Is There Theology in This Book?

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Is There Theology in This Book? Journal Code Article ID Dispatch: 14.08.17 CE: Bais, Irish Jill R I R T 1 3 0 3 6 No. of Pages: 10 ME: 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 REVIEW ARTICLE 8 9 10 11 Is there Theology in this Book? 12 13 Jonathan Teubner Q1 14 15 The Theology of Augustine’s Confessions, Paul Rigby, Cambridge University 16 Press, 2015 (ISBN 978-1107094925), xv + 340 pp., hb £67 17 Augustine’s Confessions: Philosophy in Autobiography, William E. Mann (ed.), 18 Oxford University Press, 2014 (ISBN 978-0199577552), xi +223 pp., hb £36 19 The Space of Time: A Sensualist Interpretation of Time in Augustine, 20 Confessions X to XII, David van Dusen, Brill, 2014 (ISBN 978-9004266865), xv + 21 358 pp., hb €149 22 23 Confessions: Books 1–8, Augustine of Hippo, trans. Carolyn J.-B. Hammond, Harvard University Press, 2014 (ISBN 978-0674996854), lxv + 413 pp., hb $26 24 25 Confessions: Books 9–13, Augustine of Hippo, trans. Carolyn J.-B. Hammond, 26 Harvard University Press, 2016, (ISBN 978-0674996939), xlii + 446 pp., hb $26 27 Confessions, Augustine of Hippo, trans. Sarah Ruden, The Modern Library, 2017 28 (ISBN 978-0812996562), xli + 484 pp., $28 29 30 31 Abstract 32 This review essay discusses three recent books on, and two new translations of, 33 Augustine’s Confessions. Long appreciated for its stylistic beauty and existential profun- 34 dity, the Confessions has recently become a resource for creative philosophical reflection in 35 both the analytic and continental traditions. However, there has not been a recent theolog- 36 ical treatment of the Confessions, a curious lacuna considering Augustine’s importance for 37 the history of Christian doctrine. This review probes three recent works – Paul Rigby’s The 38 Theology of Augustine’s Confessions, Gareth Matthews’ edited collection Augustine’s 39 Confessions: Philosophy in Autobiography, and David van Dusen’s The Space of Time: 40 A Sensualist Interpretation of Time in Augustine, Confessions X to XII – for how they 41 in turn attempt to address, avoid, and reject the theological subject matter within the text. 42 In each of them, a reader can discern an effort to translate Augustine’s language into a contemporary idiom that strays from traditional doctrinal location. Two new English Q2 43 translations by Carolyn J.-B. Hammond and Sarah Ruden demonstrate that conveying 44 the theology within the Confessions is a challenge even at the granular level of textual 45 46 47 Reviews in Religion & Theology, 24:4 (2017) 48 © 2017 John Wiley & Sons Ltd 1 Review Article 633 2 3 translation. This review concludes by considering how this theological lacuna might be 4 filled, considering the complexity of Augustine’s language, argument, and self-presentation 5 that has made this text more than simply another work of theology. 6 7 Key Words: Augustine of Hippo, Confessions, theological interpretation, analytic 8 philosophy, continental philosophy, Latin translation 9 10 There is a curious lacuna within the study of Augustine’s Confessions that I 11 only discovered the first time I attempted to teach this most perplexing 12 work: There is no recent theological treatment of the Confessions. Surely, this 13 work that, for many programs in Europe and North America, stands at 14 the beginning of introductory courses to Christian thought has many 15 theological treatments, and certainly, they are coming off the press at a 16 ‘galloping pace’. While I confess not being familiar with every recent 17 monograph published on the Confessions – whatever modern language 18 skills I do possess stop very firmly at the western bank of the Oder – I sus- Q3 19 pect that this lacuna has just as much to do with the uncertainty of what 20 counts as ‘theology’ today as it does with the interpretive complexities 21 of the Confessions. Therefore, when I say that there is no recent theological 22 treatment of Augustine’s Confessions, I have to admit that I’m not entirely 23 sure what would count as a possible candidate. But three recent books 24 and two translations present, explicitly and implicitly, a range of difficul- 25 ties for theological interpretations of the Confessions. In their own ways, 26 they each demonstrate that an interpretation that relies on traditional 27 theological categories – sin, grace, Christ, salvation, etc. – can fail to grasp 28 the philosophical sophistication, argumentative innovation, or existential 29 sincerity of the Confessions. 