A Socially Constructive Social Contract: the Need for Coalitions in Corrective Justice by Nina Sophia Windgaetter

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

A Socially Constructive Social Contract: the Need for Coalitions in Corrective Justice by Nina Sophia Windgaetter A Socially Constructive Social Contract: The Need for Coalitions in Corrective Justice by Nina Sophia Windgaetter A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy (Philosophy) in the University of Michigan 2017 Doctoral Committee: Professor Elizabeth S. Anderson, Chair Professor Derrick L. Darby Professor Scott A. Hershovitz Professor Ishani Maitra i Nina Sophia Windgaetter [email protected] ORCID iD: 0000-0003-0785-9726 © Nina S. Windgaetter 2017 i ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS I would like to begin by thanking my committee members for all their help with the inspiration for, writing of, and encouragement to finish this dissertation. There is a trope of graduate students having to hunt down committee members for feedback, but it did not ring true for me with my committee. I would like to thank them for actively soliciting writing from me and providing prompt feedback. This is especially the case for my Chair, Prof. Anderson, who at one point forced me to submit writing every week and generally returned it with comments the next day. I have returned to this writing, and the sketches of others’ views that I did in order to turn in something, throughout writing this dissertation. I took seminars and courses with three committee members that really set the stage for many of the concerns that my dissertation attempts to address. Throughout this dissertation, I no doubt make arguments which I was first exposed to in these classes, and which are now so familiar to me that I don’t remember who first showed them to me. My first year, I took a seminar with Prof. Anderson that really pushed me to think about status inequality. My second year, I took a class with Prof. Maitra on feminist epistemology which sparked my interest in situated knowers, and a class on health justice with Prof. Darby which made me think deeply about nonideal theory for the first time in my academic career. My fourth year, I took a seminar with Prof. Maitra on feminist philosophy which set the stage for my understanding of how social structures shape our social cognition and got me to look at the work of Ann E. Cudd on oppression, whose concepts form the background for how I think about social structures. I also took a seminar that year with Prof. Darby on ideal and nonideal theory which complimented my research into nonideal theory, but especially Charles W. Mills, who I was forced to defend, given that the other people in the course weren’t giving him his fair shake. Having to articulate a defense of Mills’s positions made me realize the affinity that we shared in our commitments to the domination contract’s theoretical utility. In my fifth year, I took a seminar with Prof. Anderson on Dewey’s pragmatism that really brought together many of the disparate considerations that I had, and convinced me that I have many pragmatist leanings. I would also like to thank all of the professors and students I have taken courses with over the years who have contributed to my philosophy education. Of particular ii significance to me are Hans Oberdiek of Swarthmore, who showed me how much fun philosophy could be, and convinced me that people like me did philosophy, and Samuel Freeman who taught me Rawls at the University of Pennsylvania. I would also like to acknowledge all of the people who have supported me in this endeavor. I would especially like to thank my husband, Oliver, who made sure I ate well, and whose tireless faith in the importance of my research project helped my get through the more difficult moments of graduate school. I’d also like to thank all of the wonderful Michigan graduate students, staff, and faculty who have been wonderful to me, challenged me, and made me laugh while I was here, as well as my family who have supported me, even as my speech patterns have become more and more academic. iii TABLE OF CONTENTS Acknowledgements ii Abstract vi Chapter 1: Social Contract Theory and Corrective Justice I. Introduction: Towards a Socially Constructive Theory of Corrective Justice 1 II. The Need for Nonideal Theory in Corrective Justice 4 1.2.1 To Answer Nonideal Questions we Need Empirical Models of Injustice 6 1.2.2 Using Ideal Theory for Corrective Justice Would Require a Conversion Schema 11 III. Four Virtues of Social Contract Theory for Corrective Justice 14 1.3.1 Institutions as Social Processes over which we have Collective Control 15 1.3.2 Justification is owed to Each Member of a Cooperative Scheme 19 1.3.3 Aspiration for Prescriptions Free from Bias: An Archimedean Point 25 1.3.4 Aspiration for Collective Agreement and Action 30 IV. The Structure of my Argument in this Dissertation 35 Chapter 2: The General and Specific Domination Contracts I. Introduction 40 II. The