Social Contract, Social Policy and Social Capital

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Social Contract, Social Policy and Social Capital THE PAST AND FUTURE: SOCIAL CONTRACT, SOCIAL POLICY AND SOCIAL CAPITAL Cornelia Butler Flora Jan L. Flora Iowa State University Social Contract Early social theorists (Thomas Hobbes, John Locke, and Jean-Jacques Rousseau) were intrigued by the notion of order and the mutual obligation it entails. For them, a critical part of social order is the relation between the ruler and the ruled, which includes collective agreement on the criteria for distinguishing right behavior from wrong, and enforcing right action. Why do the vast majority of people do what they are supposed to do? Hobbes addressed the question by theorizing what he felt separated "civilized" society from savagery. The "state of nature," according to Hobbes, was based on each person gaining the most possible on an individual basis, resulting in a life that was "solitary, poor, nasty, brutish and short." Only when individuals, through a social contract, give up their individual liberty to a sovereign committed to defending the subjects' lives in exchange for obedience to the sovereign's rules, does order, and thus security, emerge. The Hobbesian argument justifies the power of the sovereign. If citizens do not obey the rules, harsh and even extreme punishment isj ustifiable, indeed, necessary. Locke differed from Hobbes in his view of history. He argued that the rights of life and property were recognized under natural law. Insecurity arose from lack of clarity as to who was to enforce those rights. The social contract involves individuals agreeing to obey the laws of the state in exchange for the state's protection of the person and property. Locke reasoned that, when the sovereign did not provide the appropriate protec- tion, overthrow of that sovereign was justifiable. Rousseau saw history as a movement toward increasing the power of reasoning, and the sense of morality and responsibility. When individuals agree, for the sake of mutual protection, to surrender individual freedom of action and establish laws of government, they acquire a sense of moral and civic obligation. This implied a constant negotiation between the state and its citizens to maintain legitimacy, and thus, social order. When government violates the social contract and loses its legitimacy, revolution is justified. Rousseau provided the intellectual basis for the French and American Revolutions. We are currently in a situation of renegotiation-not revolu- tion-of the social contract. The thrust of the Contract with America is a 53 shift from an emphasis on the rights of life to the rights of property. For that contract to replace the previous understanding of the relation of the state to its citizens, access to property, and the security it entails, will have to be as important as ensuring that those who now have property keep it. The balance of what government should provide for citizens-and citizen obligations to the state-are now in negotiation. Contracts are ultimately based on trust that the parties to the contract will live up to their obligations. What is needed for such trust to develop? One prerequisite is a degree of social and economic equality. The nineteenth century German social and economic theorist, Max Weber, argued that the "unfettered" market contributes to inequality; thus wealth and power accumulate rapidly into the hands of a few. An important role for public policy is to compensate for the "market failure" which is the result of structural inequality, despite a strong counter tendency for policy to codify and make even more severe existing inequalities. When the state fails to ensure a level playing field, civic culture does not flourish. Absent the state's guarantee of equity (enshrined in the U.S. Consti- tution as equality of opportunity, not necessarily of outcome), civic culture is beset by social distinctions which reduce the level of trust, and substantially increase the transaction costs of conducting daily community life. Important key questions for policy are: 1. How to make it profitable to do what is moral (rational self-interest reinforced by public policy), and 2. How to nurture a civic culture. A strong civic culture is a prerequisite for a common moral order (Putnam, 1993b). Our analysis of policy is based on the notion of a common moral order and the norms of mutual trust and reciprocity which underlie it. Using the terminology of other scholars, we call that "social capital." While Coleman and others use that term to refer to resources wielded by individuals, a concept based on rational choice and game theory, others (Portes and Sensenbrenner; Granovetter) approach social capital, or embeddedness, in terms of the formation of collective conscience, which provides a social, rather than individual, basis for action. Public policy has, in general, ignored social capital, choosing instead to try to enhance other resources: financial/manufactured resources, human resources, and, more recently, environmental resources. (See C. Flora for a discussion of the different kinds of capital that emerge from these resources). As a result, the unintended consequence of many policies is to decrease social capital and undermine the social structure (not individual motivation) that contributes to civicness and the common moral order. 