30 Augustine’s Confessions entered the postwar world as generally accept- 31 able reading in the cafés of la rive gauche. Yet, despite being the subject of 32 several learned studies in the nineteenth and early twentieth centuries, 33 the Confessions did not become a scholarly blockbuster until 1950, when 34 Pierre Courcelle published his Recherches sur les Confessions de Saint 35 Augustin. Courcelle’s initial study quickly spawned a deep and reflective 36 scholarly industry, even bringing about several controversies regarding 37 whether and to what Augustine actually converted in the pages of the 38 Confessions. These historical and literary studies were then surpassed by 39 far more fashionable Freudian, Foucaldian, and Ricoeurian readings of 40 the Confessions in the 1970s and 1980s. A turning point came with James 41 O’Donnell’s 1992 commentary, which, among other things, made much 42 of the European historical and philological scholarship on the Confessions 43 easily accessible to readers in the British Isles and North America. Then, 44 in the 1990s began the recovery of Augustine’s theological voice by Rowan 45 Williams and some of his doctoral students at Oxford, all of whom were 46 deeply indebted to French and German theological and historical scholar- 47 ship. The many shifts and scholarly reboots in the study of the Confessions, 48 © 2017 John Wiley & Sons Ltd 1 634 Review Article 2 3 of which these are but a few, can easily confuse readers who would rather 4 sit with Augustine’s literary masterpiece in a café than schlepp to a 5 modern research library. What has lurked below the surface of all of these 6 develops has been a concern that Augustine’s Confessions has grown stale 7 and alien to modern life. 8 To revivify the Confessions, Paul Rigby draws upon a mixture of 9 hermeneutics, literary theory, psychoanalysis, and critical philosophy in 10 his The Theology of Augustine’s Confessions. For Rigby, it is Paul Ricoeur 11 in particular whose philosophy ‘might provide the witness stand 12 on which [Rigby] might conduct a theological cross-examination of 13 Augustine’s testimony’ (p. 2). Rigby’s task is fitting for his imagined uni- 14 versity audience, for whom Kant, Hegel, Marx, Nietzsche, Freud, and 15 Heidegger still offer all of the excitement of a forbidden first date. These 16 philosophers have, however, become our secular divines. Inspiring grati- 17 tude, wonder, and awe, they model for us intellectual virtues proper to 18 the modern university. 19 In light of the subsequent developments in the study of the Confessions, 20 Rigby’s book is a curious throwback to certain concerns of the 1970s and 21 1980s. For his contemporary reader, the challenge that Rigby sees is that, 22 in the wake of Marx and Freud, we cannot but see false consciousness and 23 Oedipal complexes on every page. A deeper, more disconcerting concern 24 of Rigby’s seems to be that we have become too alienated from traditional 25 Christian piety to appreciate the rawness of Augustine’s Confessions. In 26 fact, Rigby takes Augustine and his Confessions to be emblematic of what 27 makes traditional theological commitment all but impossible for the 28 contemporary world: ‘The righteousness we encounter in Augustine is 29 strange, his counsel alien … The Enlightenment and its modern and late 30 modern heirs have interposed themselves between him and us, making 31 his voice alien but not exotic, stale as belonging to last year’s speech’ 32 (p. 2). This is not only a problem that Rigby imagines plagues the secular 33 inhabitants of today’s university but also the contemporary scholarly 34 Augustinian Christian, who has, on Rigby’s imagining, ‘grown weary 35 of antiquarian attachment to the lost Augustinian consensus and 36 the doomed attempt to answer the secular critique with a revamped 37 Augustinianism’ (p. 3). The task Rigby gives to himself is to find ways 38 to bring Augustine ‘closer, to bridge the gap, so that I could hear his 39 Confessions with the same shocking freshness it had for his contempo- 40 raries’ (p. 2). In other words, Rigby does not want an Augustinianism 41 but rather Augustine himself. Rigby aspires to be, for us Anglophones, 42 a Frédéric Boyer, but without the literary verve simply to re-write the 43 Confessions as a thirteen-book admission of guilt. 44 Rigby identifies five kinds of problems whereby ‘Augustine’s testimony 45 has become incredible for the modern reader’ (p. 4), structuring the eleven 46 chapters accordingly. If his problems are not exactly new (or surprising), 47 his performance lends each of them new drama. Rigby’s problems begin 48 © 2017 John Wiley & Sons Ltd 1 Review Article 635 2 3 with testimony itself, which is not a perception but a story or a narration of 4 an event. As with a witness in a courtroom, the testimony is liable to be 5 false and thus requires interrogation and ultimately judgment from the 6 listener as to whether it is reliable. The judge then needs to assess not only 7 the content of the testimony but the witness’ reliability. In Chapter 2, we 8 encounter Rigby exposing, via Freudian archeology and Hegel’s philoso- 9 phy of will, the problem of Augustine’s view of God as a rewarding and 10 punishing father God with its penal view of salvation.
