Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, Volume 50

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, Volume 50 Created on 1 March 2016 at 9.58 hours page i OXFORDSTUDIESINANCIENTPHILOSOPHY Created on 1 March 2016 at 9.58 hours page ii page - is blank Created on 1 March 2016 at 9.58 hours page iii OXFORDSTUDIES INANCIENT PHILOSOPHY EDITOR:VICTORCASTON VOLUMEL 3 Created on 1 March 2016 at 9.58 hours page iv 3 Great Clarendon Street, Oxford, , United Kingdom Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University’s objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide. Oxford is a registered trade mark of Oxford University Press in the UK and in certain other countries © Except where otherwise stated, Oxford University Press, The moral rights of the authors have been asserted First Edition published in Impression: All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, without the prior permission in writing of Oxford University Press, or as expressly permitted by law, by licence, or under terms agreed with the appropriate reprographics rights organization. Enquiries concerning reproduction outside the scope of the above should be sent to the Rights Department, Oxford University Press, at the address above You must not circulate this book in any other form and you must impose this same condition on any acquirer Published in the United States of America by Oxford University Press Madison Avenue, New York, NY , United States of America British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data Data available Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data Oxford studies in ancient philosophy.— Vol. l ().—Oxford: Clarendon Press; New York: Oxford University Press, – v.; cm. Annual. Philosophy, Ancient—Periodicals. B.O .′—dc. – AACR MARC-S ISBN –––– (hbk.) ISBN –––– (pbk.) Printed in Great Britain by Clays Ltd, St Ives plc Links to third party websites are provided by Oxford in good faith and for information only. Oxford disclaims any responsibility for the materials contained in any third party website referenced in this work Created on 1 March 2016 at 9.58 hours page v ADVISORYBOARD Professor Julia Annas, University of Arizona Professor Rachel Barney, University of Toronto Professor Susanne Bobzien, All Souls College, Oxford Professor Riccardo Chiaradonna, Università degli Studi Roma Tre Professor Alan Code, Stanford University Professor Dorothea Frede, Universität Hamburg Professor Brad Inwood, Yale University Professor A. A. Long, University of California, Berkeley Professor Martha Nussbaum, University of Chicago Professor David Sedley, University of Cambridge Professor Richard Sorabji, King’s College, University of London, and Wolfson College, Oxford Professor Gisela Striker, Harvard University Professor Christopher Taylor, Corpus Christi College, Oxford Contributions and books for review should be sent to the Editor, Professor Victor Caston, Department of Philosophy, University of Michigan, South State Street, Ann Arbor, MI -, USA (e-mail [email protected]). Contributors are asked to observe the ‘Notes for Contributors to Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy’, printed at the end of this volume. Up-to-date contact details, the latest version of Notes for Con- tributors, and publication schedules can be checked on the Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy website: www.oup.co.uk/philosophy/series/osap Created on 1 March 2016 at 9.58 hours page vi page - is blank Created on 1 March 2016 at 9.58 hours page vii EDITORIAL With this volume of Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, the baton has passed again and a new editorship begun. The first thing I would like to do is warmly thank the outgoing editor, Brad Inwood, for making the transition as smooth as it could be and for all his help and encouragement. Throughout the process, he has been the very model of good judgement, taste, and remarkable efficiency, in every way an ideal to aspire towards. If I am able to replicate even some of his virtues, I will be well satisfied. I would also like to thank the Advisory Board for their con- tinuing support and advice and to welcome several new members. In addition to Brad Inwood, who as outgoing editor will join the Board, there will be three new members: Rachel Barney (University of Toronto), Riccardo Chiaradonna (Università degli Studi Roma Tre), and Alan Code (Stanford University). I look forward to work- ing together with the Board in the coming years to maintain the high standards that have become the hallmark of the series. Less visible, but no less essential, are the contributions of people who work behind the scenes, above all our anonymous readers, who are the true unsung heroes of this endeavour. In my career, I have rarely seen reports of this kind: expert, rigorous, and tough- minded, as one might expect, yet also remarkably constructive and aimed at improving the submission, whether for our pages or for those ultimately in another series. It is a privilege to