Contradiction and Confirmation: Validity As Persuasiveness

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Contradiction and Confirmation: Validity As Persuasiveness Contradiction and Confirmation: Validity as Persuasiveness TANYA DITOMMASO, University a/Ottawa Derrida's deconstruction of metaphysical identity, authority, and certainty has left contemporary philosophers scrambling to fmd ways in which they can describe and evaluate the interpreter's task without appealing to metaphysical dogma. l At the present moment, given Derrida's deconstruction, it is impossible to say that an interpretation is either "valid" or "invalid." The task of comparing and deciding between interpretations must be performed without absolute standards. Yet the postmodern interpreter is no less confronted with the task of reading competing interpretations and deciding which to accept. How, then, does the postmodern reader perform this task? What postfoundational tools or guides are available? While Derrida has taken great pains to deconstruct metaphysical grounds, we should not conclude that there are no postfoundational principles informing interpretive judgement. Undecidability Versus Indeterminacy Throughout Derrida's deconstruction of metaphysical grounds is the claim that the meaning of any text is undecidable. It is important to note, however, that the notion of undecidability does not entail the complete absence of principles in reading. Indeed, Derrida fIrmly rejects the notion of indeterminacy of meaning. In an effort to clarify his position, he claims that undecidability rather than indeterminacy is the implication of deconstruction. [AJt stake is always a set of determinate and fInite possibilities ... otherwise, one could indeed say just anything at all and I have never accepted saying, or encouraging others to say, just anything at all, nor have I argued for indeterminacy as such .... I do not believe I have ever spoken of "indeterminacy," whether in regard to "meaning" or anything else. Undecidability is something else again .... I want to recall that undecidability is always a determinate oscillation between possibilities .... These possibilities are themselves highly determined in strictly defined situations.2 Undecidability refers not to the impossibility of making any decision at all, but to the inherent complexity of decision making itself. Derrida stresses the fluidity of borders and the need for "an incessant movement ofrecontextualization" while admitting that the reader's activity limits and affects what a text means. Readers interpret within a context; "there is nothing outside context ... nothing exists outside context," and what is more, "one cannot r 24 Contradiction and Confinnation Contradiction and Confinnation 25 do anything, least of all speak, without detennining a context.,,3 The context of we can only read by deciding to highlight particular connections in a text. interpretation cannot be absolutely indetenninate or perfectly fluid; in being forced Essentially, reading or interpreting consists of organizing words into webs of to make decisions about a text's contextual margin, readers create readings that are relations, where such relations spread their effects in chains or webs over the rest detennined in part by these decisions. To say that contexts remain fluid is to of the text. Presumably, this is what Derrida is driving at when he writes: acknowledge that the meaning of an interpretation can change. It does not mean, "following the appearances of the word 'supplement' and of the corresponding however, that there is absolutely no determination to that interpretation's meaning. concept or concepts, we traverse a certain path within ... [the] text.'06 Maintaining that meaning is neither detenninate nor indetenninate, Derrida claims An appeal to structural dependency is implicit to Derrida's observation that he has never proposed an "'all or nothing' choice between pure realization of that the question "what is writing?" is guided by the interpreter's belief in the self-presence and complete freeplay or undecidability," and declares: "what has certitude of essence. Derrida, of course, rejects such essences, yet while recogniz­ always interested me the most ... is not indetenninacy in itself, but the strictest ing that a belie/in essences is necessary in prompting and guiding both the question 7 possible detennination of the figures of play, of oscillation, of undecidability.'''' "what is?" and the metaphysical answer that follows. Thus, as Derrida notes, "if While words may possess numerous meanings which alter according to words ... receive meaning only in sequences of differences, one can justify one's different readings, this does not entail a complete lack of margins for interpretation. language, and one's choice of tenns, only within ... an orientation in space." There are no absolute standards; readers must make decisions regarding the Elsewhere, Derrida suggests that the notion of "objectiVity" implies a certain contextual boundaries of a given