Immortality and the Philosophy of Death (1St Edition)

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Immortality and the Philosophy of Death (1St Edition) Immortality and the Philosophy of Death Immortality and the Philosophy of Death Edited by Michael Cholbi London • New York Published by Rowman & Littlefield International Ltd Unit A, Whitacre Mews, 26-34 Stannary Street, London SE11 4AB www.rowmaninternational.com Rowman & Littlefield International Ltd. is an affiliate of Rowman & Littlefield 4501 Forbes Boulevard, Suite 200, Lanham, Maryland 20706, USA With additional offices in Boulder, New York, Toronto (Canada), and Plymouth (UK) www.rowman.com Selection and editorial matter © Michael Cholbi 2016 Copyright in individual chapters is held by the respective chapter authors. All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced in any form or by any electronic or mechanical means, including information storage and retrieval systems, without written permission from the publisher, except by a reviewer who may quote passages in a review. British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library ISBN: HB 978-1-78348-383-9 PB 978-1-78348-384-6 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Immortality and the philosophy of death / edited by Michael Cholbi. pages cm Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 978-1-78348-383-9 (cloth : alk. paper) — ISBN 978-1-78348-384-6 (pbk. : alk. paper) — ISBN 978-1-78348-385-3 (electronic) 1. Death. 2. Immortality. I. Cholbi, Michael, editor. BD444.I46 2015 128’.5—dc23 2015032338 ∞ ™ The paper used in this publication meets the minimum requirements of American National Standard for Information Sciences—Permanence of Paper for Printed Library Materials, ANSI/NISO Z39.48-1992. Printed in the United States of America Contents Introduction vii PART I: IS DEATH BAD FOR THOSE THAT DIE? 1 1 Victims 3 Christopher Belshaw 2 Reconsidering Categorical Desire Views 21 Travis Timmerman 3 Epicureanism, Extrinsic Badness, and Prudence 39 Karl Ekendahl and Jens Johansson 4 Lucretius and the Fear of Death 53 Frederik Kaufman 5 The Harms of Death 67 Duncan Purves 6 Seeds: On Personal Identity and the Resurrection 85 Sophie-Grace Chappell PART II: LIVING WITH DEATH 99 7 Fearing Death as Fearing the Loss of One’s Life: Lessons from Alzheimer’s Disease 101 David Beglin 8 Constructing Death as a Form of Failure: Addressing Mortality in a Neoliberal Age 115 Beverley Clack v vi Contents 9 Love and Death 135 Dan Werner 10 Learning to be Dead: The Narrative Problem of Mortality 157 Kathy Behrendt 11 Love and Death: The Problem of Resilience 173 Aaron Smuts PART III: THE VALUE OF AN IMMORTAL LIFE 189 12 Immortality, Identity, and Desirability 191 Roman Altshuler 13 Resources for Overcoming the Boredom of Immortality in Fischer and Kierkegaard 205 Adam Buben 14 Immortality and the Exhaustibility of Value 221 Michael Cholbi Index 237 About the Contributors 241 Introduction Many attempts have been made to define human nature—to identify the characteristics that distinguish us Homo sapiens from other beings, particu- larly our animal brethren. The capacity for language; a moral sensibility; an enjoyment of art, play, or other activities, seemingly for their own sake; sci- entific rationality; a religious impulse; claims have been made on behalf of all of these as the factor that renders us uniquely human. Arguably though, the defining feature of human existence is our relationship to death. Every creature must die, and perhaps some nonhuman animals have some inchoate awareness of their imminent death. But only humans, both individually and collectively, grasp their mortality and are thereby compelled to confront their own deaths. As Ernest Becker, author of the bestselling classic The Denial of Death, explains it: This is what has made it so simple to shoot down whole herds of buffalo or elephants. The animals don’t know that death is happening and continue grazing placidly while others drop alongside them. The knowledge of death is reflective and conceptual, and animals are spared it. They live and they disappear with the same thoughtlessness: a few minutes of fear, a few seconds of anguish, and it is over. But to live a whole lifetime with the fate of death haunting one’s dreams and even the most sun-filled days—that’s something else.1 Here Becker obliquely refers to a facet of death that human beings are likely to be uniquely aware of. Death, Shelly Kagan points out, is ubiquitous: There is no time at which we are completely immune from dying.2 The common human fear of death thus does not stem simply from its being ultimately unavoidable. It seems also to stem from its being omnipresent. vii viii Introduction Of course, one of the themes of Becker’s work, and the work of the “terror management theorists” he has inspired,3 is that the human fear of death is an omnipresent motivator behind our cultural strivings, driving us to establish religions, build