Recommended publications
  • The Problem of Evil in Augustine's Confessions
    University of South Florida Scholar Commons Graduate Theses and Dissertations Graduate School 2011 The rP oblem of Evil in Augustine's Confessions Edward Matusek University of South Florida, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarcommons.usf.edu/etd Part of the American Studies Commons, and the Philosophy Commons Scholar Commons Citation Matusek, Edward, "The rP oblem of Evil in Augustine's Confessions" (2011). Graduate Theses and Dissertations. http://scholarcommons.usf.edu/etd/3733 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at Scholar Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Graduate Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Scholar Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. The Problem of Evil in Augustine’s Confessions by Edward A. Matusek A dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy College of Arts and Sciences University of South Florida Major Professor: Thomas Williams, Ph.D. Roger Ariew, Ph.D. Joanne Waugh, Ph.D. Charles B. Guignon, Ph.D. Date of Approval: November 14, 2011 Keywords: theodicy, privation, metaphysical evil, Manichaeism, Neo-Platonism Copyright © 2011, Edward A. Matusek i TABLE OF CONTENTS Abstract iii Chapter One: Introduction to Augustine’s Confessions and the Present Study 1 Purpose and Background of the Study 2 Literary and Historical Considerations of Confessions 4 Relevance of the Study for Various
    [Show full text]
  • History of Philosophy Outlines from Wheaton College (IL)
    Property of Wheaton College. HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY 311 Arthur F. Holmes Office: Blanch ard E4 83 Fall, 1992 Ext. 5887 Texts W. Kaufman, Philosophical Classics (Prentice-Hall, 2nd ed., 1968) Vol. I Thales to Occam Vol. II Bacon to Kant S. Stumpf, Socrates to Sartre (McGraW Hill, 3rd ed., 1982, or 4th ed., 1988) For further reading see: F. Copleston, A History of Philosophy. A multi-volume set in the library, also in paperback in the bookstore. W. K. C. Guthrie, A History of Greek Philosophy Diogenes Allen, Philosophy for Understanding Theology A. H. Armstrong & R. A. Markus, Christian Faith and Greek Philosophy A. H. Armstrong (ed.), Cambridge History of Later Greek and Early Medieval Philosophy Encyclopedia of Philosophy Objectives 1. To survey the history of Western philosophy with emphasis on major men and problems, developing themes and traditions and the influence of Christianity. 2. To uncover historical connections betWeen philosophy and science, the arts, and theology. 3. To make this heritage of great minds part of one’s own thinking. 4. To develop competence in reading philosophy, to lay a foundation for understanding contemporary thought, and to prepare for more critical and constructive work. Procedure 1. The primary sources are of major importance, and you will learn to read and understand them for yourself. Outline them as you read: they provide depth of insight and involve you in dialogue with the philosophers themselves. Ask first, What does he say? The, how does this relate to What else he says, and to what his predecessors said? Then, appraise his assumptions and arguments.
