This Is Only a Sample. to Purchase the Ebook, Please Visit Our Website. SAINT SUMMA THOMAS CONTRA AQUINAS GENTILES BOOK ONE: GOD

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

This Is Only a Sample. to Purchase the Ebook, Please Visit Our Website. SAINT SUMMA THOMAS CONTRA AQUINAS GENTILES BOOK ONE: GOD This is only a sample. To purchase the ebook, please visit our website. SAINT SUMMA THOMAS CONTRA AQUINAS GENTILES BOOK ONE: GOD Translated, University with an Introduction of and Notes, Notre Dame Press by NotreDame ANTON C. PEGIS, London ER.S.C. Copyright © 1955 by Doubleday & Company, Inc. First published in 1955 by Hanover House as On the Truth of the Catholic Faith First paperback edition 1955 by Image Books Published by arrangement with Doubleday & Company, Inc. University of Notre Dame Press edition 1975 Notre Dame, Indiana 46556 undpress.nd.edu Reprinted in 1978, 1982, 1986, 1988, 1990, 1996, 1997, 1999, 2003, 2005, 2009, 2012, 2014 Manufactured in the United States of America Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Thomas Aquinas, Saint, 1225?–1274. Summa contra gentiles. Reprint of the ed. published by Hanover House, Garden City, N.Y., under title: On the truth of the Catholic faith. Includes bibliographies. CONTENTS: book 1. God, translated, with an introd. and notes, by A. C. Pegis. —book 2. Creation, translated, with an introd. and notes, by J. F. Anderson. [etc.] 1. Apologetics—Middle Ages, 600–1500. I. Title. [BX1749.T4 1975] 239 75-19883 Summa Contra Gentiles, Book One: God ISBN 13: 978-0-268-01678-4 (pbk. : alk. paper) ISBN 10: 0-268-01678-X (pbk. : alk. paper) ISBN 9780268045524 ∞ This book is printed on acid-free paper. This e-Book was converted from the original source file by a third-party vendor. Readers who notice any formatting, textual, or readability issues are encouraged to contact the publisher at [email protected]. FOR MY CHILDREN The pursuit of wisdom especially joins man to God in friendship -SAINT THOMAS AQUINAS Contents. PAGE General Introduction I St. Thomas and his writings 1 5 u Aristotelianism and the occasion of the Summa Contra Gentiles 19 111 The plan of the Summa Contra Gentiles 26 SUMMA CONTRA GENTILES, BOOK ONE: GOD I The Christian God 4 5 11 The present translation 50 Bibliography 53 CHAPTER 1. The office of the wise man 59 2. The author's intention in the present work 61 3· On the way in which divine truth is to be made known 63 4· That the truth about God to which the natural reason reaches is fittingly proposed to men for belief 66 5· That the truths the human reason is not able to investigate are fittingly proposed to men for be- lief 69 6. That to give assent to the truths of faith is not foolishness even though they are above reason 71 9 10 CONTENTS CHAPTER PAGE 7. That the truth of reason is not opposed to the truth of the Christian faith 74 8. How the human reason is related to the truth of faith 75 9· The order and manner of procedure in the pres- ent work 77 10. The opinion of those who say that the existence of God, being self-evident, cannot be demon- strated 79 11. A refutation of the abovementioned opinion and a solution of the arguments 81 12. The opinion of those who say that the exist­ ence of God cannot be demonstrated but is held by faith alone 83 1 3· Arguments in proof of the existence of God 8 5 14- That to know God we must use the way of re- motion 96 15. That God is eternal 98 16. That there is no passive potency in God 100 17. That there is no matter in God 101 18. That there is no composition in God 103 19. That in God there is nothing violent or un- natural 105 20. That God is not a body 106 21. That God is His essence 116 22. That in God being and essence are the same 118 23. That no accident is found in God 121 24. That the divine being cannot be determined by the addition of some substantial difference 124 25. That God is not in some genus 126 CONTENTS 11 CHAPTER PAGE 26. That God is not the formal being of all things 128 2 7. That God is not the form of any body 1 3 3 28. On the divine perfection 135 29. On the likeness of creatures to God 138 30. The names that can be predicated of God 1 39 31· That the divine perfection and the plurality of divine names are not opposed to the divine sim~ plicity 141 32. That nothing is predicated univocally of God and other things 143 33· That not all names are said of God and crea~ tures in a purely equivocal way 145 34· That names said of God and creatures are said analogically 14 7 35· That many names said of God are not synonyms 149 36. How our intellect forms a proposition about G~ 1~ 37· That God is good 150 38. That God is goodness itself 152 39· That there cannot be evil in God 154 40. That God is the good of every good 156 41. That God is the highest good 1 57 42. That God is one 158 43· That God is infinite 165 44· That God is intelligent 170 45· That God's act of understanding is His essence 173 46. That God understands through nothing other than through His essence 1 74 47· That God understands Himself perfectly 176 12 CONTENTS CHAPTER PAGE 48. That primarily and essentially God knows only Himself 178 49· That God understands