text. With the recognition that contextual context, for ."what is called 'objectivity,' ... imposes itself only within a context decisions must be made by the reader, we have stumbled upon something that is which is extremely vast, old, powerfully established, stabilized or rooted in a invariably and necessarily the case in interpretation--contextual structural network of conventions ... which still remains a context."g Moreover, Derrida's dependency. As a procedural condition for the possibility of reading, this structural assumption of the critical role played by the reader's context-fonnation decisions dependency provides a partial basis for interpretive adjudication. is the very thing that fuels his critique of Searle's interpretation (or misinterpreta­ tion) of deconstruction. Derrida argues that Searle's misinterpretation is a result of 9 Contextual Structural Dependency his misunderstanding of the context of deconstruction. The above examples illustrate Derrida's acknowledgment that the reader's Derrida's writings present no exception to the rule that words mutually affect one context-fonnation decisions provide a condition for the possibility of reading, and ·another to fonn a structural dependency. If, as Derrida maintains, words contain that such decisions contribute to the success or failure of interpretation. Without alterity, then they necessarily affect and point to other words. The otherness in absolute grounds, the reader can appeal to structural dependency in judging an every word implies that words necessarily have effects. All writing is an effect of interpretation. In this light we can read Derrida's comment that "we would have to differance. That effects are integral to writing is further evident in Derrida' s reexamine all these concepts in tenns of what more and more clearly appears to be description of the supplement. In pointing toward and being dependent upon its their concantenation, not their ... identity"l0 as an indication that all is not lost in supplement, writing "marks an irreducible and generative multiplicity," where what resolving interpretive conflict. is written "unceasingly dislocates itself in a chain of differing and deferring Reading is a process wherein an interpreter, at the very least, attempts to substitutions." Differance makes supplementation not only possible but, more sketch out the margins of a structurally dependent context. The reader must decide importantly, necessary. Writing, as differance, requires a chain of affects and what he/she will regard as the "best" structurally dependent context for a given effects. Remarking that ''the concept of experience in general ... remains governed text. In attempting to make sense of a text, he/she highlights contextual connec­ by the theme of presence ... [and] difJerance finds itself enmeshed in the work that tions, thereby reducing ambiguity to a minimum. Without eliminating ambiguity pulls it through a chain of other 'concepts,' other 'words,' other textual configura­ absolutely, we can certainly limit it. This is precisely what we try to do when we tions," Derrid~ clearly acknowledges that words mutually affect, and simulta­ decide upon the "best" possible context for a text. On precisely this point, Derrida neously impose themselves upon, one another. 5 writes: To speak of a structural dependency is to acknowledge that writing must generate effects; it is structurally impossible to employ words without generating In addressing my answers to you, in the first place and as effects (words affecting other words as well as affecting the reader). Reading is a directly as possible, in entrusting myself to the contextual limits process of focusing on and winding around efficacious and dynamic word detennined by your questions, I shaH reduce just a little the connections. Despite the fact that readers never exhaust all possible connections, violence and the ambiguity. For that is what we want, isn't it, to 26 Contradiction and Confmnation Contradiction and Confirmation 27 reduce them, if possible. denied, or enclosed in a book." While the community of interpreters does not exist in a realist sense, "the reconstitution of a context ... is [nonetheless] a regulative Without identifying a context, reading and speaking about a t{;xt would be ideal in the ethics of reading, of interpretation, or of discussion." The reader's impossible. As Derrida observes: belief in the "regulative ideal" of a larger interpretive community provides a partial basis for contextual decisions. The reader's contextual decisions revolve around the Without a solid competence in this domain, the most venture­ establishing of boundaries of what is believed to be
Recommended publications
  • The Unlimited Responsibility of Spilling Ink Marko Zlomislic