work with col- leagues with such a strong sense of professionalism. Finally, I would like to express my gratitude for the generous support, moral as well as material, provided by the Departments of Philosophy and Classical Studies at the University of Michigan, and by Peter Momtchiloff and his staff at Oxford University Press, who have always worked to achieve the highest standards in the pro- duction of our volumes. Created on 1 March 2016 at 9.58 hours page viii page - is blank Created on 1 March 2016 at 9.58 hours page ix CONTENTS Parmenides’ Likely Story THOMASKJELLERJOHANSEN The Moral and Literary Character of Hippias in Plato’s Hippias Major FRANCOV.TRIVIGNO Why the Philosopher Kings Will Believe the Noble Lie CATHERINEROWETT Aristotle on Truth-Bearers DAVIDCHARLESANDMICHAILPERAMATZIS The Stoic Argument from oikeiōsis JACOBKLEIN Alexander against Galen on Motion: A Mere Logical Debate? ORNAHARARI Rational Assent and Self-Reversion: A Neoplatonist Response to the Stoics URSULACOOPE Common Sense and Extra Powers: A Discussion of Anna Marmodoro, Aristotle on Perceiving Objects KLAUSCORCILIUS Index Locorum Created on 1 March 2016 at 9.58 hours page x page x is blank Created on 1 March 2016 at 11.05 hours page 1 PARMENIDES’LIKELYSTORY THOMASKJELLERJOHANSEN T relationship between the way of Truth and the way of opinion (doxa) in Parmenides continues to exercise scholars. At its crudest the problem is this: the way of Truth tells us that being is one and changeless, and the only thing that can be thought and talked about, yet the way of doxa develops a cosmology premissed on change and plurality. How can Parmenides do both? This paper has another go at the question. It argues that being and the cosmos are related as model to likeness in a way that al- lows the cosmos to have some degree of being and intelligibility. Parmenides lays out criteria of intelligible discourse which are paradigmatically met by being. By partially fulfilling those cri- teria the cosmos comes to resemble being and thereby achieves a degree of intelligibility and reality. The cosmology reads in signi- ficant ways like a precursor to the likely story of Plato’s Timaeus. This idea is not new. Indeed, already Proclus in his commen- tary on the Timaeus ( ) quotes Parmenides (B and B ) as saying the same thing, only ‘being obscure because of his poetic © Thomas Kjeller Johansen I am most grateful to Edward Hussey, James Lesher, and Richard McKirahan for their generous comments and criticisms, as well as to the Editor, Victor Caston, and two anonymous readers. In the words of W. K. C. Guthrie, A History of Greek Philosophy, ii. The Preso- cratic Tradition from Parmenides to Democritus (Cambridge, ), : ‘Why should Parmenides take the trouble to narrate a detailed cosmogony when he has already proved that opposites cannot exist and there can be no cosmogony because plurality and change are inadmissible conceptions?’ Procl. In Tim. i. – Diehl. Works that make the connection with the Ti- maeus without developing it include U. von Wilamowitz-Möllendorf, ‘Lesefrüchte’, Hermes, (), –; J. A. Palmer, Plato’s Reception of Parmenides [Reception] (Oxford, ), ; D. W. Graham, The Texts of Early Greek Philosophy: The Com- plete Fragments and Selected Testimonies of the Major Presocratics, pt. (Cambridge, ), . A. Finkelberg, ‘Being, Truth and Opinion in Parmenides’ [‘Being’], Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie, (), – at n. , draws the ana- logy with Platonic myths in the Republic which have some truth in them. Palmer’s valuable study Reception, in particular, has done much to show the fruitfulness of Plato’s readings of Parmenides, but does not discuss how a notion of ‘likely account’ might find purchase in Parmenides. J. Bryan, Likeness and Likelihood in the Pre- socratics and Plato [Likeness] (Cambridge, ), like Proclus, sees a reference in Created on 1 March 2016 at 11.05 hours page 2 Thomas Kjeller Johansen expression’. The suggestion, however, has never been fully worked out or assessed. This is the task of the present paper. The programme The goddess first sets out her programme of instructing a young man (kouros) in B . –: χρεὼ δέ σε πάντα πυθέσθαι ἠμὲν Ἀληθείης εὐπειθέος ἀτρεμὲς ἦτορ ἠδὲ βροτῶν δόξας, ταῖς οὐκ ἔνι πίστις ἀληθής. ἀλλ᾿ ἔμπης καὶ ταῦτα μαθήσεαι, ὡς τὰ δοκοῦντα χρῆν δοκίμως εἶναι διὰ παντὸς πάντα περῶντα. It is right for you to learn all things, both the unshaken heart of persuasive Truth, and the opinions of mortals, in which there is no true conviction. But nevertheless you shall learn this too, how the things believed should have been believably, all pervading through everything. Almost everything about these lines is disputed, but this much seems initially clear. There is a contrast between Truth understood as unalterable and convincing, and the beliefs of human beings which carry no true conviction. Nonetheless, the goddess says the young man should learn how it would be (or was) necessary or right for things to be believed acceptably or believably (dokimōs).