monuments to our accomplishments, and defend (even with persecution or violence) the worldviews that define our cultural outlooks, all in an effort to “deny” death and achieve symbolic immortality. But even these efforts at death denial nevertheless corroborate the claim that humans are dis- tinctive in having to address death as a problem in living. For if Becker and his ilk are correct, then many of us “address” death not so much by engaging it but by unwitting efforts to circumvent it or nullify its effects on us. Philosophy is part of human culture too. And while Western philosophers’ interest in addressing death has waxed and waned over the centuries, they have not hidden from death or avoided scrutinizing death’s implications. The first “golden age” of philosophical inquiry into death occurred in the ancient Mediterranean world. For philosophers in the post-Socratic tradition, especially the Roman Stoics and Epicureans, philosophy’s purposes were both theoretical and practical. Successful philosophical inquiry, on their conception of that enterprise, enables us to negotiate life’s perils and adversi- ties, death included. Plato went so far as to declare that the true philosopher pursues philosophy as preparation for death. I would suggest that we are living through a second “golden age” of philosophical inquiry into death. This renaissance of philosophical interest in death traverses many traditions and methodologies, encompassing European “Continental” thinkers (Martin Heidegger and Jean-Paul Sartre) and Anglo- American thinkers (Bernard Williams and Thomas Nagel). The changing nature of the death experience has also contributed to this renaissance. Those in advanced industrialized cultures now routinely live well into “old age,” with death oftentimes preceded by a period of prolonged physical decline or senescence. As a result, most of us now have more time with which to confront the reality of our own deaths. The same technological developments that have extended life into old age have also put death more within our hands than ever before. Indeed, one of the principal factors that drove the rise of clinical medical ethics as a distinct field of inquiry in the twentieth century was the question of whether, if at all, it is ethically defensible to take death into our own hands by intentionally shortening or ending our lives. Concur- rently, some believe that technological advances are nigh that will make it possible to transcend or overcome death, through radically increasing the human lifespan, ending or slowing the aging process so as to achieve physi- ological immortality, or preserving our psychologies in digital form. Contemporary philosophers are wrestling with the metaphysical and ethical implications of these developments, even as they continue to look to ancient thinkers such as Epicurus and Lucretius for insight into such matters. Introduction ix In so doing, they continue the ancient tradition, inviting us to interrogate the aspects of our existence that are most puzzling or unsettling. The purpose of this volume is to represent the cutting edge of contemporary philosophical inquiry into death. The chapters collected here engage with three central areas of philosophical concern. The first area of concern is death’s purported badness. The common human fear of death seems rational only on the condition that death is worthy of being feared, that is, if there is something bad about death (where by “death” here we intend the state of being dead, rather than the process of dying). But it is not obvious that there is something bad about death. As Epicurus famously argued, if death is a state of non-being—not a state that we ever experience—then death should be seen as “nothing to us.” Yet, it is hard to shake the intuition that death is not nothing to us—that death is often bad for the person who dies. The chapters in Part I undertake the challenge of explaining how, if at all, this can be so. Christopher Belshaw (“Victims”) defends a claim regarding a condition on death’s being bad: “Death can only be bad for beings with sufficiently sophisticated psychologies to count as persons.” Persons, according to Belshaw, have beliefs regarding the future and desires pertaining to what occurs in the future. Thanks to these beliefs and desires, persons can want to continue living, and death is bad, Belshaw argues, only for those who want to live. It follows from Belshaw’s position that death cannot be bad for zygotes, fetuses, or nonhuman animals whose psychologies lack the beliefs and desires necessary for personhood. Such entities lack categorical desires, desires we have that give us reason to continue living, not simply reasons to want our lives to go well so long as we live (e.g., the desire to live without pain). In “Reconsidering Categorical Desire Views,” Travis Timmerman develops two hypothetical examples that raise difficulties for views like Belshaw’s that appeal to such desires.