    ISSN 1393-614X Minerva - An Internet Journal of Philosophy 11 (2007): 128-152 ____________________________________________________ The Unlimited Responsibility of Spilling Ink Marko Zlomislic Abstract In order to show that both Derrida’s epistemology and his ethics can be understood in terms of his logic of writing and giving, I consider his conversation with Searle in Limited Inc. I bring out how a deconstruction that is implied by the dissemination of writing and giving makes a difference that accounts for the creative and responsible decisions that undecidability makes possible. Limited Inc has four parts and I will interpret it in terms of the four main concepts of Derrida. I will relate signature, event, context to Derrida’s notion of dissemination and show how he differs from Austin and Searle concerning the notion of the signature of the one who writes and gives. Next, I will show how in his reply to Derrida, entitled, “Reiterating the Differences”, Searle overlooks Derrida’s thought about the communication of intended meaning that has to do with Derrida’s distinction between force and meaning and his notion of differance. Here I will show that Searle cannot even follow his own criteria for doing philosophy. Then by looking at Limited Inc, I show how Derrida differs from Searle because repeatability is alterability. Derrida has an ethical intent all along to show that it is the ethos of alterity that is called forth by responsibility and accounted for by dissemination and difference. Of course, comments on comments, criticisms of criticisms, are subject to the law of diminishing fleas, but I think there are here some misconceptions still to be cleared up, some of which seem to still be prevalent in generally sensible quarters.
    [Show full text]
  • Thinking the Concept Otherwise: Deleuze and Expression
    Thinking the Concept Otherwise: Deleuze and Expression PETER COOK University o/Sydney ABSTRACT: In What is Philosophy?, Deleuze and Guattari think the concept of concept otherwise. In keeping with Deleuze 's professed empiricism, he and Guattari study various concepts and 'extract' a new concept ofthe concept. This constructive method does not illuminate how and why their proposed concept diffors from the traditional. This paper considers how Deleuze and Guattari 's concept does differ, as afirst step towards arriving at some evaluation oftheir analysis. REsUME: Dans Qu' est-ce que la philosophie?, Deleuze et Guattari pensent Ie concept autrement. Tout en s 'en tenant aI 'empirisme avoue de Deleuze, ce dernier et Guattari analysent differents concepts et en 'extraient' un nouveau concept de concept. Cette methode constructive n 'eclaire cependant pas comment et pourquoi Ie concept qu 'ils proposent di.ffere du concept traditionnel. Apres avoir considere la faryon dont Ie concept de Deleuze et Guattari di.ffere en effit de l'acception traditionnelle, cet article pourra se pencher sur la question de I 'evaluation de leur analyse. " ... one can ... think ... the concept of concept otherwise ... "l In What is Philosophy?, Deleuze and Guattari think the concept of concept otherwise. In keeping with Deleuze's professed empiricism, he and Guattari study various concepts and 'extract' a new concept of the concept. This constructive method does not illuminate how and why their proposed concept differs from the traditional. In this paper I consider how Deleuze and Guattari's concept does differ, as a first step towards arriving at some evaluation of their analysis.
    [Show full text]
  • PHIL 463/563 Author: Jacques DERRIDA Fall 2016 Instructor
    PHIL 463/563 Author: Jacques DERRIDA Fall 2016 Instructor: Professor Beata Stawarska Noon - 1:50pm, T & TH, 250C SCH Office Hours: T 2-3:50pm & by appointment Office: SCH 247 E-mail: [email protected] Description This class surveys representative works by the contemporary Algerian-Jewish-French philosopher Jacques Derrida (1930-2004). We will focus especially on the tasks and methods of deconstruction, which is first and foremost a style of reading texts attending to their logical and rhetorical dimensions. A related focus will be on Derrida’s critique of Western metaphysics of presence with its set of violent and vertical dichotomies such as interiority and exteriority, speech and writing, male and female, self and other, and on his attempt to thematize difference in a more complex, dynamic, and non-hierarchical manner – both at the level of theory and practice. These two main foci determine the design of this class, which examines Derrida’s deconstructive reading of Husserl’s phenomenology of consciousness with its commitment to the primacy of sound and/or voice (The Voice and Phenomena); Plato’s Phaedrus and the undecidable status of writing as a pharmakon (remedy and/or poison) (Dissemination); and J. L. Austin’s and John Searle’s speech acts theory and its conception of the performative (Limited Inc). We will then address Derrida’s more recent, socially and politically situated work, especially the question of sexual difference and feminism (select essays from Psyche), of an indeconstructible and other- oriented justice (‘Force of Law: the Mystical Foundation of Authority’), and of linguistic and cultural identity within a post-colonial context (Monolingualism of the Other).
