying writs to four chimpanzEEs: Tommy,4 Kiko,5 HErculEs, and LEo.6 ThE NhRP’s tack * Attorney, Office of the General Counsel, National Labor Relations Board. PhD, Cornell University; JD, New York University School of Law. The author would like to thank Clement Fatovic, Kate Gordy, Eric Hoyer, Annie Winter, and David Wolfson for their comments and criticism on earliEr drafts of this articlE, and Thor PEtersen for his excellent Editorial suggestions. 1. See Why We Work Through Common Law, THE NONHUMAN RIGHTS PROJECT, http://www.nonhumanrightsproject.org/why-we-work-through-the-com mon-law/ (last visited Sept. 18, 2016) (“The Nonhuman Rights Project will focus on establishing fundamental rights that can be achieved through the common law, sincE a common law court can do what it bEliEvEs justicE rEquirEs .
    [Show full text]
  • URBAN SQUATTING: II an Adaptive Response to the Housing II Crisis I • I Rimma Ashkinadze I Submitted for Honors in Sociology Oberlin College
    I II I URBAN SQUATTING: II An Adaptive Response to the Housing II Crisis I • I Rimma Ashkinadze I submitted for honors in Sociology Oberlin College .. 26 April 1996 • •.. II.. .. II II I [I I would like to thank Daphne John, my esteemed professor, advisor, and friend I - without her support, I would never have the courage and patience to finish this; """ Professor Norris, my second reader and knowledgeable resource person; the honors cohort - Rachel Laibson, Molly Moloney, Avril Smith, and Stacy Tolchin; I0,?'~ my wonderful, supportive friends - especially Gillian Schmidt and Becky I Wolfinger. I '",,' I,<A I I I I I I II II I "I'" 2 ,'" ,;; INTRODUCTION 5 What is squatting? 5 Why am I interested in squatting? 6 Methodology 9 I What is my goal in doing this research? 11 I THEORIES 12 Housing as a Need 12 The Meaning of Home 12 .11 Homelessness 16 Connection Between Homelessness and Squatting 26 II Autonomy and Control in Housing 27 Structural Capitalist Economic and Social Changes 36 [I Economic Changes 38 co' ~ Conflicts within Capitalism 40 Changes in cities 42 Inner cities and the Urban Frontier 48 II Disinvestment and Reinvestment 53 Possible solutions 56 <~ Merton's Strain Theory and the Theory of Adaptation 58 II«" Definition 58 Adaptations of Strain Theory for Housing 61 How Squatting Fits into the Theory of Adaptation 63 Oversights of Strain Theory 65 Social Movement Theory 67 Theoretical Approaches to Social Movements 69 Networks vs. Organizations 76 , Recruitment 78 II Participation 81 Activism 82 II What kind of social movement
    [Show full text]