    [Show full text]
  • Post-Continental Philosophy: Its Definition, Contours, and Fundamental Sources
    Post-continental Philosophy: Its Definition, Contours, and Fundamental Sources NELSON MALDONADO-TORRES It is no accident that the global geographical framework in use today is essentially a cartographic celebration of European power. After centuries of imperialism, the presumptions of a worldview of a once-dominant metropole has become part of the intellectual furniture of the world…. Metageography matters, and the attempt to engage it critically has only begun. Martin W. Lewis and Kären W. Wigen, The Myth of Continents.1 or several decades now the contours of legitimate philosophy have been drawn by advocates of F so-called analytic and continental philosophies. Analytic philosophy is often referred to as a style of thinking centered on the question of whether something is true, rather than, as continental philosophy, on the multiple factors that constitute meaning.2 Analytic philosophy is also said to be closer to the sciences, while continental philosophy has more affinity with the humanities.3 One of the reasons for this lies in that while analytic philosophy tends to dismiss history from its reflections, continental philosophy typically emphasizes the relevance of time, tradition, lived experience, and/or social context. Fortunately, this situation is slowly but gradually changing today. A variety of intellectuals are defying the rigid boundaries of these fields. Some of the most notable are Afro- American, Afro-Caribbean, and Latina/o scholars using the arsenal of these bodies of thought to analyze and interpret problems related to colonialism, racism, and sexism in the contemporary world.4 These challenges demand a critical analysis of the possibilities and limits of change within the main coordinates of these different styles or forms of philosophizing.
    [Show full text]
  • Book Review: Gadamer's Ethics of Play: Hermeneutics and the Other
    Eastern Illinois University The Keep Faculty Research and Creative Activity Kinesiology, Sport & Recreation January 2013 Book Review: Gadamer’s Ethics of Play: Hermeneutics and the Other Chad R. Carlson Eastern Illinois University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://thekeep.eiu.edu/kss_fac Part of the Kinesiology Commons Recommended Citation Carlson, Chad R., "Book Review: Gadamer’s Ethics of Play: Hermeneutics and the Other" (2013). Faculty Research and Creative Activity. 19. https://thekeep.eiu.edu/kss_fac/19 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Kinesiology, Sport & Recreation at The Keep. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Research and Creative Activity by an authorized administrator of The Keep. For more information, please contact [email protected]. BOOK REVIEW Chad Carlson Eastern Illinois University Gadamer’s ethics of play: Hermeneutics and the other, by Monica Vilhauer, Lanham, MD, Lexington Books, 2010, 166 pp., £37 (hardback), ISBN 978-0739139141 As a naıve graduate student, I remember signing up for a course in the Philosophy Department entitled, ‘Art and Truth’. Although I was studying sport and play in a different department, I was intrigued by the title – art seemed closely related to play and sport in the landscape of human experiences. Further, the course was offered at a convenient time and it fulfilled a deficiency I had toward graduation. Unfortunately, I had no idea what I was getting into. The course readings, which included Martin Heidegger, Friedrich Nietzsche, Maurice Merleau- Ponty, Jacques Derrida, Jurgen Habermas, and, most prominently, Hans-Georg Gadamer, seemed so dense that they necessitated long hours of introduction and prior training that I did not have.
    [Show full text]
  • Analytic and Continental Philosophy, Science, and Global Philosophy
    CHAPTER SIX ANALYTIC AND CONTINENTAL PHILOSOPHY, SCIENCE, AND GLOBAL PHILOSOPHY Richard Tieszen There are many references in the philosophical literature to the division between analytic and Continental philosophy but it is not easy to provide a simple formulation of what it is that distinguishes these approaches to or styles of philosophy. There have been significant subdivisions within what has been considered analytic philosophy, such as that between for- mal philosophy, ordinary language philosophy, and conceptual analysis, and there have of course also been many variations within the general grouping of Continental philosophy, extending from eidetic phenomenol- ogy, existential phenomenology, existentialism, structuralism and semiot- ics, and neo-Freudian analysis to deconstruction. Philosophers who have written about the split between the analytic and Continental traditions have often focused on the work of particular figures who seem to embody much of what is involved in the division. In The Origins of Analytic Philoso- phy, for example, Michael Dummett looks to Frege and Husserl and holds that Frege took a turn into the philosophy of language but that Husserl did not, thus initiating a split in modern philosophy. Michael Friedman, to take another example, writes a book entitled A Parting of the Ways in which he focuses on Carnap, Cassirer, and Heidegger. Over the years I have heard or read a host of characterizations of the two traditions, such as the following: Analytic philosophy strives for clarity, exactness, precision and Continental philosophy does not. Con- tinental philosophy instead tends toward the use of poetic or dramatic language. The methodology of analytic philosophy is argumentation while Continental philosophy, if it has a methodology at all, is concerned with description or narrative or literary quality.