things other than Him- ~H 1~ 50. That God has a proper knowledge of all things 181 51-52. Arguments inquiring how a multitude of in- tellectual objects is in the divine intellect 18 5 53· The solution of the above difficulty 187 54· How the divine essence, being one and simple, is the proper likeness of all intelligible objects 189 55· That God understands all things together 192 56. That God's knowledge is not habitual 194 57· That God's knowledge is not discursive 196 58. That God does not understand by composing and dividing 199 59· That the truth of enunciables is not excluded from God 201 6o. That God is truth 204 61. That God is the purest truth 205 62. That the divine truth is the first and highest ~~ 2~ 63. The arguments of those who wish to take away the knowledge of singulars from God 209 64. The order of what is to be said on the divine knowledge 212 65. That God knows singulars 213 66. That God knows the things that are not 217 67. That God knows future contingent singulars 221 68. That God knows the motions of the will 22 5 69. That God knows infinite things 227 CONTENTS 13 CHAPTER PAGE 70. That God knows lowly things 231 71. That God knows evils 235 72. That God has will 239 73· That the will of God is His essence 242 74· That the principal object of the divine will is the divine essence 244 7 5. That in willing Himself God also wills other things 245 76. That God wills Himself and other things by one act of will 24 7 77· That the multitude of the objects of the will is not opposed to the divine simplicity 2 50 7S. That the divine will extends to singular goods 251 79· That God wills even the things that are not yet 2 53 So. That His own being and His own goodness God wills necessarily 2 55 S1. That God does not will other things in a neces- sary way 257 S2. Arguments leading to awkward consequences if God does not necessarily will things other than Himself 260 S3. That God wills something other than Himself with the necessity of supposition 263 S4. That the will of God is not of what is in itself impossible 264 S5. That the divine will does not remove contin­ gency from things, nor does it impose absolute necessity on them 266 S6. That a reason can be assigned to the divine will 267 S7. That nothing can be the cause of the divine ~ 2~ CONTENTS CHAPTER PAGE 88. That in God there is free choice 270 89. That in God there are not the passions of the appetites 271 90. That in God there are delight and joy, but they are not opposed to the divine perfection 275 91. That in God there is love 277 92. How virtues may be held to be in God 282 93· That in God there are the moral virtues that deal with actions 285 94· That in God there are contemplative virtues 289 95· That God cannot will evil 290 96. That God hates nothing, and the hatred of no thing befits Him 292 97. That God is living 294 98. That God is His life 29 5 99· That the life of God is everlasting 296 100. That God is blessed 298 101. That God is His blessedness 300 102. That the perfect and unique blessedness of God excels every other blessedness 301 Subject Index 30 5 Index of Proper Names 313 General Introduction. I. ST. THOMAS AND HIS WRITINGS St. Thomas Aquinas was born in Italy in the castle of Roccasecca, near Aquino, early in 1225. Until 1239 he re­ mained an oblate in the Benedictine Monastery of Monte Cassino where he had been entered by his parents in 1231. He studied the liberal arts at the newly established Uni­ versity of Naples, and in 1244 decided to become a Domini­ can. He set out for Paris, arriving there in the summer of 1245.
Recommended publications
  • CTR EDITORIAL (1000 Words)
    CTR n.s.16/2 (Spring 2019) 49–66 Sola Scriptura, the Fathers, and the Church: Arguments from the Lutheran Reformers Carl L. Beckwith Beeson Divinity School Samford University, Birmingham, AL I. INTRODUCTION I learned to show this reverence and respect only to those books of the scriptures that are now called canonical so that I most firmly believe that none of their authors erred in writing anything. And if I come upon something in those writings that seems contrary to the truth, I have no doubt that either the manuscript is defective or the translator did not follow what was said or that I did not understand it. I, however, read other authors in such a way that, no matter how much they excel in holiness and learning, I do not suppose that something is true by reason of the fact that they thought so, but because they were able to convince me either through those canonical authors or by plausible reason that it does not depart from the truth.1 Augustine to Jerome, Letter 82 Martin Luther and his reforming colleagues maintained that Scripture alone determines the articles of faith. All that the church believes, teaches, and confesses rests upon the authority of the canonical scriptures, upon the unique revelation of God himself through his prophets and apostles. Luther declares, “It will not do to make articles of faith out of 1Augustine, Letter 82.3 in Letters 1–99, trans. Roland Teske (Hyde Park, NY: New City Press, 2001), 316. 50 Criswell Theological Review the holy Fathers’ words or works.
