The Origins of Freedom of Speech and Press David S

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Origins of Freedom of Speech and Press David S Maryland Law Review Volume 42 | Issue 3 Article 3 The Origins of Freedom of Speech and Press David S. Bogen Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.law.umaryland.edu/mlr Part of the First Amendment Commons Recommended Citation David S. Bogen, The Origins of Freedom of Speech and Press, 42 Md. L. Rev. 429 (1983) Available at: http://digitalcommons.law.umaryland.edu/mlr/vol42/iss3/3 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Academic Journals at DigitalCommons@UM Carey Law. It has been accepted for inclusion in Maryland Law Review by an authorized administrator of DigitalCommons@UM Carey Law. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Maryland Law Review VOLUME 42 1983 NUMBER 3 © Copyright Maryland Law Review, Inc. 1983 THE ORIGINS OF FREEDOM OF SPEECH AND PRESS DAVID S. BOGEN* The Virginia Declarationof Rights containedthe first con- stitutional guarantee offreedom of the press. Edmund Ran- dolph, a member of the drafting committee, statedit was one of "the fruits of genuine democracy and historical experience." ' The organic metaphor is apt, but two centuries later thefruit is still maturing. The adoption of a constitutional provision is a significant event. It exerts a magnetic attraction. In the perennial debate over the nature and effect of framers' intention on constitutional interpretation, discus- sion tends to commence with the statements made during the drafting and ratification process. Some scholars argue that adoption crystallizes a principle.2 They would freeze the meaning at that point in time to prevent modem judges from imposing their personal values. For these writers, the adoption of a provision marks the end to the development of a principle.3 Others seem to find that the adoption of a provision marks the beginning of a process to give it meaning. They reject limit- ing the inquiry to the applications that the drafters would make on a B.A. 1962, LL.B. 1965, Harvard University; LL.M. 1967, New York University; Pro- fessor of Law, University of Maryland School of Law. 1. Randolph, Essay on the Revolutionary History of Virginia, 44 VA. MAG. OF HIST. & BIoGRAPHY 43, 46 (1936). 2. Eg., R. BERGER, GOVERNMENT BY JUDICIARY: THE TRANSFORMATION OF THE FOURTEENTH AMENDMENT 288-99 (1977); Berger, Paul Brest's Brieffor an ImperialJudici- ary, 40 MD. L. REV. 1, 2-7, 26-31 (1981). 3. Berger acknowledges that some provisions may be too murky for a defined historical content and new circumstances may call for applications of the principle to unanticipated contexts. Thus, later applications inevitably "develop" the principle. He insists, however, that the Court is bound to the specific value judgments made by the framers and the specific applications that they would have made of their language. In that sense, the adoption marks the end of the evolution of the principle. R. BEROER, supra note 2, at 288-99. MARYLAND LAW REVIEW [VOL. 42 wide variety of grounds: Original intent is impossible to determine,4 the framers intended later generations to infuse the language with sub- sequently acquired values,5 the original conception is too narrow to ful- fill the proper function of a constitution in our society,6 or the judiciary is the best organ to state and uphold evolving principles.7 There is much to be said (and much of it has been) on behalf of all of these views, but not enough attention has been paid to the proposi- tion that the adoption of a constitutional provision is a midpoint in the development of principles of government. Freezing the meaning of a principle or freeing it from the context in which it arose are equally false to history. When a principle becomes a part of the formal consti- tution, it introduces the Court to a new role in the development pro- cess, but the process is a continuing one. The confluence of ideas and events that led to the declaration of a principle are important influences in the direction it takes, but the very nature of the development of prin- ciples suggests that they should not completely control the subsequent application. This article explores one provision of the constitution in this light: the guarantee of freedom of speech and of the press. The meaning of the words "freedom of speech and of the press" for those who adopted the first amendment was the product of many strands of thought woven over many centuries and across an ocean. Some of these strands became separate constitutional guarantees while others were mentioned either directly or indirectly in the adoption pro- cess. Among the most prominent of these sources for understanding the guarantee of the first amendment are the parliamentary privilege of freedom of debate, the abolition of prior censorship in England, the 4. Eg., Brest, The Misconceived Questfor the Original Understanding, 60 B.U. L. REV. 204 (1980); Bridwell, Book Review, 1978 DUKE L. J. 907. See Schauer, An Essay on Consti- tutional Language, 29 U.C.L.A. L. REv. 797, 804-12 (1982). 