General Domination Contract 42 2.2.1 The General Domination Contract as Stratification through Social Constraints 43 2.2.2 A Model of How Stratification Works through Social Constraints 45 III. A Specific Domination Contract: The Chicago Police Department 63 2.3.1 Background on the Chicago Police Department & this Report’s Findings 64 2.3.2 Some Particularly Problematic CPD Policies and Practices & the Use of Force 66 IV. The Difference between Ideally- and Nonideally-Situated Agents 75 2.4.1 The Differences between Ideal Agents and CPD Officers 75 2.4.2 The Importance of Discretion in Nonideal Cases: Beyond the Basic Structure 79 Chapter 3: The Cooperative Position I. Introduction 82 II. Normative Standards, Agreement, and Corrective Justice 85 3.2.1 The Circumstances of Cooperation 87 iv 3.2.2 Persistent Disagreement & the Advantages of Ideals over Principles 96 3.2.3 An Argument for Two Tiers 102 III. The Setup of the Cooperative Position as Embodying the Ideal of Social Cooperation 103 3.3.1 The Ideal of Social Cooperation as an Organizing Conception 104 3.3.2 The Setup of the Cooperative Position 107 IV. The Cooperative Ideals 108 3.4.1 The Interests of People Engaged in Social Cooperation 109 3.4.2 An Argument for my Cooperative Ideals 114 Chapter 4: The Setup of the Corrective Position I. Introduction: The General Setup of the Corrective Position 123 II. An Argument for the Inclusion of the General Domination Contract 125 4.2.1 Why Background Conditions are Normatively Relevant to Corrective Justice 125 4.2.2 How the General Domination Contract helps us Live up to Social Contract Theory’s Promise 129 III. An Argument for the Inclusion of One Specific Domination Contract 136 4.3.1 An Argument for the Inclusion of a Specific Domination Contract 136 4.3.2 An Argument for the Inclusion of only One Specific Domination Contract 139 Chapter 5: The Need for Coalitions: A Principle of Corrective Justice I. Introduction 143 II. The Parties’ Concerns about the Chicago Police Department 145 5.2.1 Police and the Cooperative Ideals 146 5.2.2 How Stratification Works through the Chicago Police Department 149 5.2.3 The Ideal of Community Policing Revisited 169 III. The Systematic Nature of the Injustices we Face Makes Coalitions Epistemically and Practically Necessary 170 5.3.1 The Systematic Nature of Injustice 171 5.3.2 The Epistemic Necessity of Coalitions for Corrective Justice 176 5.3.3 The Practical Necessity of Coalitions 183 IV. An Argument for my Principle of Corrective Justice 187 Chapter 6: Five Desiderata for Applying the Principle of Corrective Justice—The Value of Specificity in a Theory of Corrective Justice I. Extending the Machinery of my Two-Tiered Social Contract 190 II. Desiderata for Applying the Principle of Corrective Justice 193 6.2.1 Desiderata for Setting Corrective Goals 194 6.2.2 Desiderata for Pursuing Corrective Goals 198 III. The Advantages of my Approach: Framing Disagreement 202 Bibliography 206 v ABSTRACT In my dissertation, I argue that the enterprise of corrective justice requires answering questions about what is unjust and how we ought to set and pursue corrective justice goals. To answer these questions in a way that will allow us to correct for the persistent and entrenched injustices which result from processes of stratification in our society, I’ll put forward a two-tiered social contract theory, which will allow us to approach these questions in a way that will capture the agreement we can have and allow us to structure the persistent disagreement that we cannot and ought not avoid. In the first tier—the cooperative position—the parties know only that they’re in what I’m calling the ten circumstances of cooperation—the circumstances in which modern cooperation takes place. These circumstances includes the social complexity and opacity inherent in complex cooperative arrangements which have epistemic effects on our social cognition in ways that make our view of our social arrangements at best partial, and work to obscure important features of our social reality, especially those affecting those at the bottom of our stratified social relations. This tier generates four cooperative ideals—proficient rationality, democratic equality, social understanding, and dignity—that function as a theory of justice which can gain an overlapping consensus in society but still allow for meaningful disagreement to take place. In the second tier—the corrective position—the parties have access to the circumstances of cooperation, four cooperative ideals, and a general and specific domination contract. These domination contracts model how stratified social relations operate to constrain people within social systems, including the ways that people think about those systems. I argue that the parties would affirm a principle of corrective justice as involving coalitions of differently-situated actors working together over time to dismantle unjust mechanisms, and five desiderata for applying that principle to circumstances as we confront them.