54 Attempts, such as efforts by the religious right to impose a common moral order, which ignore the importance of social embeddedness as a structural prerequisite, further diminish social capital, and are thus counterproduc- tive. The level of all resources available to a society declines. Putnam (1995) uses longitudinal survey data to document the decline in civic engagement and levels of trust of individuals in the United States, which he summarizes in his title, Bowling Alone. He traces the decline of bowling leagues (and the accompanying decline in sales of food and drink at bowling alleys), and the increase in number of lines bowled, to the individualization of leisure and the separation of the individual from community. This concern is not with leisure but with democracy. Based on Roper polls, participation in town and school meetings, writing Congress, attending rallies or speeches, being a member of any civic committee, or doing volunteer political party work declined between 29 percent and 56 percent between 1973 and 1993. Weekly church attendance has declined between 1950 and 1991, although there are significant year to year fluctuations. Volunteerism, measured through involvement or membership in selected civic organizations, such as the Elks, Federated Women's Clubs, Lions and League of Women Voters, is decreasing. Volunteers in Scouting and the Red Cross are also down. Membership first declined in women's organizations as economic shifts and global restructuring basically required two incomes in households during the inflationary times of the 1970s. Participation in men's organizations followed suit in the 1980s, when for many families, particularly in the working class, even two incomes in a household were no longer adequate. Parent-Teacher Association membership is down from 1960 to 1992, even controlling for number of school age children. Spending social evenings with neighbors more than once a year (not a stringent indicator of neighborliness) declined about 12 percent between 1974 and 1995. Decreased participation in formal organizations is not replaced with informal interactions. Finally, social trust has declined precipitously. Distrust of government peaked at Watergate, and, by 1992, had returned to the Watergate level. Fifty- eight percent of the U.S. public agreed with, "Most people can be trusted," as opposed to, "You can't be too careful in dealing with people" in 1960, compared to 41 percent in 1975 and 37 percent in 1993. If social capital depends on mutual trust, certainly on an individual level, it is declining. This paper attempts to show the need for policy to take into account the balance among the various resources in society, particularly at the commu- 55 nity level. We argue that, in the past, policies which have sought to privilege a single resource and to maximize it, have reduced social capital-and thus the long term sustainability of the social system. By reducing social capital, often in the name of short-term problem solution which maximizes the return to a single resource, the social basis of the relation between citizen and state deteriorates, and extreme reactions-from the bombing of build- ings to the Posse Comitatis-emerge. There is a tendency to judge community progress in terms of the increase in financial and manufactured capital, in part because it is easy to measure. Financial and manufactured capital is either already monetized or easily expressible in monetary terms. Only if policy makers and citizens articulate additional goals for policy can alternative policies be developed. An unarticulated goal is that of enhancing social capital, trust and reciprocity. By articulating it, we make it legitimate to measure it, and, as is pointed out in Reinventing Government, what we measure is what we do. And as devolution is put into place, it is critical that we measure multiple goals at the community level. There are communities of interest and communities of place. A commu- nity of interest is composed of people who interact with each other, but who may not be together in the same place except for short periods of time. The National Public Policy Education Committee is a community of interest. Many members of that group are particularly concerned about the second type of community, community of place. The community of place is composed of people who live in and interact with one another within a geographic area. This geographic area may be urban or rural. Communities of interest can be very powerful. They are becoming more powerful as communities of place become more unstable. Communities of interest are able to mobilize a particular kind of capital that is a sub-category of social capital: political capital.