5. Eg., Bickel, The Original Understanding and the Segregation Decision, 69 HARV. L. REv. 1 (1955); L. TRIBE, AMERICAN CONSTITUTIONAL LAW iii (1978); R. DWORKIN, TAKING RIGHTS SERIOUSLY 133 (1980). 6. Eg., Sandalow, ConstitutionalInterpretation, 79 MICH. L. REv. 1033 (1981); Brest, supra note 4. 7. Eg., Perry, NoninterpreiveReview in Human Rights Cases: A FunctionalJust#Fcation, 56 N.Y.U. L. Rv. 278 (1981). 8. Some events, such as the Zenger trial and Wilkes' expulsion from Parliament, are important contributions to the background of the first amendment. They prove difficult to analyze, however, because each involves an individual making statements with which the successful American revolutionists agreed. Thus, support for Zenger and Wilkes is not con- clusive evidence of any particular principle of free speech beyond the unhelpful proposition that "persons should be able to say things with which I agree." This ambiguity in events leads to a focus on the statements of principle rather than specific events. If an event gives rise to universal acceptance of a principle, that principle should be evidenced by incorpora- tion in a basic document or discussion. 19831 FREEDOM OF SPEECH AND PRESS ORIGINS letters of "Cato," the theory of natural rights, the growth of religious toleration, and the limited function of a national government in a fed- eral system. Each thread in this constitutional tapestry has its own history. Often a thread originated in controversies only tangentially related to freedom of speech. The path followed, however, led from expedient to principle, and the interrelationship of the principles that developed formed the design of the first amendment. A closer look at each strand reveals the dynamics of the process and suggests that the first amend- ment itself is capable of growth and development. I. PARLIAMENTARY PRIVILEGE Freedom of speech and debate in Congress shall not be im- peached or questioned in any court or place out of Congress 9 Articles of Confederation A. The Development of ParliamentaryPrivilege Before the American Revolution the only mention of "freedom of speech" in the basic charter of any colony referred to the rights of legis- lators during sessions of the legislature. The meaning given the term in this limited context influenced its meaning when applied to the whole society. The development of parliamentary privilege demonstrates a recognition in early America of the relationship between speech and the political process and of the importance of the procedures for en- forcing limits on speech as an aspect of securing its freedom. The privilege evolved during the struggle of the British Parliament to gain more authority at the expense of the Crown. Parliament had begun as a convocation by the King of the most influential individuals in the realm to advise him on the governance of the country. In 1215 the powerful barons went beyond advising and secured from King John in the Magna Carta a promise not to levy certain taxes upon them without their assembled consent.' 0 As the social and economic struc- ture of society changed, the support of a broader group was enlisted, and in 1295 representatives from the hundreds (districts within a county) were added to the lords spiritual and temporal.I Initially, the representatives had power only in matters of taxation. The King and barons together promulgated general laws of major importance; and 9. ARTICLES OF CONFEDERATION art. 5, cl. 5. 10. F. MAITLAND, THE CONSTITUTIONAL HISTORY OF ENGLAND 64 (1963). 11. Id at 74-75. MARYLAND LAW REVIEW [VOL. 42 minor, temporary, or special laws were the province of the King alone.' 2 During the next century the representatives or Commons be- came the appropriate body to initiate action by petitioning the King. 3 Fearful of royal wrath due to these petitions, the Speaker of the House of Commons prefaced his term in office with a plea for forgiveness, protesting that if he said anything in the performance of his duties that displeased the King, it was unintentional.14 Gradually during the next century, the form of the petitions changed. The general request that the King make a law to resolve a problem became a bill whose form could not be altered by the Crown and which became law if the King consented. '-5 The shift to the House of Commons of responsibility for the text of laws caused its members to recognize a need for debate and discussion. Participants in a drafting process readily appreciate the assistance of criticism and the need for an atmosphere that encourages it. Debate within the House became accepted practice and the Speaker dropped the plea for forgiveness. Although the strongest discussions may have arisen over measures initiated wholly within the House of Commons, debate also included limited criticism of measures proposed by the King or his ministers.