    [Show full text]
  • Jacques Derrida Law As Absolute Hospitality
    JACQUES DERRIDA LAW AS ABSOLUTE HOSPITALITY JACQUES DE VILLE NOMIKOI CRITICAL LEGAL THINKERS Jacques Derrida Jacques Derrida: Law as Absolute Hospitality presents a comprehensive account and understanding of Derrida’s approach to law and justice. Through a detailed reading of Derrida’s texts, Jacques de Ville contends that it is only by way of Derrida’s deconstruction of the metaphysics of presence, and specifi cally in relation to the texts of Husserl, Levinas, Freud and Heidegger, that the reasoning behind his elusive works on law and justice can be grasped. Through detailed readings of texts such as ‘To Speculate – on Freud’, Adieu, ‘Declarations of Independence’, ‘Before the Law’, ‘Cogito and the History of Madness’, Given Time, ‘Force of Law’ and Specters of Marx, de Ville contends that there is a continuity in Derrida’s thinking, and rejects the idea of an ‘ethical turn’. Derrida is shown to be neither a postmodernist nor a political liberal, but a radical revolutionary. De Ville also controversially contends that justice in Derrida’s thinking must be radically distinguished from Levinas’s refl ections on ‘the Other’. It is the notion of absolute hospitality – which Derrida derives from Levinas, but radically transforms – that provides the basis of this argument. Justice must, on de Ville’s reading, be understood in terms of a demand of absolute hospitality which is imposed on both the individual and the collective subject. A much needed account of Derrida’s infl uential approach to law, Jacques Derrida: Law as Absolute Hospitality will be an invaluable resource for those with an interest in legal theory, and for those with an interest in the ethics and politics of deconstruction.
    [Show full text]
  • THE PRAGMATICS of DIRECT ADDRESS in the ILIAD: a STUDY in LINGUISTIC POLITENESS DISSERTATION Presented in Partial Fulfillment Of
    THE PRAGMATICS OF DIRECT ADDRESS IN THE ILIAD: A STUDY IN LINGUISTIC POLITENESS DISSERTATION Presented in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of the Ohio State University By H. Paul Brown The Ohio State University 2003 Dissertation Committee: Approved by Stephen V. Tracy, Advisor Victoria Wohl ________________________ Advisor Brian Joseph Department of Greek and Latin Daniel Collins Copyright by H. Paul Brown 2003 ABSTRACT The purpose of this paper will be to examine, in the text of Homer’s Iliad, some of the pragmatic and sociolinguistic factors in the choice of form of address (epithet). Specifically I will look at these in light of the Parry-Lord theory of oral composition and its claims of ‘economy of form.’ The results of this limited examination have important implications for the viability of such methods and for our understanding of oral, traditional literature. Milman Parry, as is well known, demonstrated that the choice of appellation for any character, between the given-name (e.g., ÉAgam°mnvn) and the patronymic (e.g., ÉAtre˝dhw) was a decision based on metrical considerations alone, and importantly, not on semantic ones. The two terms cannot simply be substituted for the other without changing the meter of the whole line. The choice between the two is, according to Parry, driven by metrical necessity alone and hence any possible distinction of meaning is automatically bleached. The two names mean the same thing (i.e., Agamemnon). In this study I will look specifically at the use types of address within the narrative frame of the Iliad, in light of two potentially contributing factors.