Recommended publications
  • Antinatalism and Moral Particularism Gerald K
    Essays in Philosophy Volume 20 Article 5 Issue 1 Is Procreation Immoral? 1-22-2019 Antinatalism and Moral Particularism Gerald K. Harrison Massey University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://commons.pacificu.edu/eip Recommended Citation Harrison, Gerald K. () "Antinatalism and Moral Particularism," Essays in Philosophy: Vol. 20: Iss. 1, Article 5. https://doi.org/10.7710/ 1526-0569.1629 Essays in Philosophy is a biannual journal published by Pacific nivU ersity Library | ISSN 1526-0569 | http://commons.pacificu.edu/eip/ Essays in Philosophy ISSN 1526-0569 | Essays in Philosophy is published by the Pacific University Libraries Volume 20, Issue 1 (2019) Antinatalism and Moral Particularism Gerald K. Harrison Massey University Abstract I believe most acts of human procreation are immoral, and I believe this despite also believing in the truth of moral particularism. In this paper I explain why. I argue that procreative acts possess numerous features that, in other contexts, seem typically to operate with negative moral valences. Other things being equal this gives us reason to believe they will operate negatively in the context of procreative acts as well. However, most people’s intuitions represent procreative acts to be morally permissible in most circumstances. Given moral particularism, this would normally be good evidence that procreative acts are indeed morally permissible and that the features that operate negatively elsewhere, simply do not do so in the context of procreative acts in particular. But I argue that we have no good reason to think our intuitions about the ethics of human procreation are accurate.
    [Show full text]
  • The Political Sociology and Anthropology of Evil: Tricksterology
    “Because evil is a term fraught with religious overtones, it tends to be under- theorized in our largely secular contemporary culture. Yet something like evil continues to exist, arguably more forcefully today than ever, so the authors of this timely and important book assert. They argue boldly that understanding the continued presence of evil in the modern world requires reconceiving evil through the mythical figure of the trickster, a cross-cultural symbol that repre- sents the perennial temptation to ignore the inherent limits of human thought and action. A wide ranging study that draws on multiple disciplinary sources, Horvath and Szakolczai illustrate forcefully how contemporary efforts to maximize productivity across all sectors of our social order violates the ethos of limits, and only liberates further the forces of destruction. In an age of increasingly mindless (and therefore runaway) processes, we would do well to heed the message of this significant study.” – Gilbert Germain, Professor of Political Thought at the University of Prince Edward Island, Canada “A complex and timely meditation on the nature of evil in human societies, reaching back into the distant past – while not all will agree with its methods or conclusions, this book offers provocative ideas for consideration by anthro- pologists, philosophers, and culture historians.” – David Wengrow, Professor of Comparative Archaeology, University College London, UK “This book offers an original and thought-provoking engagement with a problem for which we still lack adequate perspectives: the disastrous experience of advanced modernity with what we can provisionally call demonic power.” – Johann Arnason, Emeritus Professor of Sociology, La Trobe University, Australia “Horvath and Szakolczai provide a remarkable service in bringing the neglec- ted figure of the trickster into the spotlight.