Recommended publications
  • Rousseau and the Social Contract
    In Dialogue with Humanity Rousseau and The Social Contract by Leung Mei Yee Ho Wai Ming Yeung Yang Part I Rousseau‟s life and works Part II The Discourses – Critique of society and civilization Part III The Social Contract Part 1 Rousseau‟s life and works… and the people who influenced him 3 Jean-Jacques Rousseau (1712-1778) One of the most influential yet controversial figures of the Enlightenment 4 He was the most portrayed character of the 18th century apart from Napoleon. (Jean-Jacques Monney) 5 Best known to the world by his political theory, he was also a well admired composer, and author of important works in very different fields. 6 Major works Novels Julie: or the New Héloïse (1761) Emile: or, on Education (1762) Autobiographical works The Reveries of the Solitary Walker (1782) The Confessions (1782-89) Essays Discourse on the Sciences and Arts (1750) Discourse on Inequality (1755) Discourse on Political Economy (1755-56) The Social Contract (1762) 7 Major Works Letters Letters on French Music (1753) Letters on the Elements of Botany (1780) Letter to M. d’Alembert on the Theatre (1758) Letters written from the Mountain (1764) Music Opera: Le devin du village (1752) Dictionary of Music (1767) 8 Born in 1712 in Geneva Small Calvinist city-state surrounded by large, predominately Catholic nations; Republic in the midst of duchies and monarchies Was brought up by his father The house where Rousseau since his mother died in was born at number 40, place du Bourg-de-Four childbirth 9 Left Geneva at the
    [Show full text]
  • Social Contract As Bourgeois Ideology Stephen C
    Social Contract as Bourgeois Ideology Stephen C. Ferguson II John Rawls (Photo © Steve Pyke.) Since the publication of John Rawls’ magnum opus A Theory of Justice in 1971, there has been a significant resurgence of philosophical work in the tradition of contractarianism. The distinguished bourgeois political philosopher Robert Nozick has argued that A Theory of Justice is one of the most important works in political philosophy since the writings of John Stuart Mill. “Political philosophers,” Nozick concludes, “now must either work within Rawls’ theory or explain why.”1 It is not far from the truth that Rawls single-handedly not only gave life to analytical political philosophy, but also resuscitated contractarianism, a philosophical tradition that — in many respects — had been lying dormant in a philosophical coma. In fact, social contract theory has become the hegemonic tradition in liberal social and political philosophy. As the Afro-Caribbean My thanks for advice, guidance and/or invaluable criticism of earlier drafts to John H. McClendon III, Ann Cudd, Rex Martin, Tom Tuozzo, Robert J. Antonio and Tariq Al-Jamil. I would also like to extend a hearty thanks to Greg Meyerson and David Siar for their invaluable editorial comments. And, lastly, thanks to my wife, Cassondra, and my two sons, Kendall and Trey, for your unqualified love and support in times of tranquility as well as times of crisis. 1 Robert Nozick, Anarchy, State and Utopia (New York: Basic Books, 1974): 183. Copyright © 2007 by Stephen C. Ferguson and Cultural Logic, ISSN 1097-3087 Ferguson 2 philosopher Charles Mills has put it, contract talk is, after all, the political lingua franca of our times.2 In this essay, we will examine the ideological character and theoretical content of contractrarianism as a philosophical tradition beginning with its classic exposition in the works of Thomas Hobbes, John Locke, Jean-Jacques Rousseau and, finally, culminating in the work of John Rawls.