    [Show full text]
  • Aquinas and the Cry of Rachel John F
    Aquinas and the Cry of Rachel John F. X. Knasas Suffering and Hope Conference University of St. Thomas November 10-13, 2005 I examine Jacques Maritain’s critique of a Thomistic explanation of suffering from his 1942 Marquette Aquinas Lecture, St. Thomas and the Problem of Evil.1 In sum, at Summa Theologiae I, 48, 2c, Aquinas argues that God permits evils for the perfection of the universe. Evils are the concomitant of corruptible things. And corruptible things belong to the perfection of the created order which requires every grade of goodness. Using the Biblical personage of Rachel, who has lost her children to the soldiers of King Herod, Maritain poignantly observes that Aquinas’ reason would never satisfy a mother suffering the loss of her child. What can be the value of the perfection of the universe in comparison to the loss of a young and innocent human being? And so, according to Maritain, one must balance 48, 2, with Summa Contra Gentiles III, 112, in which Aquinas describes the rational creature as a person.2 This description means that the rational creature is more like a whole than a part thereof. Hence, in the perspective of the human as person, Martian concludes that human suffering is “an utter anomaly”3 that is better understood as the unfortunate result of the rational creature’s free refusal of divine love, i.e., as a result of original sin. In my opinion, neither of Maritain’s two reasons hold. First, SCG III, 112, never ascribes to humans the exalted sense of person used by Maritain.
    [Show full text]
  • Natural Reason in the Summa Contra Gentiles
    Natural Reason in the Summa contra Gentiles RUDI A. TE VELDE A distinctive feature of Aquinas's Summa contra Gentiles is the central role the author assigns to natural reason in his project of manifesting the truth of Christian faith. Reason is supposed to give a rational account of the truth of what faith professes about God, to arrive at a veritas demonstrative!,) which will be shown to accord with the Christian religion. It is mainly because of this emphatic and what seems to be a rather presumptuous role of natural reason that the work has occasioned so much discussion and, consequently, diversity of opinion among the interpreters of Aquinas's thought. Is the Contra Gentiles, insofar as reason is the leading principle of the investigation, to be regarded as a kind of 'philosophical' summa) as it was sometimes labeled in the past? The objection immediately arises that the fourth book explicitly deals with those truths of faith which are above reason. And further, on account of its declared subject-matter—the truth of the Catholic faith—it seems unmistakably a theological work or, more exactly, a work in which the truth of Christian faith is expounded and defended. Those who stress the theological character of the work, a work written from the point of view of faith, usually refer to what seems to be the original title: "On the Truth of the Catholic Faith against the Errors of the Infidels."1 1. In early manuscripts of the work the title used is "Liber de veritate catholicae fΐdei contra errores inήdelium." See the Leonine edition of the Contra Gentiles in 42 NATURAL REASON IN THE CONTRA GENTILES 43 The riddle of the Contra Gentiles goes deeper than the question of whether it is intended primarily as a theological or as a philosophical work, based on reason as a common human faculty for truth.
    [Show full text]
  • Durham Research Online
    Durham Research Online Deposited in DRO: 05 September 2017 Version of attached le: Accepted Version Peer-review status of attached le: Peer-reviewed Citation for published item: Van Nieuwenhove, Rik (2017) 'Contemplation, intellectus, and simplex intuitus in Aquinas : recovering a Neoplatonic theme.', American Catholic philosophical quarterly., 91 (2). pp. 199-225. Further information on publisher's website: https://doi.org/10.5840/acpq2017227108 Publisher's copyright statement: Additional information: Use policy The full-text may be used and/or reproduced, and given to third parties in any format or medium, without prior permission or charge, for personal research or study, educational, or not-for-prot purposes provided that: • a full bibliographic reference is made to the original source • a link is made to the metadata record in DRO • the full-text is not changed in any way The full-text must not be sold in any format or medium without the formal permission of the copyright holders. Please consult the full DRO policy for further details. Durham University Library, Stockton Road, Durham DH1 3LY, United Kingdom Tel : +44 (0)191 334 3042 | Fax : +44 (0)191 334 2971 https://dro.dur.ac.uk Contemplation, intellectus and simplex intuitus in Aquinas: Recovering a Neoplatonic Theme.1 Rik Van Nieuwenhove Abstract. This contribution examines two related points in relation to Aquinas’s understanding of contemplation (a sorely neglected topic in scholarship). First, (a) after having outlined that the final act of contemplation culminates in an intellective (or non- discursive), simple apprehension of the truth (especially divine truth) I will examine how this act relates to the three operations of the intellect (grasping of quiddity; judgement; reasoning) Aquinas identifies in a number of places.