    [Show full text]
  • Information to Users
    INFORMATION TO USERS This manuscript has been reproduced from the microfilm master. UMI films the text directly from the original or copy submitted. Thus, some thesis and dissertation copies are in typewriter face, while others may be from any type of computer printer. The quality of this reproduction is dependent upon the quality of the copy sutimitted. Broken or indistinct print, colored or poor quality illustrations and photographs, print bleedthrough, substandard margins, and improper alignment can adversely affect reproduction. In the unlikely event that the author did not send UMI a complete manuscript and there are missing pages, these will be noted. Also, if unauthorged copyright material had to be removed, a note will indicate the deletion. Oversize materials (e g., maps, drawings, charts) are reproduced by sectioning the original, beginning at the upper left-hand comer and continuing from left to right in equal sections with small overlaps. Photographs included in the original manuscript have been reproduced xerographically in this copy. Higher quality 6" x 9* black and white photographic prints are available for any photographs or illustrations appearing in this copy for an additional charge. Contact UMI directly to order. ProQuest Information and Leaming 300 North Zeeb Road, Ann Arbor, Ml 48106-1346 USA 800-521-0600 UMÏ EIHETORICAL HYBRIDITY: ASHBERY, BERNSTEIN AND THE POETICS OF CITAHON DISSERTATION Presented in. Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for The Degree Doctor of Philosophy m the Graduate School o f The Ohio State University By \fatthew Richardson^ hlA . ***** The Ohio State Unwersity 2001 Dissertation Committee: Approved by Professor Jon Erickson. Adviser Professor Jessica Prinz .
    [Show full text]
  • 1 After the Event: Looking Back on Deconstruction
    Notes 1 After the Event: Looking Back on Deconstruction 1. The question of immediate retrospect has figured in many commentaries on this event, but often focused on the supposedly inaugural nature of the con- ference for structuralism in America, organized as it was to celebrate the work of Claude Levi-Strauss. Russell Daylight claims that the ‘force of Derrida’s 1966 paper was such that it simultaneously announced the opening and closing of structuralism in the Anglophone world’ (Daylight 2012). The simultaneity of the beginning and the end was extended to deconstruction itself partly by the length of time that it took for Derrida’s paper to be made widely available in the United States. For further detail see Chapter 2 below. 2. In ‘Structure, Sign and Play’ this is a concern with an emerging monstrosity that cannot yet be fully discerned. We see this also in the mention of the future anterior at the opening of Of Grammatology. The epoch more generally has been characterized this way by François Lyotard and Julia Kristeva: see Lyotard (1978); Kristeva (1981). 3. The wording is borrowed here from Thomas Pavel and David Herman, and the phrase is widely used in cognitive narratology to describe one of the ten- dencies of the structuralist phase that ‘postclassical’ narratology has had to move beyond. 4. Psyche: Invention of the Other and ‘Typewriter Ribbon’. 5. Derrida refers to a wide debate on this subject, and in particular to essays by Suzanne Gearhart and Rodolphe Gasché. These discussions figure later in this book. It is worth speculating, though, that the notion of self-reflexivity may simply have been mistaken for the notion of self-reflection, which makes perfectly good sense.