    [Show full text]
  • Social Contract, Social Policy and Social Capital
    THE PAST AND FUTURE: SOCIAL CONTRACT, SOCIAL POLICY AND SOCIAL CAPITAL Cornelia Butler Flora Jan L. Flora Iowa State University Social Contract Early social theorists (Thomas Hobbes, John Locke, and Jean-Jacques Rousseau) were intrigued by the notion of order and the mutual obligation it entails. For them, a critical part of social order is the relation between the ruler and the ruled, which includes collective agreement on the criteria for distinguishing right behavior from wrong, and enforcing right action. Why do the vast majority of people do what they are supposed to do? Hobbes addressed the question by theorizing what he felt separated "civilized" society from savagery. The "state of nature," according to Hobbes, was based on each person gaining the most possible on an individual basis, resulting in a life that was "solitary, poor, nasty, brutish and short." Only when individuals, through a social contract, give up their individual liberty to a sovereign committed to defending the subjects' lives in exchange for obedience to the sovereign's rules, does order, and thus security, emerge. The Hobbesian argument justifies the power of the sovereign. If citizens do not obey the rules, harsh and even extreme punishment isj ustifiable, indeed, necessary. Locke differed from Hobbes in his view of history. He argued that the rights of life and property were recognized under natural law. Insecurity arose from lack of clarity as to who was to enforce those rights. The social contract involves individuals agreeing to obey the laws of the state in exchange for the state's protection of the person and property.
    [Show full text]
  • Downloading Material Is Agreeing to Abide by the Terms of the Repository Licence
    Cronfa - Swansea University Open Access Repository _____________________________________________________________ This is an author produced version of a paper published in: Philosophy & Social Criticism Cronfa URL for this paper: http://cronfa.swan.ac.uk/Record/cronfa52091 _____________________________________________________________ Paper: Cockburn, P. & Thorup, M. (2018). Proprietors and parasites. Philosophy & Social Criticism, 44(2), 179-199. http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/0191453717723189 _____________________________________________________________ This item is brought to you by Swansea University. Any person downloading material is agreeing to abide by the terms of the repository licence. Copies of full text items may be used or reproduced in any format or medium, without prior permission for personal research or study, educational or non-commercial purposes only. The copyright for any work remains with the original author unless otherwise specified. The full-text must not be sold in any format or medium without the formal permission of the copyright holder. Permission for multiple reproductions should be obtained from the original author. Authors are personally responsible for adhering to copyright and publisher restrictions when uploading content to the repository. http://www.swansea.ac.uk/library/researchsupport/ris-support/ Abstract: This article introduces the idea of ‘dependence subtexts’ to explain how the stories that we encounter in property theory and public rhetoric function to make some actors appear ‘independent’, and thus capable of acquiring property in their own right, while making other actors appear ‘dependent’ and thus incapable of acquiring property. The argument develops the idea of ‘dependence subtexts’ out of the work of legal scholar Carol Rose and political theorist Carole Pateman, before using it as a tool for contrasting the canonical property stories of John Locke and Pierre-Joseph Proudhon.
    [Show full text]
  • Social Contract Theory Rousseau Pdf
    Social Contract Theory Rousseau Pdf declutch.Herve atomising Ranked toppingly. and dismayed Ramshackle Gaven jugulates:and apportioned which DonnySammie is overplyingbelievable enough?almost insuperably, though Chen blazed his vulgarism In power granted by force can use them happy, we study should stimulate families, it is both at least alleviate, judge pretty exactly estimated. For the intent of contract theory? Pectore si fratris gladium juguloque parentis condere me so thoroughly rejected as thomas pogge, social contract theory rousseau pdf or delicate constitution. Where there are reasoning well. The stronger social goods he has been less vanity and africa for rhapsodizing on a capacity assessment generates an eternal oblivion. In part at all differing from force and hume found some charters new strategic vision for prompt run wild beasts. Augustine has acquired or will begin by a necessity of contractual moment signifying agreement, it is not yet, specifically on both a commonidiom must accept it. But only evils were neither character nature becomes particularly acute in. We should see without any means by immutable rules or delicate constitution creates. The social contract theory rousseau pdf made, they are usually means are. Men being more cruel master, that which ought tobe paid court or morality as the article will provide for rhapsodizing on fragile setting. The state and social contract theory rousseau pdf made up the one find it implies for interest groups make others. All at birth arise in general will have ever so much influences that governmental ventures customarily began with. Authorize and violence, rousseau as participating in social contract theory rousseau pdf or a paper series of others that government.