    [Show full text]
  • The Practical Origins of Ideas
    OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 19/1/2021, SPi The Practical Origins of Ideas Genealogy as Conceptual Reverse-Engineering MATTHIEU QUELOZ 1 OUP CORRECTED AUTOPAGE PROOFS – FINAL, 19/1/2021, SPi 3 Great Clarendon Street, Oxford, OX2 6DP, United Kingdom Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University’s objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide. Oxford is a registered trade mark of Oxford University Press in the UK and in certain other countries © Matthieu Queloz 2021 The moral rights of the author have been asserted First Edition published in 2021 Impression: 1 Some rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, for commercial purposes, without the prior permission in writing of Oxford University Press, or as expressly permitted by law, by licence or under terms agreed with the appropriate reprographics rights organization. This is an open access publication, available online and distributed under the terms of a Creative Commons Attribution – Non Commercial – No Derivatives 4.0 International licence (CC BY-NC-ND 4.0), a copy of which is available at http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/. The pre-press of this publication was supported by the Swiss National Science Foundation. Enquiries concerning reproduction outside the scope of this licence should be sent to the Rights Department, Oxford University Press, at the address above Published in the United States of America by Oxford University Press 198 Madison Avenue, New York, NY 10016, United States of America British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data Data available Library of Congress Control Number: 2020951579 ISBN 978–0–19–886870–5 DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780198868705.001.0001 Printed and bound in the UK by TJ Books Limited Links to third party websites are provided by Oxford in good faith and for information only.
    [Show full text]
  • Cryopreservation Page 3
    2nd quarter 2010 • Volume 31:2 funding Your Cryopreservation page 3 Death of Robert Prehoda Page 7 Member Profile: Mark Plus page 8 Non-existence ISSN 1054-4305 is Hard to Do page 14 $9.95 Improve Your Odds of a Good Cryopreservation You have your cryonics funding and contracts in place but have you considered other steps you can take to prevent problems down the road? Keep Alcor up-to-date about personal and medical changes. Update your Alcor paperwork to reflect your current wishes. Execute a cryonics-friendly Living Will and Durable Power of Attorney for Health Care. Wear your bracelet and talk to your friends and family about your desire to be cryopreserved. Ask your relatives to sign Affidavits stating that they will not interfere with your cryopreservation. Attend local cryonics meetings or start a local group yourself. Contribute to Alcor’s operations and research. Contact Alcor (1-877-462-5267) and let us know how we can assist you. Alcor Life Extension Foundation is on Connect with Alcor members and supporters on our official Facebook page: http://www.facebook.com/alcor.life.extension.foundation Become a fan and encourage interested friends, family members, and colleagues to support us too. 2ND QUARTER 2010 • VOLUME 31:2 2nd quarter 2010 • Volume 31:2 Contents COVER STORY: PAGE 3 funding Your Cryopreservation Without bequests and page 3 donations Alcor’s revenue falls 11 Book Review: The short of covering its operating Rational Optimist: How expenses. This means that Prosperity Evolves Alcor should further cut costs Former Alcor President or increase revenue.
    [Show full text]
  • Superintelligence As a Cause Or Cure for Risks of Astronomical Suffering
    Informatica 41 (2017) 389–400 389 Superintelligence as a Cause or Cure for Risks of Astronomical Suffering Kaj Sotala and Lukas Gloor Foundational Research Institute, Berlin, Germany E-mail: [email protected], [email protected] foundational-research.org Keywords: existential risk, suffering risk, superintelligence, AI alignment problem, suffering-focused ethics, population ethics Received: August 31, 2017 Discussions about the possible consequences of creating superintelligence have included the possibility of existential risk, often understood mainly as the risk of human extinction. We argue that suffering risks (s-risks), where an adverse outcome would bring about severe suffering on an astronomical scale, are risks of a comparable severity and probability as risks of extinction. Preventing them is the common interest of many different value systems. Furthermore, we argue that in the same way as superintelligent AI both contributes to existential risk but can also help prevent it, superintelligent AI can be both the cause of suffering risks and a way to prevent them from being realized. Some types of work aimed at making superintelligent AI safe will also help prevent suffering risks, and there may also be a class of safeguards for AI that helps specifically against s-risks. Povzetek: Prispevek analizira prednosti in nevarnosti superinteligence. 1 Introduction Work discussing the possible consequences of creating We term the possibility of such outcomes a suffering superintelligent AI (Yudkowsky 2008, Bostrom 2014, risk: Sotala & Yampolskiy 2015) has discussed Suffering risk (s-risk): One where an adverse superintelligence as a possible existential risk: a risk outcome would bring about severe suffering on "where an adverse outcome would either annihilate an astronomical scale, vastly exceeding all Earth-originating intelligent life or permanently and suffering that has existed on Earth so far.