Recommended publications
  • Rousseau and the Social Contract
    In Dialogue with Humanity Rousseau and The Social Contract by Leung Mei Yee Ho Wai Ming Yeung Yang Part I Rousseau‟s life and works Part II The Discourses – Critique of society and civilization Part III The Social Contract Part 1 Rousseau‟s life and works… and the people who influenced him 3 Jean-Jacques Rousseau (1712-1778) One of the most influential yet controversial figures of the Enlightenment 4 He was the most portrayed character of the 18th century apart from Napoleon. (Jean-Jacques Monney) 5 Best known to the world by his political theory, he was also a well admired composer, and author of important works in very different fields. 6 Major works Novels Julie: or the New Héloïse (1761) Emile: or, on Education (1762) Autobiographical works The Reveries of the Solitary Walker (1782) The Confessions (1782-89) Essays Discourse on the Sciences and Arts (1750) Discourse on Inequality (1755) Discourse on Political Economy (1755-56) The Social Contract (1762) 7 Major Works Letters Letters on French Music (1753) Letters on the Elements of Botany (1780) Letter to M. d’Alembert on the Theatre (1758) Letters written from the Mountain (1764) Music Opera: Le devin du village (1752) Dictionary of Music (1767) 8 Born in 1712 in Geneva Small Calvinist city-state surrounded by large, predominately Catholic nations; Republic in the midst of duchies and monarchies Was brought up by his father The house where Rousseau since his mother died in was born at number 40, place du Bourg-de-Four childbirth 9 Left Geneva at the
    [Show full text]
  • Social Contract As Bourgeois Ideology Stephen C
    Social Contract as Bourgeois Ideology Stephen C. Ferguson II John Rawls (Photo © Steve Pyke.) Since the publication of John Rawls’ magnum opus A Theory of Justice in 1971, there has been a significant resurgence of philosophical work in the tradition of contractarianism. The distinguished bourgeois political philosopher Robert Nozick has argued that A Theory of Justice is one of the most important works in political philosophy since the writings of John Stuart Mill. “Political philosophers,” Nozick concludes, “now must either work within Rawls’ theory or explain why.”1 It is not far from the truth that Rawls single-handedly not only gave life to analytical political philosophy, but also resuscitated contractarianism, a philosophical tradition that — in many respects — had been lying dormant in a philosophical coma. In fact, social contract theory has become the hegemonic tradition in liberal social and political philosophy. As the Afro-Caribbean My thanks for advice, guidance and/or invaluable criticism of earlier drafts to John H. McClendon III, Ann Cudd, Rex Martin, Tom Tuozzo, Robert J. Antonio and Tariq Al-Jamil. I would also like to extend a hearty thanks to Greg Meyerson and David Siar for their invaluable editorial comments. And, lastly, thanks to my wife, Cassondra, and my two sons, Kendall and Trey, for your unqualified love and support in times of tranquility as well as times of crisis. 1 Robert Nozick, Anarchy, State and Utopia (New York: Basic Books, 1974): 183. Copyright © 2007 by Stephen C. Ferguson and Cultural Logic, ISSN 1097-3087 Ferguson 2 philosopher Charles Mills has put it, contract talk is, after all, the political lingua franca of our times.2 In this essay, we will examine the ideological character and theoretical content of contractrarianism as a philosophical tradition beginning with its classic exposition in the works of Thomas Hobbes, John Locke, Jean-Jacques Rousseau and, finally, culminating in the work of John Rawls.
    [Show full text]
  • Downloading Material Is Agreeing to Abide by the Terms of the Repository Licence
    Cronfa - Swansea University Open Access Repository _____________________________________________________________ This is an author produced version of a paper published in: Philosophy & Social Criticism Cronfa URL for this paper: http://cronfa.swan.ac.uk/Record/cronfa52091 _____________________________________________________________ Paper: Cockburn, P. & Thorup, M. (2018). Proprietors and parasites. Philosophy & Social Criticism, 44(2), 179-199. http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/0191453717723189 _____________________________________________________________ This item is brought to you by Swansea University. Any person downloading material is agreeing to abide by the terms of the repository licence. Copies of full text items may be used or reproduced in any format or medium, without prior permission for personal research or study, educational or non-commercial purposes only. The copyright for any work remains with the original author unless otherwise specified. The full-text must not be sold in any format or medium without the formal permission of the copyright holder. Permission for multiple reproductions should be obtained from the original author. Authors are personally responsible for adhering to copyright and publisher restrictions when uploading content to the repository. http://www.swansea.ac.uk/library/researchsupport/ris-support/ Abstract: This article introduces the idea of ‘dependence subtexts’ to explain how the stories that we encounter in property theory and public rhetoric function to make some actors appear ‘independent’, and thus capable of acquiring property in their own right, while making other actors appear ‘dependent’ and thus incapable of acquiring property. The argument develops the idea of ‘dependence subtexts’ out of the work of legal scholar Carol Rose and political theorist Carole Pateman, before using it as a tool for contrasting the canonical property stories of John Locke and Pierre-Joseph Proudhon.