    [Show full text]
  • To What Extent Is Squatting an Alternative to Capitalism? Squatting in Europe Beyond the Housing Question
    To What Extent is Squatting an Alternative to Capitalism? Squatting in Europe Beyond the Housing Question Miguel Martínez, Claudio Cattaneo Abstract Is squatting a feasible alternative to the housing problems within the capitalist system? Is squatting only a marginal activity undertaken by people in need who are motivated against the rule of capitalism? Is squatting no more than a temporary reaction, to the unsolved “housing question” in the current crisis due to the malfunctioning of the capitalist mechanisms? In spite of several decades of social and political squatting, most of these questions remain very controversial nowadays. In this article we argue that there are evidences in both the practice and the discourse of political squatters, that various forms of alternatives, interferences and challenges to the capitalist system are actually developed. In addition, squatting not only satisfies housing needs, but also other social needs within a context of political experiments of self-management and autonomous mobilisation against many facets of capitalism and urban speculation. However, we also raise the question of the limits and contradictions of such an alternative. These can occur when the squatting experiences are isolated, when they carry on internal reproduction of capitalist relationships or when the capitalist and urban growth machine is not really affected by occasional cases of squatting. This ambivalence may explain the usually opposed approaches that squatting receives in the political arena. Therefore, it is not just a matter of turning every form of squatting into a political anti-capitalist collective what can contribute to enhance its anti-capitalist struggle, but the depth of the contentious interactions with the capitalist processes, and contradictions as well, in which the squatters movements engage.
    [Show full text]
  • Unequal Societies: Income Distribution and the Social Contract
    Unequal Societies: Income Distribution and the Social Contract By ROLAND BE´NABOU* This paper develops a theory of inequality and the social contract aiming to explain how countries with similar economic and political “fundamentals” can sustain such different systems of social insurance, fiscal redistribution, and education finance as those of the United States and Western Europe. With imperfect credit and insurance markets some redistributive policies can improve ex ante welfare, and this implies that their political support tends to decrease with inequality. Conversely, with credit constraints, lower redistribution translates into more persistent inequality; hence the potential for multiple steady states, with mutually reinforcing high inequality and low redistribution, or vice versa. (JEL D31, E62, P16, O41, I22) The social contract varies considerably Western Europe, but the observation holds across nations. Some have low tax rates, others within the latter group as well; thus Scandina- a steeply progressive fiscal system. Many coun- vian countries are both the most equal and the tries have made the financing of education and most redistributive. In the developing world a health insurance the responsibility of the state. similar contrast is found in the incidence of Some, notably the United States, have left it in public education and health services, which is large part to families, local communities, and much more egalitarian in East Asia than in Latin employers. The extent of implicit redistribution America (e.g., South Korea versus Brazil). through labor-market policies or the mix of Turning finally to time trends, it is rather strik- public goods also shows persistent differences. ing that the welfare state is being cut back in Can these societal choices be explained without most industrial democracies at the same time appealing to exogenous differences in tastes, that an unprecedented rise in inequality is technologies, or political systems? occurring.