    [Show full text]
  • Malebranche's Augustinianism and the Mind's Perfection
    University of Pennsylvania ScholarlyCommons Publicly Accessible Penn Dissertations Spring 2010 Malebranche's Augustinianism and the Mind's Perfection Jason Skirry University of Pennsylvania, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations Part of the History of Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Skirry, Jason, "Malebranche's Augustinianism and the Mind's Perfection" (2010). Publicly Accessible Penn Dissertations. 179. https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations/179 This paper is posted at ScholarlyCommons. https://repository.upenn.edu/edissertations/179 For more information, please contact [email protected]. Malebranche's Augustinianism and the Mind's Perfection Abstract This dissertation presents a unified interpretation of Malebranche’s philosophical system that is based on his Augustinian theory of the mind’s perfection, which consists in maximizing the mind’s ability to successfully access, comprehend, and follow God’s Order through practices that purify and cognitively enhance the mind’s attention. I argue that the mind’s perfection figures centrally in Malebranche’s philosophy and is the main hub that connects and reconciles the three fundamental principles of his system, namely, his occasionalism, divine illumination, and freedom. To demonstrate this, I first present, in chapter one, Malebranche’s philosophy within the historical and intellectual context of his membership in the French Oratory, arguing that the Oratory’s particular brand of Augustinianism, initiated by Cardinal Bérulle and propagated by Oratorians such as Andre Martin, is at the core of his philosophy and informs his theory of perfection. Next, in chapter two, I explicate Augustine’s own theory of perfection in order to provide an outline, and a basis of comparison, for Malebranche’s own theory of perfection.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter One Transcendentalism and the Aesthetic Critique Of
    Chapter One Transcendentalism and the Aesthetic Critique of Modernity Thinking of the aesthetic as both potentially ideological and potentially utopian allows us to understand the social implications of modern aes- thetics. The aesthetic experience can serve to evade questions of justice and equality as much as it offers the opportunity for a vision of freedom. If the Transcendentalists stand at the end of a Romantic tradition which has always been aware of the utopian dimension of the aesthetic, why should they have cherished the consolation the aesthetic experience of- fers while at the same time forfeiting its critical implications, which have been so important for the British and the early German Romantics? Is the American variety of Romanticism really much more submissive than European Romanticism with all its revolutionary fervor? Is it really true that “the writing of the Transcendentalists, and all those we may wish to consider as Romantics, did not have this revolutionary social dimension,” as Tony Tanner has suggested (1987, 38)? The Transcendentalists were critical of established religious dogma and received social conventions – so why should their aesthetics be apolitical or even adapt to dominant ideologies? In fact, the Transcendentalists were well aware of the philo- sophical and social radicalism of the aesthetic – which, however, is not to say that all of them wholeheartedly embraced it. While the Transcendentalists’ American background (New England’s Puritan legacy and the Unitarian church from which they emerged) is crucial for an understanding of their social, religious, and philosophical thought, it is worth casting an eye across the ocean to understand their concept of beauty since the Transcendentalists were also heir to a long- standing tradition of transatlantic Romanticism which addressed the re- lationship between aesthetic experience, utopia, and social criticism.