    [Show full text]
  • Social Capital in First Nations Communities / 125 6 Social Capital in First Nations Communities: Concept and Measurement
    Social Capital in First Nations Communities / 125 6 Social Capital in First Nations Communities: Concept and Measurement Javier Mignone, Janet Longclaws, John O’Neil and Cameron Mustard Introduction Social epidemiology is motivated by the question “Why is this society unhealthy?” versus the traditional epidemiological question “Why did this individual get sick?”1 These are two kinds of etiological questions. The latter question seeks the causes of cases, whereas the former seeks the causes of prevalence and incidence, and thus requires the study of population features—not so much the characteristics of individuals.2 Compositional explanations for variations in health between different communities assume that these areas include different types of individuals, and differences between these individuals would account for the observed difference between places. On the other hand, a contextual explanation would consider that there are features of the social or physical environment that influence the health of those exposed to it (either in addition to or in interaction with individual characteristics). This derives in the key distinction between individual level determinants and ecological level determinants of health. The critical view held by the Royal Commission on Aboriginal Peoples (RCAP) on the individualistic analysis of socioeconomic determinants of health is aligned with this contextual explanation (Royal Commission on Aboriginal Peoples 1996a). It was with this perspective that the Health Information and Research Committee (HIR) of the Assembly of Manitoba Chiefs (AMC), together with the Centre for Aboriginal Health Research (CAHR) at the University of Manitoba, outlined a strategic program of research entitled “Why Are Some First Nations Communities Healthy and Others Are Not? Constituting Evidence in First Nations Health Policy” (O’Neil et al.
    [Show full text]
  • Social Contract Theory Rousseau Pdf
    Social Contract Theory Rousseau Pdf declutch.Herve atomising Ranked toppingly. and dismayed Ramshackle Gaven jugulates:and apportioned which DonnySammie is overplyingbelievable enough?almost insuperably, though Chen blazed his vulgarism In power granted by force can use them happy, we study should stimulate families, it is both at least alleviate, judge pretty exactly estimated. For the intent of contract theory? Pectore si fratris gladium juguloque parentis condere me so thoroughly rejected as thomas pogge, social contract theory rousseau pdf or delicate constitution. Where there are reasoning well. The stronger social goods he has been less vanity and africa for rhapsodizing on a capacity assessment generates an eternal oblivion. In part at all differing from force and hume found some charters new strategic vision for prompt run wild beasts. Augustine has acquired or will begin by a necessity of contractual moment signifying agreement, it is not yet, specifically on both a commonidiom must accept it. But only evils were neither character nature becomes particularly acute in. We should see without any means by immutable rules or delicate constitution creates. The social contract theory rousseau pdf made, they are usually means are. Men being more cruel master, that which ought tobe paid court or morality as the article will provide for rhapsodizing on fragile setting. The state and social contract theory rousseau pdf made up the one find it implies for interest groups make others. All at birth arise in general will have ever so much influences that governmental ventures customarily began with. Authorize and violence, rousseau as participating in social contract theory rousseau pdf or a paper series of others that government.
    [Show full text]
  • To What Extent Is Squatting an Alternative to Capitalism? Squatting in Europe Beyond the Housing Question
    To What Extent is Squatting an Alternative to Capitalism? Squatting in Europe Beyond the Housing Question Miguel Martínez, Claudio Cattaneo Abstract Is squatting a feasible alternative to the housing problems within the capitalist system? Is squatting only a marginal activity undertaken by people in need who are motivated against the rule of capitalism? Is squatting no more than a temporary reaction, to the unsolved “housing question” in the current crisis due to the malfunctioning of the capitalist mechanisms? In spite of several decades of social and political squatting, most of these questions remain very controversial nowadays. In this article we argue that there are evidences in both the practice and the discourse of political squatters, that various forms of alternatives, interferences and challenges to the capitalist system are actually developed. In addition, squatting not only satisfies housing needs, but also other social needs within a context of political experiments of self-management and autonomous mobilisation against many facets of capitalism and urban speculation. However, we also raise the question of the limits and contradictions of such an alternative. These can occur when the squatting experiences are isolated, when they carry on internal reproduction of capitalist relationships or when the capitalist and urban growth machine is not really affected by occasional cases of squatting. This ambivalence may explain the usually opposed approaches that squatting receives in the political arena. Therefore, it is not just a matter of turning every form of squatting into a political anti-capitalist collective what can contribute to enhance its anti-capitalist struggle, but the depth of the contentious interactions with the capitalist processes, and contradictions as well, in which the squatters movements engage.