    [Show full text]
  • SUMMA CONTRA GENTILES by Thomas Aquinas (Selections)
    Summa Contra Gentiles - Aquinas SUMMA CONTRA GENTILES derstanding cannot go so far of its natural power as to grasp by Thomas Aquinas His substance, since under the conditions of the present life the knowledge of our understanding commences with (selections) sense; and therefore objects beyond sense cannot be grasped by human understanding except so far as knowledge is gathered of them through the senses. But things of sense I, 3 That the Truths which we confess concerning God fall cannot lead our understanding to read in them the essence under two Modes or Categories of the Divine Substance, inasmuch as they are effects inade- BECAUSE not every truth admits of the same mode of mani- quate to the power that caused them. Nevertheless our un- festation, and "a well-educated man will expect exactness in derstanding is thereby led to some knowledge of God, every class of subject, according as the nature of the thing namely, of His existence and of other attributes that must admits," as is very well remarked by the Philosopher (Eth. necessarily be attributed to the First Cause. There are, there- Nicom. I, 1094b), we must first show what mode of proof is fore, some points of intelligibility in God, accessible to hu- possible for the truth that we have now before us. The truths man reason, and other points that altogether transcend the that we confess concerning God fall under two modes. Some power of human reason. things true of God are beyond all the competence of human The same thing may be understood from consideration of reason, as that God is Three and One.
    [Show full text]
  • St.-Thomas-Aquinas-The-Summa-Contra-Gentiles.Pdf
    The Catholic Primer’s Reference Series: OF GOD AND HIS CREATURES An Annotated Translation (With some Abridgement) of the SUMMA CONTRA GENTILES Of ST. THOMAS AQUINAS By JOSEPH RICKABY, S.J., Caution regarding printing: This document is over 721 pages in length, depending upon individual printer settings. The Catholic Primer Copyright Notice The contents of Of God and His Creatures: An Annotated Translation of The Summa Contra Gentiles of St Thomas Aquinas is in the public domain. However, this electronic version is copyrighted. © The Catholic Primer, 2005. All Rights Reserved. This electronic version may be distributed free of charge provided that the contents are not altered and this copyright notice is included with the distributed copy, provided that the following conditions are adhered to. This electronic document may not be offered in connection with any other document, product, promotion or other item that is sold, exchange for compensation of any type or manner, or used as a gift for contributions, including charitable contributions without the express consent of The Catholic Primer. Notwithstanding the preceding, if this product is transferred on CD-ROM, DVD, or other similar storage media, the transferor may charge for the cost of the media, reasonable shipping expenses, and may request, but not demand, an additional donation not to exceed US$25. Questions concerning this limited license should be directed to [email protected] . This document may not be distributed in print form without the prior consent of The Catholic Primer. Adobe®, Acrobat®, and Acrobat® Reader® are either registered trademarks or trademarks of Adobe Systems Incorporated in the United States and/or other countries.