    [Show full text]
  • Hermeneutical Phenomenology and the Philosophy of Science Patrick A
    Fordham University Masthead Logo DigitalResearch@Fordham Hermeneutic and Phenomenological Philosophies Research Resources of Science 1991 Hermeneutical Phenomenology and the Philosophy of Science Patrick A. Heelan Georgetown University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://fordham.bepress.com/phil_research Part of the Continental Philosophy Commons, and the Philosophy of Science Commons Recommended Citation Heelan, Patrick A., "Hermeneutical Phenomenology and the Philosophy of Science" (1991). Research Resources. 11. https://fordham.bepress.com/phil_research/11 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Hermeneutic and Phenomenological Philosophies of Science at DigitalResearch@Fordham. It has been accepted for inclusion in Research Resources by an authorized administrator of DigitalResearch@Fordham. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Hermeneutical Phenomenology and the Philosophy of Science Heelan, Patrick, “Hermeneutical Phenomenology and the Philosophy of Science,” in Silverman, Hugh (ed.), Gadamer and Hermeneutics: Science, Culture, and Literature, (New York: Routledge, 1991). pp. 213-228 HERMENEUTICAL PHENOMENOLOGY AND THE PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE PATRICK A. HEELAN PART I: Continental and Analytic Philosophy of Science Compared The two most characteristic interests of continental philosophy1 are (1) its preoccupation with the problem of the “constitution” of knowledge, and (2) the effect of the historical and cultural world context of science on the “social constitution” of scientific knowledge. Such constitution is “hermeneutical,” when it essentially involves language, natural and artifactual symbols, and historical communities of interpreters. Continental philosophy from the start sees science as an institution in a cultural, historical, and hermeneutical setting. The domain of its discourse is values, subjectivity, Life Worlds, history, and society, as these affect the constitution of scientific knowledge.
    [Show full text]
  • Theory of Knowledge in Britain from 1860 to 1950
    Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication Volume 4 200 YEARS OF ANALYTICAL PHILOSOPHY Article 5 2008 Theory Of Knowledge In Britain From 1860 To 1950 Mathieu Marion Université du Quéebec à Montréal, CA Follow this and additional works at: https://newprairiepress.org/biyclc This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 4.0 License. Recommended Citation Marion, Mathieu (2008) "Theory Of Knowledge In Britain From 1860 To 1950," Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication: Vol. 4. https://doi.org/10.4148/biyclc.v4i0.129 This Proceeding of the Symposium for Cognition, Logic and Communication is brought to you for free and open access by the Conferences at New Prairie Press. It has been accepted for inclusion in Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication by an authorized administrator of New Prairie Press. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Theory of Knowledge in Britain from 1860 to 1950 2 The Baltic International Yearbook of better understood as an attempt at foisting on it readers a particular Cognition, Logic and Communication set of misconceptions. To see this, one needs only to consider the title, which is plainly misleading. The Oxford English Dictionary gives as one August 2009 Volume 4: 200 Years of Analytical Philosophy of the possible meanings of the word ‘revolution’: pages 1-34 DOI: 10.4148/biyclc.v4i0.129 The complete overthrow of an established government or social order by those previously subject to it; an instance of MATHIEU MARION this; a forcible substitution of a new form of government.
    [Show full text]
  • Gareth B. Matthews Curriculum Vitae1
    1 Gareth B. Matthews curriculum vitae1 Born 8 July 1929; married; three children; six grandchildren. Died 17 April 2011; survived by wife, three children, and seven grandchildren. Education Franklin College (Indiana) 1947-51 A.B. (1951) Middlebury German School Summer 1950 Harvard University 1951-52 A.M. (1952) University of Tübingen Summer 1952 Free University of Berlin 1952-53 Harvard University 1957-60 Ph.D. (1961) Military Service United States Naval Reserve Active duty: 1954-57, served to rank of (full) Lieutenant Academic Appointments University of Virginia Assistant Professor 1960-61 University of Minnesota Assistant Professor 1961-65 Associate Professor 1965-69 University of Massachusetts Professor 1969-2005 Professor emeritus 2005-2011 Visiting Professorships Amherst College (1973, 1998, 2006, 2007) Brown University (1988, 2005) University of Calgary Summer School (1978, 1987) Harvard Summer School (1968, 1976) University of Minnesota (1981) Mount Holyoke College (1977, 1991, 2006) Smith College (1972, 1974, 1988, 2008) Tufts University (2008) Fellowships and Scholarships Harvard University Graduate School Scholarship (1951-52) George Santayana Postdoctoral Fellowship (1967-68) Rotary Foundation Fellowship (1952-53) National Endowment for the Humanities Research Fellowships (1982-83; 1989-90) Institute for Advanced Study Member (January – June, 1986 for project: Augustine and Descartes: philosophy from a first-person perspective) Presentations A. To the American Philosophical Association 2 Eastern Division: 1965, 1970, 1972, 1974, 1976, 1980, 1984, 1994, 1995, 1996, 1997, 1998, 2001, 2005 Central Division: 1962, 1965, 1967, 1970, 1972, 1973, 1980, 1982, 1986, 1987, 1989, 1997, 1998, 2001, 2002 Pacific Division: 1974, 1979, 1987, 1988, 1989, 1992, 1994, 1996, 1997, 1998, 1999, 2000, 2003, 2004 B.