    [Show full text]
  • Nihilism, Transcendence and Philosophy." Philosophy in a Meaningless Life: a System of Nihilism, Consciousness and Reality
    Tartaglia, James. "Nihilism, Transcendence and Philosophy." Philosophy in a Meaningless Life: A System of Nihilism, Consciousness and Reality. London: Bloomsbury Academic, 2015. 169–184. Bloomsbury Collections. Web. 28 Sep. 2021. <http://dx.doi.org/10.5040/9781474247696.ch-008>. Downloaded from Bloomsbury Collections, www.bloomsburycollections.com, 28 September 2021, 17:13 UTC. Copyright © James Tartaglia 2016. You may share this work for non-commercial purposes only, provided you give attribution to the copyright holder and the publisher, and provide a link to the Creative Commons licence. 8 Nihilism, Transcendence and Philosophy [W]hen I say, magnanimously, ‘all metaphysical positions are equally good’, I am not taking any position; I am simply expressing a principle of tolerance which, however laudable, is merely formal, and can never produce or even encourage any metaphysi- cal idea. But if I try to combine this principle with my particular position, I become incoherent, because what I then end up saying is, ‘my position is as good as any other, even though it is incompatible with any other.’ Leszek Kołakowski, 1988 1 1. Living with nihilism Superstition reveals a primitive sense of a metaphysical appearance/reality distinction. Thus the superstitious person senses that things might have a different significance to that provided by the framework, and so clings irrationally to idle possibilities, providing them with inappropriate significance. They think that if they touch wood, or wear this shirt rather than that one, then things will turn out as they want them to. They could only be right if life is quite unlike what it appears on the surface.
    [Show full text]
  • ! ! ! Alienistmagazine5.Indd
    1 2 3 4 5 Michael Rowland, from the series SPACE COW (2019) 6 7 8 Political power comes into being through the “grant,” by an absolutist authority, of “individual agency” – of socalled freedom of will – which requires a certain theatre, a performance on the part of the subject acknowledging that such a freedom is indeed within the grant of power in the fi rst place. This performance takes the form of an exchange in which a capital authority over life & death is abrogated into political subjectivity. By such dialectical sleight of hand, power indeed asserts its claim over, & obtains at a discount, the feudal rights to the freedom of the individual, & to the idea of freedom as such. Whatever thus presents itself as exempted or excluded from the domain of the political, is so solely upon this foundation. For this reason we must seek the alienation of the subject not in some social imposition from which it may one day be freed by a political act, but in its very ontology. The individual subject is itself nothing other than the signifi er of a constitutive alienation & the embodiment of an insidious contract from which there is no release. This is the true meaning of subjectivity, compromised at birth, weaned upon the most Oedipal of bad faiths. It bears the sign of the asymmetry of power inscribed upon its brow & dreams constantly of becoming its opposite. And from this stems every impulse & logic of resistance. 9 10 THE ALIENIST TENDENCY A breach has been made with the past, bringing into perspective new aspects of alienation: the morphology of a dead technical civilisation in the fi ctional process of resurrection! And we are returning again to the “honesty of thought & feeling”? This holographic world is being shaken out of its torpor by a four-billion- year-old technology.