    [Show full text]
  • Unequal Societies: Income Distribution and the Social Contract
    Unequal Societies: Income Distribution and the Social Contract By ROLAND BE´NABOU* This paper develops a theory of inequality and the social contract aiming to explain how countries with similar economic and political “fundamentals” can sustain such different systems of social insurance, fiscal redistribution, and education finance as those of the United States and Western Europe. With imperfect credit and insurance markets some redistributive policies can improve ex ante welfare, and this implies that their political support tends to decrease with inequality. Conversely, with credit constraints, lower redistribution translates into more persistent inequality; hence the potential for multiple steady states, with mutually reinforcing high inequality and low redistribution, or vice versa. (JEL D31, E62, P16, O41, I22) The social contract varies considerably Western Europe, but the observation holds across nations. Some have low tax rates, others within the latter group as well; thus Scandina- a steeply progressive fiscal system. Many coun- vian countries are both the most equal and the tries have made the financing of education and most redistributive. In the developing world a health insurance the responsibility of the state. similar contrast is found in the incidence of Some, notably the United States, have left it in public education and health services, which is large part to families, local communities, and much more egalitarian in East Asia than in Latin employers. The extent of implicit redistribution America (e.g., South Korea versus Brazil). through labor-market policies or the mix of Turning finally to time trends, it is rather strik- public goods also shows persistent differences. ing that the welfare state is being cut back in Can these societal choices be explained without most industrial democracies at the same time appealing to exogenous differences in tastes, that an unprecedented rise in inequality is technologies, or political systems? occurring.
    [Show full text]
  • Developing Communities
    Developing 1 Communities Jerry W. Robinson, Jr., and Gary Paul Green BEHAVIOR OBJECTIVES After studying this chapter and completing the online learning activities, students should be able to 1. Understand the criticism of the concept of “community.” 2. Define community of place. 3. Differentiate between community development and economic development. 4. Describe the social forces that led to the rise of the community development field. 5. Differentiate between development “of” community and development “in” community. 6. Identify issues that influence the interests of residents in specific localities. 7. Understand the role of participation in the community development process. 8. Distinguish between community service-learning and volunteering/community service. ________________________________________ Introduction Much has been written in recent years about the loss of community and the implications for civil society (Putnam, 2000). Globalization has restructured economic, political, and social relationships at the local level. Technological and social changes have opened new paths for sharing collective interests, such as social networking sites on the Internet and mass media that link individuals to a common culture. Corporations and financial institutions shift capital around the globe to seek out more profitable locations for doing business. Workers increasingly move to places where they can find better job opportu - nities. All of these factors undermine the sense of community in places. 1 2 INTRODUCTION TO COMMUNITY DEVELOPMENT Although our social relationships and interests are no longer limited to local communities, the power of place remains. Local issues, such as education, housing, health, and jobs, are critical concerns for most residents. There continues to be interest in mobilizing local residents to build assets that improve their quality of life (Green & Haines, 2007; Kretzmann & McKnight, 1993).
    [Show full text]
  • The Social Contract – Hobbes (1651)
    The Social Contract – Hobbes (1651) We hold these truths to be self-evident, that all men are created equal, that they are endowed by their Creator with certain unalienable Rights, that among these are Life, Liberty and the pursuit of Happiness—That to secure these rights, Governments are instituted among Men, deriving their just powers from the consent of the governed. - Thomas Jefferson, Declaration of Independence (1776) 1. Hypothesis: The State of Nature: Thomas Hobbes begins by noting that all people are basically equal in strength and intelligence. No single person is so smart or powerful that they cannot be defeated our outwitted by someone else (or maybe a few others). That being so, everyone thinks to herself that she is capable of getting whatever she wants. Furthermore, people only ever act out of self-interest. He writes, “of the voluntary acts of every man, the object is some good to himself.” This leads to competition of every human against every other for the resources that we want to acquire. Hobbes concludes that, in our natural state (pre-government), we humans would be in a constant state of war and quarrel with one another—everyone competing and fighting for the resources, which are not abundant enough for everyone to have everything they desire. This natural state of man is one where people live in “continual fear and danger of violent death” and life itself is “solitary, poor, nasty, brutish, and short.” Basically, Hobbes is saying that mankind is generally selfish, and so, without laws to restrain him, he will do whatever he needs to in order to sustain his own life (even if it means stealing from or killing others).