    [Show full text]
  • Immanuel Kant and the Development of Modern Psychology David E
    University of Richmond UR Scholarship Repository Psychology Faculty Publications Psychology 1982 Immanuel Kant and the Development of Modern Psychology David E. Leary University of Richmond, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.richmond.edu/psychology-faculty- publications Part of the Theory and Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Leary, David E. "Immanuel Kant and the Development of Modern Psychology." In The Problematic Science: Psychology in Nineteenth- Century Thought, edited by William Ray Woodward and Mitchell G. Ash, 17-42. New York, NY: Praeger, 1982. This Book Chapter is brought to you for free and open access by the Psychology at UR Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Psychology Faculty Publications by an authorized administrator of UR Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. 1 Immanuel Kant and the Development of Modern Psychology David E. Leary Few thinkers in the history of Western civilization have had as broad and lasting an impact as Immanuel Kant (1724-1804). This "Sage of Konigsberg" spent his entire life within the confines of East Prussia, but his thoughts traveled freely across Europe and, in time, to America, where their effects are still apparent. An untold number of analyses and commentaries have established Kant as a preeminent epistemologist, philosopher of science, moral philosopher, aestheti­ cian, and metaphysician. He is even recognized as a natural historian and cosmologist: the author of the so-called Kant-Laplace hypothesis regarding the origin of the universe. He is less often credited as a "psychologist," "anthropologist," or "philosopher of mind," to Work on this essay was supported by the National Science Foundation (Grant No.
    [Show full text]
  • John D. Caputo CURRICULUM VITAE
    John D. Caputo CURRICULUM VITAE EMPLOYMENT: Thomas J. Watson Professor of Religion and Humanities, Syracuse University, 2004– David R. Cook Professor Emeritus of Philosophy, Villanova University, 2004– David R. Cook Professor of Philosophy, Villanova University, 1993-2004 Assistant Professor, Associate Professor, Professor, Villanova University, 1968-2004 Visiting Professor, New School for Social Research, Spring, 1994 Distinguished Adjunct Professor, Fordham University Graduate Program, 1985-88 Visiting Professor, Fordham University, Fall, 1980 Visiting Professor, Duquesne University, Fall, 1978 Instructor, St. Joseph's University (Philadelphia, 1965-68) EDUCATION: Ph.D., 1968, Bryn Mawr College M.A., 1964, Villanova University B.A., 1962, La Salle University AWARDS Winner of the ForeWord Magazine Best Philosophy Book of 2007 award for What Would Jesus Deconstruct? 2008 Loyola Medal (Seattle University), 2007 American Academy of Religion Book Award for Excellence in Studies in Religion, “Constructive-Reflective Studies,” for The Weakness of God: A Theology of the Event (Indiana UP, 2007). 2004, Appointed Thomas J. Watson Professor of Religion and Humanities, Syracuse University; David R. Cook Professor Emeritus, Villanova University 1998, Choice Magazine, “Outstanding Academic Book Award” for Deconstruction in a Nutshell (Fordham UP, 1997) 1992, Appointed David R. Cook Professor of Philosophy 1991-92, National Endowment for the Humanities, Fellowship for College Teachers 1989, Phi Beta Kappa, Honorary Member, Villanova Chapter 1985, National Endowment for the Humanities, Summer Stipend 1983-84, American Council of Learned Societies, Fellowship 1982, Outstanding Faculty Scholar Award (V.U.) 1982, Summer Research Grant (V.U.) 1981, Distinguished Alumnus, V.U. Graduate School 1979-80, Phi Kappa Phi Honorary Society, Villanova University Chapter, President 1972, American Council of Learned Societies, Grant-in-aid (Summer grant) OFFICES Member, Book Awards Committee, American Academy of Religion, 2008-2009.
    [Show full text]