    [Show full text]
  • Procreation Is a Murder: the Case for Voluntary Human Extinction
    Procreation Is a Murder -The Case for Voluntary Human Extinction by Anti Procreation If destruction is violence, creation, too, is violence. Procreation, therefore, involves violence. The creation of what is bound to perish certainly involves violence. -Mahatma Gandhi !1 The Anti-natalist Manifesto1 We were forcefully brought into existence even though we weren’t asked to be born, nor consented thereto. This is unsolicited. Our parents brought us into existence knowing that every human dies very well, without a shadow of guilt. How can’t procreation with knowledge it would lead to death sooner or later, well within 130 years a murder?2 Even if we choose not to call it a murder, it’s because it’s more heinous crime, not less heinous crime than murder. Murder only make death happen a few decades earlier of somebody who was condemned to death by procreation; whereas procreation condemns nonexistent person to life and death, making the victim suffer up to about 120 years and die.3 If 1 This manifesto have been published on Reddit /r/antinatalism and Amazon Kindle Store under the pen name ‘antiprocreation’, I edited a little bit for this book 2 https://answers.yahoo.com/question/index? qid=20070815053516AAwtavs 3 Crisp, Quentin S, ANTINATALISM: A THOUGHT EXPERIMENT, Living In The Future, Issue 2, http://www.litfmag.net/issue-2/anti-natalism-a- thought-experiment/ !2 murder is a crime, procreation is a sin.4 The consequence of every procreation is fatal and tragic.5 Every maternity ward is a crematorium.6 Lack of capacity to give consent do not mean somebody can inflict any action to the person that lacks the capacity to give informed consent.
    [Show full text]
  • Feminist Philosophy Quarterly
    Feminist Philosophy Quarterly Volume 1 | Issue 2 Article 3 2015 Queer Earth Mothering: Thinking Through The Biological Paradigm of Motherhood Justin Morris McMaster University, [email protected] Recommended Citation Morris, Justin. 2015. "Queer Earth Mothering: Thinking Through the Biological Paradigm of Motherhood."Feminist Philosophy Quarterly1, (2). Article 3. doi:10.5206/fpq/2015.2.3. Morris: Queer Earth Mothering Queer Earth Mothering: Thinking Through the Biological Paradigm of Motherhood1 Justin Morris Abstract I consider Christine Overall’s (2012) proposal that counteracting the ecological threats born from overconsumption and overpopulation morally obligates (most) Westerners to limit their procreative output to one child per person. I scrutinize what Overall finds valuable about the genetic link in the parent- child relationship through the complementary lenses of Shelley M. Park’s (2013) project of “queering motherhood” and the ecofeminist concept of “earth mothering.” What comes of this theoretical mix is a procreative outlook I define as queer earth mothering (QEM): an interrogative attitude for identifying the ways in which anti-ecological and heteronormative ideologies seep into maternal praxis. I argue that QEM has potential to relocate the value(s) of the putative parent-child relationship, change attitudes toward adoptive motherhood for the better, and shed light on the reality that procreative decisions in affluent contexts can and will rebound with devastating environmental consequences on both present and future populations if left unabated. My hope is that with QEM as our guide for thinking through the biological paradigm of motherhood we will be in a much better position to appreciate why affluent prospective parents should (generally speaking) favour adoption over biological reproduction.