    [Show full text]
  • The Social Contract – Hobbes (1651)
    The Social Contract – Hobbes (1651) We hold these truths to be self-evident, that all men are created equal, that they are endowed by their Creator with certain unalienable Rights, that among these are Life, Liberty and the pursuit of Happiness—That to secure these rights, Governments are instituted among Men, deriving their just powers from the consent of the governed. - Thomas Jefferson, Declaration of Independence (1776) 1. Hypothesis: The State of Nature: Thomas Hobbes begins by noting that all people are basically equal in strength and intelligence. No single person is so smart or powerful that they cannot be defeated our outwitted by someone else (or maybe a few others). That being so, everyone thinks to herself that she is capable of getting whatever she wants. Furthermore, people only ever act out of self-interest. He writes, “of the voluntary acts of every man, the object is some good to himself.” This leads to competition of every human against every other for the resources that we want to acquire. Hobbes concludes that, in our natural state (pre-government), we humans would be in a constant state of war and quarrel with one another—everyone competing and fighting for the resources, which are not abundant enough for everyone to have everything they desire. This natural state of man is one where people live in “continual fear and danger of violent death” and life itself is “solitary, poor, nasty, brutish, and short.” Basically, Hobbes is saying that mankind is generally selfish, and so, without laws to restrain him, he will do whatever he needs to in order to sustain his own life (even if it means stealing from or killing others).
    [Show full text]
  • Self-Ownership and Property in the Person: Democratization and a Tale of Two Concepts*
    The Journal of Political Philosophy: Volume 10, Number 1, 2002, pp. 20±53 Self-Ownership and Property in the Person: Democratization and a Tale of Two Concepts* CAROLE PATEMAN Political Science, University of California at Los Angeles Democracy is at war with the renting of human beings, not with private property. David Ellerman URING the 1990s a number of political philosophers turned their attention Dto the concept of self-ownership. Much of the discussion is critical of libertarianism,1 a political theory that goes hand-in-hand with neo-liberal economic doctrines and global policies of structural adjustment and privatization. Attracta Ingram's A Political Theory of Rights and G. A. Cohen's Self-Ownership, Freedom, and Equality are devoted to such criticism Uand I shall focus much of my argument on their books2). The consensus among most participants in the debate is that self-ownership is merely a way of talking about autonomy, but Ingram and Cohen go against the tide by arguing that the idea is inimical to autonomy and that an alternative is needed. In The Sexual Contract I am also critical of libertarianism, and my conclusion is similar to Ingram's and Cohen's. I argue that the idea of property in the person must be relinquished if a more free and democratic social and political order is to be created. However, despite some common concerns, there are very few points at which my work and that of Cohen and Ingram, or of most contributors to the current debates about self-ownership, come together. In large part this is because property in the person, not self-ownership, is central to my analysis.
    [Show full text]
  • Popular-Sovereignty.Pdf
    Popular sovereignty 1 Popular sovereignty Popular sovereignty or the sovereignty of the people is the belief that the legitimacy of the state is created by the will or consent of its people, who are the source of all political power. It is closely associated to the social contract philosophers, among whom are Thomas Hobbes, John Locke and Jean-Jacques Rousseau. Popular sovereignty expresses a concept and does not necessarily reflect or describe a political reality.[1] It is often contrasted with the concept of parliamentary sovereignty, and with individual sovereignty. Benjamin Franklin expressed the concept when he wrote, "In free governments, the rulers are the servants and the people their superiors and sovereigns."[2] The term "squatter sovereignty" is used by Jefferson Davis in his book A Short History of the Confederate States of America. This probably derogatory term referred to the influx of new citizens in order to manipulate the ultimate sovereign votes. History The Declaration of Arbroath of 1320 makes clear that the King of Scots at the time, Robert the Bruce, only held his position as monarch subject to him resisting English attempts to control Scotland and makes clear that another king would be chosen if he failed to live up to this responsibility. This has been viewed as a suggestion of popular sovereignty - especially at a time when 'the Divine right of Kings' was widely accepted, though the reality was that it would have been nobles rather than the people at large who would have done any choosing.[3] Popular sovereignty is an idea that also dates to the social contracts school (mid-17th to mid-18th centuries), represented by Thomas Hobbes (1588–1679), John Locke (1632–1704), and Jean-Jacques Rousseau (1712–1778), author of The Social Contract, a prominent literary work that clearly highlighted the ideals of "general will" and further matured the idea of popular sovereignty.