    [Show full text]
  • Community Resilience: a Policy Tool for Local Government?
    This is a repository copy of Community resilience: a policy tool for local government?. White Rose Research Online URL for this paper: http://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/108066/ Version: Accepted Version Article: Platts-Fowler, D. and Robinson, D. (2016) Community resilience: a policy tool for local government? Local Government Studies, 42 (5). pp. 762-784. ISSN 0300-3930 https://doi.org/10.1080/03003930.2016.1186653 Reuse Unless indicated otherwise, fulltext items are protected by copyright with all rights reserved. The copyright exception in section 29 of the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988 allows the making of a single copy solely for the purpose of non-commercial research or private study within the limits of fair dealing. The publisher or other rights-holder may allow further reproduction and re-use of this version - refer to the White Rose Research Online record for this item. Where records identify the publisher as the copyright holder, users can verify any specific terms of use on the publisher’s website. Takedown If you consider content in White Rose Research Online to be in breach of UK law, please notify us by emailing [email protected] including the URL of the record and the reason for the withdrawal request. [email protected] https://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/ Community Resilience: A Policy Tool for Local Government? Published: Local Government Studies Deborah Platts-Fowler Department of Law and Criminology Sheffield Hallam University Sheffield S1 1WB [email protected] David Robinson (Corresponding Author) Centre for Regional Economic and Social Research Sheffield Hallam University Sheffield S1 1WB [email protected] Community Resilience: A Policy Tool for Local Government? Abstract In many countries local government has been a prime target of austerity measures.
    [Show full text]
  • Self-Ownership and Property in the Person: Democratization and a Tale of Two Concepts*
    The Journal of Political Philosophy: Volume 10, Number 1, 2002, pp. 20±53 Self-Ownership and Property in the Person: Democratization and a Tale of Two Concepts* CAROLE PATEMAN Political Science, University of California at Los Angeles Democracy is at war with the renting of human beings, not with private property. David Ellerman URING the 1990s a number of political philosophers turned their attention Dto the concept of self-ownership. Much of the discussion is critical of libertarianism,1 a political theory that goes hand-in-hand with neo-liberal economic doctrines and global policies of structural adjustment and privatization. Attracta Ingram's A Political Theory of Rights and G. A. Cohen's Self-Ownership, Freedom, and Equality are devoted to such criticism Uand I shall focus much of my argument on their books2). The consensus among most participants in the debate is that self-ownership is merely a way of talking about autonomy, but Ingram and Cohen go against the tide by arguing that the idea is inimical to autonomy and that an alternative is needed. In The Sexual Contract I am also critical of libertarianism, and my conclusion is similar to Ingram's and Cohen's. I argue that the idea of property in the person must be relinquished if a more free and democratic social and political order is to be created. However, despite some common concerns, there are very few points at which my work and that of Cohen and Ingram, or of most contributors to the current debates about self-ownership, come together. In large part this is because property in the person, not self-ownership, is central to my analysis.
    [Show full text]
  • Community-Based Participatory Research: Ethical Challenges
    Connected Communities Community-based Participatory Research: Ethical Challenges Durham Community Research Team Centre for Social Justice and Community Action, Durham University 1 COMMUNITY-BASED PARTICIPATORY RESEARCH: ETHICAL CHALLENG ES Community-based Participatory Research: Ethical Challenges Durham Community Research Team Centre for Social Justice and Community Action, Durham University Executive Summary This paper outlines the findings of a scoping study examining ethical issues in community-based participatory research (CBPR), based on a literature search and the deliberations of a co-inquiry action research group. The search indicated a range of research approaches claiming to be participatory and community-based, showing significant variation in degrees of participation and community control. Ethical challenges in CBPR include matters relating to: partnership, collaboration and power; community rights, conflict and representation; ownership and dissemination of data, findings and publications; anonymity, privacy and confidentiality; institutional ethical review processes; and blurred boundaries between researcher and researched, academic and activist. While many of these issues are common in qualitative social research, what is distinctive about CBPR is the openness, fluidity and unpredictability of the research process. It is often complicated by multi-layered partnerships based on the negotiation of power relations between diverse groups (with specific histories, politics, cultures and personalities), whilst also being constrained
    [Show full text]