    [Show full text]
  • Learning to Live Finally Learning to Live Finally the Last Interview
    ZJ ~T~} 'Along with Ludwig Wittgenstein and Martin Heidegger, Jacques Q, Qj Derrida, who died in Paris at the age of 74, will be remembered as —— one of the three most important philosophers of the 20th century.' LEARNING TO >*J — The New York Times r— ^-» With death looming, Jacques Derrida, the world's most famous __ *T\ philosopher - known as the father of 'deconstruction' - sat down ~' with journalist Jean Birnbaum of the French daily Le Monde. They LIVE FINALLY revisited his life's work and his impending death in a long, surpris• ingly accessible, and moving final interview. The Last Interview Sometimes called 'obscure' and branded 'abstruse' by his critics, the Derrida found in this book is open and engaging, reflecting on a long career challenging important tenets of European philosophy 'ACOUES DERRIDA from Plato to Marx. The contemporary meaning of Derrida's work is also examined, including a discussion of his many political activities. But, as Derrida says, 'To philosophize is to learn to die'; as such, this philosophical discussion turns to the realities of his imminent death-including life with a fatal cancer. In the end, this interview remains a touching final look at a long and distinguished career. The late Jacques Derrida was Director of Studies at the Ecole des Hautes Etudes en Sciences Sociales, France, and Professor of Humanities at the University of California, Irvine. ISBN 978-0-230-53785-9 9 780230 537859 Cover illustration © Carol Hayes Learning to Live Finally Learning to Live Finally The Last Interview Jacques Derrida An Interview with Jean Birnbaum Translated by Pascale-Anne Brault and Michael Naas With a bibliography by Peter Krapp All rights reserved.
    [Show full text]
  • Pragmatics, Prague- Matics, Metapragmatics: Contextuaiizing Pragmatic Contexts
    Pragmatics, Prague- matics, Metapragmatics: ContextuaIizing Pragmatic Contexts DAVID HERMAN ...the complete meaning of a sign cannot be but the historical recording of the pragmatic labour that has accompanied every contextual instance of it; . to interpret a sign menas to foresee- ideally-- all the possible contexts in,which it can be inserted (Eco 1937 : 706). 1. Analytic and Structuralist Pragamatics When Charles Morrls(1938) isolated syntax, semantics and pragmatics as three interactive dimensions of semiosis, he thought that he was contributing to an international project envisaged by the founding members of the Vienna Circle-- the project, namely, of the unification of the sciences. Ironically, a half- century after Morris specified these three dimensions, and despite his having dermed the notions of syntax, semantics and pragmatics in what no doubt seemed to him a highly general and therefore maximally non- controversial manner, consensus about what falls within the scope of each semiotic dimension remains split roughly along the lines of scholars' nationalities. Herman Parret (1983) has shown how ,in general, scholars working in the Anglo Saxon or Peircean ("analytic") semiotic tradition find themselves pitted against scholras in the ("structural") Continental tradition, which began with Saussure, extends through Hjelmslev and perpetuates itself in post- Hjclmslevians like Greimas (23-88).1 Specifically, the dispute between the analytic and structuralist factions centers on the element of dynamism that Peircean semiotics, in constrast
    [Show full text]
  • Derrida's Debt to Milton Friedman Michael Tratner Bryn Mawr College, [email protected]
    Bryn Mawr College Scholarship, Research, and Creative Work at Bryn Mawr College English Faculty Research and Scholarship English 2003 Derrida's Debt to Milton Friedman Michael Tratner Bryn Mawr College, [email protected] Let us know how access to this document benefits ouy . Follow this and additional works at: http://repository.brynmawr.edu/engl_pubs Part of the English Language and Literature Commons Custom Citation Tratner, Michael. "Derrida's Debt to Milton Friedman." New Literary History: A Journal of Theory and Interpretation 34, no. 4 (Autumn 2003): 791-806. This paper is posted at Scholarship, Research, and Creative Work at Bryn Mawr College. http://repository.brynmawr.edu/engl_pubs/7 For more information, please contact [email protected]. Tratner, Michael: "Derrida's Debt to Milton Friedman," New Literary History: A Journal of Theory and Interpretation , (34:4), 2003 Autumn, 791-806. (2003), 791-806. In the essay Given Time: I. Counterfeit Money , Jacques Derrida says it is important to trace the literary consequences of certain events in economic history: "To study, for example, in so-called modern literature, that is, contemporaneous with capital-city, polis, metropolis-of a state and with a state of capital, the transformation of money forms (metallic, fiduciary-the bank note-or scriptural-the bank check), a certain rarification of payments in cash, the recourse to credit cards, the coded signature, and so forth, in short, a certain dematerialization of money, and therefore of all the scenes that depend on it." 1 The transformation Derrida describes is part of the development of late capitalism; though his essay analyzes a short story by the nineteenth century writer Baudelaire, the transformation away from "metallic" to "fiduciary" forms of money officially occurred in the twentieth century, as did the spread of credit cards and coded signatures.