    [Show full text]
  • ZEN? Dwinrfes, LX, If 2019
    ZEN? Dwinrfes, LX, iF 2019 IS THERE A PLACE FOR DOCTRINAL DEVELOPMENT IN AQUINAS’ THOUGHT? EDUARDO ECHEVERRIA as em How should we think aboutlegitimate doctrinal development?' Briefly, re Aidan Nicholsis right, “What we shouldlookfor is a theory which allowsfor a genuine developmentin doctrineyet respects the substantial homogeneity of revealed truth”? Does Aquinashelp us in this search? In his 1998 Encyclical, Fides et Ratio, John PaulII wrote,“the Church has beenjustified in consistently proposingSt. Thomasas a master of thought and a model of the right way to do theology {and philosophy].”? Does Aquinasprovide a model with regard to doctrinal development? Yes,in this short essay I will show that he adumbrates a theoryof doctrinal development. Admittedly, Henri de Lubac is correct that Aquinas does not devoteat- tention as suchin his writings to an account of doctrinal development.’ Avery Dulles,S.J., suggests why:“Priorto the nineteenth century, theologians [such as Aquinas] had practically no awarenessofreal doctrinal change... [D]octrinal reform couldnot take the form of true progress or development. Improvement 1 Throughoutthis article, I am muchindebted to Christopher Kaczor, “Thomas Aquinas on the Developmentof Doctrine,” Theological Studies 62 (2001): 283-302. Of great help to mein general is also Aidan Nichols, From Newman to Congar: The Idea of Doctrinal Developmentfrom the Victoriansto the Second Vatican Council (Edinburgh: T&T Clark, 1990), butparticularly helpfulis his account ofNeo-Scholasticism on doctrinal developmentin the first halfofthe twentieth century, 155-94. In addition, helpfulis the work ofCharles Journet, What is Dogma?Translated by MarkPontifex, O.S.B. (New York: Hawthorn Books, 1964). 2 Nichols, From Newman to Congar, 169.
    [Show full text]
  • The Friendships of St. Thomas
    THE FRIENDSHIPS OF ST. THOMAS BRO. CYRIL DORE, 0 . P. T . Thomas Aquinas is a perfect type of that harmonious un­ ion of sanctity and learning which characterizes the great Doctors of the Church. A tender affection and a sympathetic understanding, which unites hearts entirely devoted to God, can be observed in all his friendships. While bearing himself affably towards all, the Angelic Doctor had but few intimate friends and these were persons of singular learning and holiness. From a consideration of these few, we can see the great influence for good which he exerted, the wide extent of his knowledge, and the deep penetration of his in­ tellectual prowess. They not only give us an insight into the reaction of personality on personality and the interplay of mind on mind, but in a very special manner, they exhibit the practical aspect of his writ­ ings. From the investigations of his biographers, the friendships of St. Thomas can be considered under four headings; namely, within his own Order, in the religious world, in the academic world, and in the political world. Amongst the members of the Dominican Order, the first friend mentioned is John of St. Julian. He is referred to as the old adviser and dear familiar friend of St. Thomas.1 This celebrated preacher directed the footsteps of the young Aquinas during the three years previous to his entrance into the Dominican Order. As a student at the University of Naples, the mind and imagination of Aquinas were captivated by the sanctity, the learning and the marvellous activ­ ity of the Dominicans.
    [Show full text]
  • The Alexandrian and the Cappadocian Fathers of the Church in the Writings of Thomas Aquinas
    The Alexandrian and the Cappadocian Fathers of the Church in the writings of Thomas Aquinas Los Padres alejandrinos y capadocios en los escritos de Tomás de Aquino Leo J. Elders s.v.d. Pontifical Academy of St. Thomas Aquinas Resumen: Santo Tomás considera que los escritos de los Padres están directamente relacionados con las Escrituras ya que fueron escritos bajo la influencia rectora del mismo Espíritu Santo. Existe, pues, una continuidad de pensamiento entre los Padres como re- presentantes de la autoridad de los Apóstoles y la Biblia. Por este motivo, sería bueno re- conocer cuán profundamente santo Tomás se inspira en el pensamiento de los Padres. En esta contribución presentaremos los temas principales dentro de los escritos de los Padres Alejandrinos y Capadocios que han influido en el propio pensamiento de santo Tomás. Palabras clave: Atanasio de Alejandría, Cirilo de Alejandría, Basilio Magno, Gre- gorio Nacianceno, Gregorio de Nisa, Tomás de Aquino. Abstract: St. Thomas considers the writings of the Fathers as directly related to Scrip- ture since these were composed under the guiding influence of the same Holy Spirit. There exists therefore a continuity of thought between the Fathers as representatives of the au- thority of the Apostles and the Bible.1 For this reason, one would do well to recognize how deeply St. Thomas draw upon the thought of the Fathers. In this contribution we will present the main themes within the writings of the Alexandrian and Cappadocian Fathers that have influenced St. Thomas’s own thought.2 Key words: Athanasius of Alexandria, Cyril of Alexandria, Basil the Great, Gregory of Nazianzus, Gregory of Nyssa, Thomas Aquinas.