Recommended publications
  • Ideological Contributions of Celtic Freedom and Individualism to Human Rights
    chapter 4 Ideological Contributions of Celtic Freedom and Individualism to Human Rights This chapter emphasizes the importance of the often-overlooked contribu- tions of indigenous European cultures to the development of human rights. Attention is given to the ancient Celtic culture, the ideas of Celtic freedom and individualism, the distinctive role of the Scottish theologian, John Dunn Scotus and the Scottish Arbroath Declaration of Freedom (1320).1 It is from the Scottish Enlightenment and its subsequent influence on the late 18th century revolutions that we see an affirmative declaration of the Rights of Man, which is a precursor to the development of modern human rights. The importance of the Celtic-Irish-Scottish contribution to human rights is that it was the foun- dation for individual liberty and dignity in Western civilization. Indigenous Celtic culture staked an original and critical claim to the ideal of universal hu- man dignity. This is an important insight because it broadens the ideals that promote human rights, including within them those ideals of the indigenous cultures of the world, whose voices are oftentimes forgotten. It strengthens the universality of human rights. i The Intellectual and Philosophical Origins of International Law and Human Rights The intellectual and philosophical origins of human rights rhetoric and law, democracy, freedom and ideas supporting “consent of the governed” are in- tertwined in this composite explanation that attempts to explain all of these themes with the historical themes of Roman natural law, Athenian democracy and later the modern political philosophy of John Locke and his followers. The absence of a medieval connection between the alleged ancient Roman and Greek sources and the modern developments of human rights indicates that this perspective is faulty.
    [Show full text]
  • Freedom, Democracy and Economic Welfare
    copyright The Fraser Institute copyright The Fraser Institute LORD BAUER RAMON DIAZ MILTON FRIEDMAN RAYMOND D GASTIL TIBOR R MACHAN DOUGLASS NORTH SVETOZAR PEJOVICH ALVIN RABUSHKA INGEMAR STAHL LINDSAY M WRIGHT PROCEEDINGS OF AN INTERNATIONAL EDITED BY MICHAEL A WALKER SYMPOSIUM copyright The Fraser Institute Proceedings of an International Symposium on Economic, Political, and Civil Freedom, held October 5-8, 1986 in Napa Valley, California. This event is part of the programme of Liberty Fund Inc., under the direction of its President, Dr W. W. Hill. This Symposium was managed by The Fraser Institute and organized by its Director, Dr. Michael A. Walker. Canadian Cataloguing in Publication Data Main entry under title: Freedom, democracy and economic welfare Symposium held Oct 5-8, 1986 in Napa Valley, Calif. Includes bibliographical references. ISBN 0-88975-116-1 1.Capitalism – Congresses. 2. Liberty – Congresses. 3. Economics – Political aspects – Congresses. 4. Economics – Philosophy – Congresses. I. Walker, Michael 1945 – II.Fraser Institute (Vancouver, BC.) HB501.F74 1988 330.12’2 C88-091102-6 Copyright 1988 by the Fraser Institute. All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced in any manner whatsoever without written permission except in the case of brief quotations embodied in critical arti- cles and reviews. Printed in Canada copyright The Fraser Institute CONTENTS Participants / vii Preface, Michael A. Walker / ix PART ONE POLITICAL, ECONOMIC AND CIVIL FREEDOMS: A CONCEPTUAL, HISTORICAL AND STATISTICAL OVERVIEW 1 INSTITUTIONS, ECONOMIC GROWTH AND FREEDOM: AN HISTORICAL INTRODUCTION, Douglass C. North / 3 Discussion / 26 2 CAPITALISM AND FREEDOM, Milton Friedman / 47 Discussion / 59 3 THE STATE OF THE WORLD POLITICAL AND ECONOMIC FREEDOM, Raymond D.