    [Show full text]
  • Bibliography
    Bibliography Aristotle. (1941). Metaphysics, Physics. In The Basic Works of Aristotle. Richard McKeon. (Ed.). New York, NY: Random House. Attridge, Derek (Ed.). (1992). Acts of Literature. London and NY: Routledge. Augustine, St. (2006). Confessions. Indianapolis: Hackett. Bacon, Francis. (1960). The New Organon and Related Writings. New York: Prentice-Hall. Baker, Lynne Rudder. (2000). Metaphysics of Everyday Life. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Baldwin, Thomas. (2008). “Presence, Truth and Authenticity.” In S.Glendenning & R. Eaglestone. (Eds.), Derrida’s Legacies Literature and Philosophy (pp. 107-17). New York: Routledge. Bennington, Geoffrey. (2000). Interrupting Derrida. London: Routledge. Berman, Art. (1988).From the New Criticism to Deconstruction. Urbana: University of Illinois Press. Bernasconi, Robert. (1989). “Seeing Double: Destruktion and Deconstruction.” In D. Michelfelder (Ed.), Dialogue and Deconstruction The Gadamer-Derrida Encounter (pp. 233-50). Albany: SUNY Press. Brann, Eva T. H. (1991). The World of the Imagination. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield. Caputo, John D. (1989). “Gadamer’s Closet Essentialism: A Derridean Critique.” In D. Michelfelder (Ed.), Dialogue and Deconstruction The Gadamer-Derrida Encounter (pp. 258-64). Albany: SUNY Press. ________. (1993). “In Search of the Quasi-Transcendental: The Case of Derrida and Rorty.” In G. Madison (Ed.). Working through Derrida (pp. 147-69). Evanston: Northwestern University Press. ________. (1997). Deconstruction in a Nutshell: A Conversation with Jacques Derrida. New York: Fordham University Press. Chalmers, David, D. Manley, R. Wasserman (Eds.). (2009). Metametaphysics New Essays on the Foundations of Ontology. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Churchland, Paul. (2013). Matter and Consciousness. 3rd. Ed. Cambridge: MIT Press. Cohen, Tom (Ed.). (2001). Jacques Derrida and the Humanities. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
    [Show full text]
  • The Paradox of Ipseity and Difference: Derrida's
    KRITIKĒ VOLUME ONE NUMBER ONE (JUNE 2007) 32-51 Article The Paradox of Ipseity and Difference: Derrida’s Deconstruction and Logocentrism Roland Theuas S. Pada Deconstruction and Repetition n thinking of Derrida’s notion of deconstruction as an attitude in understanding logocentrism, one might find it necessary to pre-empt this I discourse by taking into serious consideration three words: center, consciousness, and difference. These words offer the key towards the problem of logocentrism within Derrida’s deconstruction and, as far as these words seem to contextualize themselves within Derrida’s texts, they also offer an explanation of how meaning becomes possible. Derrida’s deconstruction is a form of writing in which the “I-ness” of the self is given emphasis as both the limitation and possibility of appropriation in so far as context is concerned. Reading for him is already considered as an act of writing, the text, being polysemic in its inscription, already implies that the repetition of the syntax of words will always be rendered by the consciousness with a relative amount of impurity. Every instance of reading then is a form of writing, each time an Other tries to read the singularity of the construction of the text, it is already altered as another occurrence within another consciousness. Deconstruction alters what it concerns itself with. This is made apparent by most of Derrida’s works, and to be particular, his deconstruction of the speech act theory.1 In dealing with Austin’s texts, Derrida’s position was questioned by Searle,
    [Show full text]