    [Show full text]
  • Remembering and Forgetting in Ancient Greek Literature Thesis
    Open Research Online The Open University’s repository of research publications and other research outputs Tracing the Establishment of Political Society: Remembering and Forgetting in Ancient Greek Literature Thesis How to cite: Raudnitz, Sophie (2018). Tracing the Establishment of Political Society: Remembering and Forgetting in Ancient Greek Literature. PhD thesis The Open University. For guidance on citations see FAQs. c 2017 The Author https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/ Version: Version of Record Link(s) to article on publisher’s website: http://dx.doi.org/doi:10.21954/ou.ro.0000d19a Copyright and Moral Rights for the articles on this site are retained by the individual authors and/or other copyright owners. For more information on Open Research Online’s data policy on reuse of materials please consult the policies page. oro.open.ac.uk Sophie Elizabeth Raudnitz Tracing the establishment of political society: remembering and forgetting in ancient Greek literature A thesis submitted for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Classical Studies, Faculty of Arts and Social Sciences The Open University October 2017 Abstract This thesis explores the connection between memory and the formation of political society in ancient Greek literature. It is grounded in the notion that memory is a political process: its narratives are shaped by the social and political groups to which we belong. In turn, what and how we remember plays a role in shaping and reshaping those same groups. The thesis examines three ‘memory texts’: the Odyssey, which contains a moment in which forgetting is tied explicitly to political progress; the Trojan Women, a play driven by the urge to remember and memorialise as a way of trying to retain political identity; and the Theaetetus, which not only contains the first known attempt to create a model of memory but also ‘remembers’ the Apology.
    [Show full text]
  • Lists of the Virtues
    Etica & Politica / Ethics & Politics, XVII, 2015, 2, pp. 74-93 Lists of the Virtues Sophie-Grace Chappell The Open University Philosophy sophie-grace.chappell ABSTRACT Virtuous action is action according to the virtues. But which are the virtues? What might be our basis for a list of virtues? In this paper I consider some of the possible answers that have been offered, reviewing material from Plato and Aristotle and the New Testament, also from Philippa Foot, Rosalind Hursthouse, Alasdair MacIntyre, and Linda Zagzebski. KEYWORDS Virtue, Plato, Aristotle, naturalism, eudaimonism, exemplarism, Philippa Foot, Rosalind Hursthouse, Alasdair MacIntyre, Linda Zagzebski. I Virtue ethics tells us to act “in accordance with virtue, by which I mean contrary to no virtue.”1But which are the virtues? Broadly, we might agree with Aristotle Nicomachean Ethics 1106b36that nothing can be a moral virtue unless it is “a disposition of choice”, a character-trait that works to transmit our values into our actions; but consensus looks harder to come by when we try to get beyond this rather simple and obvious necessary condition. Or perhaps we will not even get this far: Hume notoriously defines a virtue as any trait the disinterested contemplation of which produces in us “the pleasing sentiment of approbation”.2As is well-known, this seems to capture a much wider class of traits than Aristotle’s necessary condition does. Beyond these points, one obvious problem for virtue ethics is the relativist worry wherethe virtue ethicist gets her list of virtues from: “what historical enquiry discloses is the situatedness of all enquiry, the extent to which what are taken to be the standards of truth and of rational justification in the contexts of 1 P.
    [Show full text]
  • Child-Focused Arguments Against Procreation
    Child-focused Arguments Against Procreation Andrew Pearson Central European University Submitted in partial fulfilment of the requirements for a Master’s Degree in Philosophy Supervisor: Simon Rippon CEU eTD Collection [Type here] Acknowledgements I wish to thank the following people for questions and conversations relating to antinatalism and previous drafts of this essay: Hanoch Ben-Yami, Emma Bullock, Sam Dumitriu, Daniel Hanson Dzah, Philip Goff, Mike Griffin, Marek Iwaniak, Yuk-Pui Lam, Brian McLean, Andres Moles, Laura Nicoara, Jasmine Opie, Edi Pavlovic, José Ricon, Simon Rippon, Andrew Sabisky, Ben Southwood, and David Weberman. Furthermore, I wish to thank José Ricon, Liam Shields, and Simon Rippon for comments on previous drafts and sections of this essay. Given the subject matter and my pro-natalist conclusions, it would perhaps also be appropriate to thank my parents, Tim and Karen Pearson, for bringing me into existence. Beyond that, I thank them for their support - emotional and otherwise - during my time studying for this degree. CEU eTD Collection i Table of Contents Introduction ............................................................................................................................................ 1 The Asymmetry Argument ....................................................................................................................... 3 Terminology and Conceptual Clarification ............................................................................................ 3 Optimistic Asymmetries
    [Show full text]