    [Show full text]
  • Unit 24 Individualism and Communitarianism
    Gandhism (Dharma, UNIT 24 INDIVIDUALISM AND Swaraj, Sarvodaya and COMMUNITARIANISM Satyagraha) Structure 24.0 Objectives 24.1 Introduction 24.1.1 Individualist Versus Communitarian Position 24.1.2 Relevance in the Indian Context 24.2 Meaning and Development of Individualism 24.2.1 Atomism and Methodological Individualism 24.2.2 Views of Contractualists Including John Rawls 24.2.3 Views of Utilitarians 24.3 The Individualist Conception of the Self 24.4 The Individualist Theory of the Nature and Functions of the State 24.4.1 Functions of State and Government 24.5 Communitarianism: An Introduction 24.6 The Communitarian Critique of the Individualist Conception of the Self 24.6.1 Two Main Limitations of Individualism 24.7 The Communitarian Critique of the Idea of State Neutrality 24.8 Let Us Sum Up 24.9 Some Useful References 24.10 Answers to Check Your Progress Exercises 24.0 OBJECTIVES Our objective in this unit is to understand and assess one of the major ongoing debates in contemporary political theory; namely, the debate between liberal individualism and communitarianism. After studying this unit, you should be able to: • Understand the individualistic theory of the nature and functions of state; • Describe and assess the communitarian critique of liberal individualism; • Compare the major theoretical positions of individualism and communitarianism; and • Understand the relevance of this debate to contemporary political theory and practice. 24.1 INTRODUCTION In this unit, you will be introduced to one of the central debates in contemporary political theory, namely, the debate between liberal individualism and communitarianism. The debate between individualism and communitarianism developed and became central to political theory during the 1980s with the publication of Michael Sandel’s Liberalism and the Limits of Justice (1982).
    [Show full text]
  • The Right to Freedom of Thought, Conscience and Religion Or Belief
    Level 1, 4 Campion St 594 St Kilda Rd DEAKIN ACT 2600 MELBOURNE VIC 3004 T 02 6259 0431 T 02 6171 7446 E [email protected] E [email protected] 14 February 2018 The Expert Panel on Religious Freedom C/o Department of the Prime Minister and Cabinet By email: [email protected] RE: Submission to the Commonwealth Expert Panel on Religious Freedom 1. The Human Rights Law Alliance and the Australian Christian Lobby welcome this opportunity to make a submission to the Inquiry into the Status of the Human Right to Freedom of Religion or Belief. 2. The Human Rights Law Alliance implements legal strategies to protect and promote fundamental human rights. It does this by resourcing legal cases with funding and expertise to create rights-protecting legal precedents. The Alliance is especially concerned to protect and promote the right to freedom of thought, conscience and religion or belief. In the past 24 months, the Alliance has aided more than 30 legal cases, and allied lawyers appeared in State Tribunals and Magistrates, District and Supreme Courts as well as the Federal Court. 3. With more than 100,000 supporters, ACL facilitates professional engagement and dialogue between the Christian constituency and government, allowing the voice of Christians to be heard in the public square. ACL is neither party partisan or denominationally aligned. ACL representatives bring a Christian perspective to policy makers in Federal, State and Territory parliaments. 4. This submission focusses on the intersection between freedom of religion and other human rights first in international law, second in Australian law, and third in the lived experience of Australians.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 4 Freedom and Progress
    Chapter 4 Freedom and Progress The best road to progress is freedom’s road. John F. Kennedy The only freedom which deserves the name, is that of pursuing our own good in our own way, so long as we do not attempt to deprive others of theirs, or impeded their efforts to obtain it. John Stuart Mill To cull the inestimable benefits assured by freedom of the press, it is necessary to put up with the inevitable evils springing therefrom. Alexis de Tocqueville Freedom is necessary to generate progress; people also value freedom as an important component of progress. This chapter will contend that both propositions are correct. Without liberty, there will be little or no progress; most people will consider an expansion in freedom as progress. Neither proposition would win universal acceptance. Some would argue that a totalitarian state can marshal the resources to generate economic growth. Many will contend that too much liberty induces libertine behavior and is destructive of society, peace, and the family. For better or worse, the record shows that freedom has increased throughout the world over the last few centuries and especially over the last few decades. There are of course many examples of non-free, totalitarian, ruthless government on the globe, but their number has decreased and now represents a smaller proportion of the world’s population. Perhaps this growth of freedom is partially responsible for the breakdown of the family and the rise in crime, described in the previous chapter. Dictators do tolerate less crime and are often very repressive of deviant sexual behavior, but, as the previous chapter reported, divorce and illegitimacy are more connected with improved income of women than with a permissive society.