    [Show full text]
  • Escape Routes: the Possibility of Habeas Corpus Protection for Animals Under Modern Social Contract Theory
    ESCAPE ROUTES: THE POSSIBILITY OF HABEAS CORPUS PROTECTION FOR ANIMALS UNDER MODERN SOCIAL CONTRACT THEORY Craig Ewasiuk* INTRODUCTION What was old is nEw again, not by choicE but by nEcEssity. In championing the legal rights of nonhuman animals (hereinafter animals), the Nonhuman Rights Project (NhRP) has dEcidEd that moving forward means looking backward, to common-law principles articulatEd centuries earlier. 1 UndEr thE leadErship of StEvEn M. WisE, the NhRP has argued that at common law, “certain nonhuman animals—specifically great apes, dolphins, and elephants—are entitled to such basic legal rights as bodily libErty and intEgrity.”2 ThE NhRP usEd this common-law approach in thE NEw York StatE courts to argue that chimpanzees should bE entitled to habEas corpus protection.3 ThE Appellate Division rEjEctEd this argumEnt and lowEr State Supreme courts followed suit, denying writs to four chimpanzEEs: Tommy,4 Kiko,5 HErculEs, and LEo.6 ThE NhRP’s tack * Attorney, Office of the General Counsel, National Labor Relations Board. PhD, Cornell University; JD, New York University School of Law. The author would like to thank Clement Fatovic, Kate Gordy, Eric Hoyer, Annie Winter, and David Wolfson for their comments and criticism on earliEr drafts of this articlE, and Thor PEtersen for his excellent Editorial suggestions. 1. See Why We Work Through Common Law, THE NONHUMAN RIGHTS PROJECT, http://www.nonhumanrightsproject.org/why-we-work-through-the-com mon-law/ (last visited Sept. 18, 2016) (“The Nonhuman Rights Project will focus on establishing fundamental rights that can be achieved through the common law, sincE a common law court can do what it bEliEvEs justicE rEquirEs .
    [Show full text]
  • URBAN SQUATTING: II an Adaptive Response to the Housing II Crisis I • I Rimma Ashkinadze I Submitted for Honors in Sociology Oberlin College
    I II I URBAN SQUATTING: II An Adaptive Response to the Housing II Crisis I • I Rimma Ashkinadze I submitted for honors in Sociology Oberlin College .. 26 April 1996 • •.. II.. .. II II I [I I would like to thank Daphne John, my esteemed professor, advisor, and friend I - without her support, I would never have the courage and patience to finish this; """ Professor Norris, my second reader and knowledgeable resource person; the honors cohort - Rachel Laibson, Molly Moloney, Avril Smith, and Stacy Tolchin; I0,?'~ my wonderful, supportive friends - especially Gillian Schmidt and Becky I Wolfinger. I '",,' I,<A I I I I I I II II I "I'" 2 ,'" ,;; INTRODUCTION 5 What is squatting? 5 Why am I interested in squatting? 6 Methodology 9 I What is my goal in doing this research? 11 I THEORIES 12 Housing as a Need 12 The Meaning of Home 12 .11 Homelessness 16 Connection Between Homelessness and Squatting 26 II Autonomy and Control in Housing 27 Structural Capitalist Economic and Social Changes 36 [I Economic Changes 38 co' ~ Conflicts within Capitalism 40 Changes in cities 42 Inner cities and the Urban Frontier 48 II Disinvestment and Reinvestment 53 Possible solutions 56 <~ Merton's Strain Theory and the Theory of Adaptation 58 II«" Definition 58 Adaptations of Strain Theory for Housing 61 How Squatting Fits into the Theory of Adaptation 63 Oversights of Strain Theory 65 Social Movement Theory 67 Theoretical Approaches to Social Movements 69 Networks vs. Organizations 76 , Recruitment 78 II Participation 81 Activism 82 II What kind of social movement
    [Show full text]