    [Show full text]
  • The “Five Ways” of St. Thomas in Proving the Existence Of
    The Language of Analogy in the “Five Ways” of St. Thomas Aquinas San Beda College Moses Aaron T. Angeles, Ph.D. The Language of Analogy in the “Five Ways” Ways” “Five in the Analogy of Language The he “Five Ways” of St. Thomas in proving the existence of God is, needless to say, a most important and significant part in his magisterial Summa Theologiae. I can still recall what my professor then during my studies in Philosophy told us about it. He said that the “Five Ways” is the very hinge of the Summa.T His conclusion is logical – if the existence of God is not properly argued upon, then the whole discourse about the Divine Attributes, about Creation, about Divine Government, about Salvation and Redemption, about Grace and the Sacraments, all of these discourses will amount to nothing. This is the reason why ... St. Thomas himself placed his arguments about God’s existence immediately following his discussion about the nature and extent of Sacred Doctrine. In this paper, it is not my intent to discuss and argue about Aquinas’ proof regarding the existence of God. The topic is so ubiquitous that a plethora1 of studies about this abound in every book about Aquinas. My objective here is to look into the analogical nature of language concerning the Five Ways in proving the existence of God. Since there is an infinite distance between God and Man, between the Creator and the created, it necessitates that concepts involved in such a demonstration be analogical in character. Furthermore, it is also my intent here to show that the “Five Ways” is not only a monolithic intellectual articulation on the existence of God but also an argument that opens up the mind further to investigate a Being that is the object of faith.
    [Show full text]
  • Why Thomas Aquinas Rejects Infinite, Essentially Ordered, Causal Series
    There Must Be A First: Why Thomas Aquinas Rejects Infinite, Essentially Ordered, Causal Series Abstract Several of Thomas Aquinas’s proofs for the existence of God rely on the claim that causal series cannot proceed in infinitum. I argue that Aquinas has good reason to hold this claim given his conception of causation. Because he holds that effects are ontologically dependent on their causes he holds that the relevant causal series are wholly derivative: the later members of such series serve as causes only insofar as they have been caused by and are effects of earlier members. Because the intermediate causes in such series possess causal powers only by deriving them from all the preceding causes, they need a first and non-derivative cause to serve as the source of their causal powers. Keywords Thomas Aquinas; Five Ways; Causal Series; Infinite; Causal Regress; Causation; Ontological Dependence; God; Proofs This is an Author's Original/Accepted Manuscript of an article whose final and definitive form, the Version of Record, has been published in the British Journal for the History of Philosophy, September 5, 2013, copyright Taylor & Francis, available online at: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/09608788.2013.816934 A. Introduction Thomas Aquinas claims that certain sorts of causal series cannot proceed in infinitum. This claim is central to the first three of the famous five ways for demonstrating the existence of God that he presents in his Summa Theologiae (ST). Many interpreters have attacked both the claim and the considerations which Aquinas offers in support of it. Some interpreters, such as Bertrand Russell and John Hick, read Aquinas either as negligently dismissing the possibility of infinite series without a first member or as assuming a rejection of the infinite, based on certain (supposedly dubious) arguments that Aquinas puts forward elsewhere.1 Other interpreters, including distinguished scholars 1 Bertrand Russell writes that the Five Ways “depend on the supposed impossibility of a series having no first term.
    [Show full text]
  • Syntax and Readings According to the Stem Method
    Syntax and Readings According to The Stem Method Volume 2 Sophomore Language Fall 2016 38.1 Latin Nouns: Endings Nom Gen Dat Acc Abl Common Endings -s / |a -m Sg. -i/-s -i | / -e N: -m / | N: -m / | -i / -es -s Pl. -um -is / -bus -is / -bus N: -a N: -a Endings by Stem Type - Singular -a a- a-(i!)e a-(i!)e a-m a- (o!)u-s -o /o-i o-/i (o!)u-m o- N: (o!)u-m -e e-s e-i e-i e-m e- u-s u-i u-m -u u-s u- N: u- N:u-/i N: u- C-sb C-em C C-is C-i C-e N: C- N: C- i-s / /i-s /i-em /i-ec -i i-s /i-i N: /i/ (i!)e- N: /i/ (i!)e- N: i- Endings by Stem Type - Plural -a a-(i!)e a-rum /a-is a-s /a-is /o-i o-s -o o-rum /o-is /o-is N: /o-a N: /o-a -e e-/es e-rum e-bus e-s e-bus u-/es u-s -u u-um /u-ibus /u-ibus N: u-a N: u-a C-es C-es C C-um C-ibus C-ibus N: C-a N: C-a /i-es /i-es -i i-um i-bus i-bus N: i-a N: i-a aThe notation \-s / |" means that this form either takes the ending -s or remains as the bare stem.
    [Show full text]