    [Show full text]
  • Freedom of Speech, Freedom of Self-Expression, and Kant's Public
    Diametros 54 (2017): 118–137 doi: 10.13153/diam.54.2017.1136 FREEDOM OF SPEECH, FREEDOM OF SELF-EXPRESSION, AND KANT’S PUBLIC USE OF REASON – Geert Van Eekert – Abstract. This article turns to early modern and Enlightenment advocates of tolerance (Locke, Spi- noza, John Stuart Mill) to discover and lay bare the line of argument that has informed their com- mitment to free speech. This line of argument will subsequently be used to assess the shift from free speech to the contemporary ideal of free self-expression. In order to take this assessment one step further, this article will finally turn to Immanuel Kant’s famous defense of the public use of reason. In the wake of Katerina Deligiorgi’s readings of Kant, it will show that the idea of free speech requires a specific disposition on behalf of speakers and writers that is in danger of being neglected in the contemporary prevailing conception of free speech as freedom of self-expression. Keywords: John Locke, Baruch Spinoza, Immanuel Kant, John Stuart Mill, freedom of speech, free- dom of self-expression, public use of reason, Enlightenment. Contemporary debates about free speech or freedom of speech primarily deal with the question how free speech should be (in the sense of both “How free should speech be?” and “How should free speech be?”), and not (or at least not mainly) with the question why speech should be free.1 Admittedly, there seems to be no reason to urge the latter question: it is rather generally agreed upon today (at least in liberal democratic societies) that freedom of speech should be both es- teemed and categorically defended because it is both a fundamental human right and a key pillar of democracy and of the (scientific) quest for knowledge.
    [Show full text]
  • Some Worries About the Coherence of Left-Libertarianism Mathias Risse
    John F. Kennedy School of Government Harvard University Faculty Research Working Papers Series Can There be “Libertarianism without Inequality”? Some Worries About the Coherence of Left-Libertarianism Mathias Risse Nov 2003 RWP03-044 The views expressed in the KSG Faculty Research Working Paper Series are those of the author(s) and do not necessarily reflect those of the John F. Kennedy School of Government or Harvard University. All works posted here are owned and copyrighted by the author(s). Papers may be downloaded for personal use only. Can There be “Libertarianism without Inequality”? Some Worries About the Coherence of Left-Libertarianism1 Mathias Risse John F. Kennedy School of Government, Harvard University October 25, 2003 1. Left-libertarianism is not a new star on the sky of political philosophy, but it was through the recent publication of Peter Vallentyne and Hillel Steiner’s anthologies that it became clearly visible as a contemporary movement with distinct historical roots. “Left- libertarian theories of justice,” says Vallentyne, “hold that agents are full self-owners and that natural resources are owned in some egalitarian manner. Unlike most versions of egalitarianism, left-libertarianism endorses full self-ownership, and thus places specific limits on what others may do to one’s person without one’s permission. Unlike right- libertarianism, it holds that natural resources may be privately appropriated only with the permission of, or with a significant payment to, the members of society. Like right- libertarianism, left-libertarianism holds that the basic rights of individuals are ownership rights. Left-libertarianism is promising because it coherently underwrites both some demands of material equality and some limits on the permissible means of promoting this equality” (Vallentyne and Steiner (2000a), p 1; emphasis added).
    [Show full text]
  • The Freedom of Academic Freedom: a Legal Dilemma
    Chicago-Kent Law Review Volume 48 Issue 2 Article 4 October 1971 The Freedom of Academic Freedom: A Legal Dilemma Luis Kutner Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.kentlaw.iit.edu/cklawreview Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Luis Kutner, The Freedom of Academic Freedom: A Legal Dilemma, 48 Chi.-Kent L. Rev. 168 (1971). Available at: https://scholarship.kentlaw.iit.edu/cklawreview/vol48/iss2/4 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Scholarly Commons @ IIT Chicago-Kent College of Law. It has been accepted for inclusion in Chicago-Kent Law Review by an authorized editor of Scholarly Commons @ IIT Chicago-Kent College of Law. For more information, please contact [email protected], [email protected]. THE FREEDOM OF ACADEMIC FREEDOM: A LEGAL DILEMMA Luis KUTNER* Because modern man in his search for truth has turned away from kings, priests, commissars and bureaucrats, he is left, for better or worse, with professors. -Walter Lippman. Complete liberty of contradicting and disproving our opinion is the very condition which justifies us in assuming its truth for purposes of action.... -John Stuart Mill, On Liberty. I. INTRODUCTION IN THESE DAYS of crisis in higher education, part of the threat to aca- demic freedom-which includes the concepts of freedom of thought, inquiry, expression and orderly assembly-has come, unfortunately, from certain actions by professors, who have traditionally enjoyed the protection that academic freedom affords. While many of the professors who teach at American institutions of higher learning are indeed competent and dedicated scholars in their fields, a number of their colleagues have allied themselves with student demonstrators and like organized groups who seek to destroy the free and open atmosphere of the academic community.
    [Show full text]
  • Freedom of Thought, Conscience and Religion
    Freedom of thought, COUNCIL CONSEIL conscience OF EUROPE DE L’EUROPE and religion A guide to the implementation of Article 9 of the European Convention on Human Rights Jim Murdoch Human rights handbooks, No. 9 HRHB9_EN.book Page 1 Tuesday, June 26, 2007 4:08 PM HRHB9_EN.book Page 1 Tuesday, June 26, 2007 4:08 PM Freedom of thought, conscience and religion A guide to the implementation of Article 9 of the European Convention on Human Rights Jim Murdoch Human rights handbooks, No. 9 HRHB9_EN.book Page 2 Tuesday, June 26, 2007 4:08 PM In the “Human rights handbooks” series: No. 1: The right to respect for private No. 6: The prohibition of torture. A Directorate General and family life. A guide to the implemen- guide to the implementation of Article 3 of Human Rights tation of Article 8 of the European Con- of the European Convention on Human and Legal Affairs vention on Human Rights (2001) Rights (2003) Council of Europe F-67075 Strasbourg Cedex No. 2: Freedom of expression. A guide to the implementation of Article 10 of the No. 7 : Positive obligations under the © Council of Europe, 2007 European Convention on Human Rights European Convention on Human Cover illustration © Sean Nel – Fotolia.com (2001) Rights. A guide to the implementation of No. 3: The right to a fair trial. A guide to the European Convention on Human 1st printing, June 2007 the implementation of Article 6 of the Rights (2007) Printed in Belgium European Convention on Human Rights (2001; 2nd edition, 2006) No. 8: The right to life.
    [Show full text]
  • The Right to Freedom of Thought, Conscience and Religion Or Belief
    Level 1, 4 Campion St PO Box 232 DEAKIN ACT 2600 DEAKIN WEST ACT 2600 T 02 6259 0431 T 02 6171 7446 E [email protected] E [email protected] 04 May 2017 Committee Secretary Joint Standing Committee on Foreign Affairs, Defence and Trade PO Box 6021 Parliament House Canberra ACT 2600 RE: Inquiry into the status of the human right to freedom of religion or belief 1. The Human Rights Law Alliance and the Australian Christian Lobby welcome this opportunity to make a submission to the Inquiry into the Status of the Human Right to Freedom of Religion or Belief. 2. The Human Rights Law Alliance implements legal strategies to protect and promote fundamental human rights. It does this by resourcing legal cases with funding and expertise to create rights-protecting legal precedents. The Alliance is especially concerned to protect and promote the right to freedom of thought, conscience and religion or belief. In the past 12 months, the Alliance has aided more than 20 legal cases, and allied lawyers appeared in State Tribunals and Magistrates, District and Supreme Courts as well as the Federal Court. 3. With more than 80,000 supporters, ACL facilitates professional engagement and dialogue between the Christian constituency and government, allowing the voice of Christians to be heard in the public square. ACL is neither party partisan or denominationally aligned. ACL representatives bring a Christian perspective to policy makers in Federal, State and Territory parliaments. 4. Broadly, the terms of reference invite submissions concerning the status of the right in Australia and around the world.
    [Show full text]
  • Universal Declaration of Human Rights
    Universal Declaration of Human Rights Preamble Whereas recognition of the inherent dignity and of the equal and inalienable rights of all members of the human family is the foundation of freedom, justice and peace in the world, Whereas disregard and contempt for human rights have resulted in barbarous acts which have outraged the conscience of mankind, and the advent of a world in which human beings shall enjoy freedom of speech and belief and freedom from fear and want has been proclaimed as the highest aspiration of the common people, Whereas it is essential, if man is not to be compelled to have recourse, as a last resort, to rebellion against tyranny and oppression, that human rights should be protected by the rule of law, Whereas it is essential to promote the development of friendly relations between nations, Whereas the peoples of the United Nations have in the Charter reaffirmed their faith in fundamental human rights, in the dignity and worth of the human person and in the equal rights of men and women and have determined to promote social progress and better standards of life in larger freedom, Whereas Member States have pledged themselves to achieve, in cooperation with the United Nations, the promotion of universal respect for and observance of human rights and fundamental freedoms, Whereas a common understanding of these rights and freedoms is of the greatest importance for the full realization of this pledge, Now, therefore, The General Assembly, Proclaims this Universal Declaration of Human Rights as a common standard of achievement for all peoples and all nations, to the end that every individual and every organ of society, keeping this Declaration constantly in mind, shall strive by teaching and education to promote respect for these rights and freedoms and by progressive measures, national and international, to secure their universal and effective recognition and observance, both among the peoples of Member States themselves and among the peoples of territories under their jurisdiction.
    [Show full text]
  • Quong-Left-Libertarianism.Pdf
    The Journal of Political Philosophy: Volume 19, Number 1, 2011, pp. 64–89 Symposium: Ownership and Self-ownership Left-Libertarianism: Rawlsian Not Luck Egalitarian Jonathan Quong Politics, University of Manchester HAT should a theory of justice look like? Any successful answer to this Wquestion must find a way of incorporating and reconciling two moral ideas. The first is a particular conception of individual freedom: because we are agents with plans and projects, we should be accorded a sphere of liberty to protect us from being used as mere means for others’ ends. The second moral idea is that of equality: we are moral equals and as such justice requires either that we receive equal shares of something—of whatever it is that should be used as the metric of distributive justice—or else requires that unequal distributions can be justified in a manner that is consistent with the moral equality of persons. These twin ideas—liberty and equality—are things which no sound conception of justice can properly ignore. Thus, like most political philosophers, I take it as given that the correct conception of justice will be some form of liberal egalitarianism. A deep and difficult challenge for all liberal egalitarians is to determine how the twin values of freedom and equality can be reconciled within a single theory of distributive justice. Of the many attempts to achieve this reconciliation, left-libertarianism is one of the most attractive and compelling. By combining the libertarian commitment to full (or nearly full) self-ownership with an egalitarian principle for the ownership of natural resources, left- libertarians offer an account of justice that appears firmly committed both to individual liberty, and to an egalitarian view of how opportunities or advantages must be distributed.
    [Show full text]