Recommended publications
  • Plato's Cratylus
    Cambridge University Press 0521584922 - Plato’s Cratylus David Sedley Frontmatter More information PLATO’S CRATYLUS Plato’s Cratylus is a brilliant but enigmatic dialogue. It bears on a topic, the relation of language to knowledge, which has never ceased to be of central philosophical importance, but tackles it in ways which at times look alien to us. In this radical reappraisal of the dialogue, Professor Sedleyargues that the etymologieswhich take up well over half of it are not an embarrassing lapse or semi-private joke on Plato’s part. On the contrary,if taken seriouslyas theyshould be, theyare the keyto understanding both the dialogue itself and Plato’s linguistic philosophymore broadly.The book’s main argument is so formulated as to be intelligible to readers with no knowledge of Greek, and will have a significant impact both on the studyof Plato and on the history of linguistic thought. david sedley is Laurence Professor of Ancient Philosophyat the Universityof Cambridge. His work has ranged over most periods and subject areas of Greek and Roman philosophy, including a number of editions of philosophical texts preserved on papyrus. He has been a visiting professor at Princeton, Berkeley, Yale and Cornell, and in2004 will be the Sather Professor at Berkeley. He is the author of Lucretius and the Transformation of Greek Wisdom (Cambridge 1998) and (with A. A. Long) The Hellenistic Philosophers (Cambridge 1987), as well as editor of The Cambridge Companion to Greek and Roman Philosophy (Cambridge 2003). He has been editor of Classical Quarterly (1986–92) and, since 1998,ofOxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • MICHAEL FREDE Michael Johannes Frede 1940–2007
    MICHAEL FREDE Michael Johannes Frede 1940–2007 WHEN MICHAEL JOHANNES FREDE died (11 August 2007), by drowning in the Corinthian Gulf at a beach near Itea below Delphi, Greece, the world of ancient philosophy lost the most accomplished philosopher and scholar, and one of the most distinguished and influential teachers, of the generation of specialists in this field internationally who began their careers in the 1960s and 1970s. He was born 31 May 1940, in Kreuzberg, a working-class district of Berlin, the first child of Roman Catholic parents (a second, Stefanie, was born several years later). He was brought up in Germany and educated there through the Ph.D. and beyond, emigrating later, first to the United States in 1971, then to the United Kingdom, where he was Professor of the History of Philosophy at Oxford University and Fellow of Keble College from 1991 until he chose to retire two years before required, in 2005. In 1943, at the age of two, the apartment building where his family lived was reduced to rubble in an Allied bombing attack while his mother had taken him out for a walk in his carriage, so the family had to move, first to Lippstadt in Westphalia and then in the early 1950s to Hamburg, where Frede attended the Sankt Ansgar-Gymnasium, a Jesuit school, studying classics and the classical languages (Abitur 1959). At university, he studied first in Munich (1959–60) then back in Hamburg (1960–2), where he became a student of Günther Patzig; he rejoined Patzig at Göttingen in 1963 to complete his Ph.D., after a momentous year (1962–3) at Oxford, on Patzig’s suggestion and with his assistance, as a visiting research student, working on his dissertation on Plato’s Sophist, in consul- tation with G.
    [Show full text]
  • STOIC and CHRISTIAN CONCEPTIONS of HAPPINESS Dr
    STOIC AND CHRISTIAN CONCEPTIONS OF HAPPINESS Dr. David Naugle Introduction With reference to the Western concept of courage, the "theologian of culture" Paul Tillich (1886-1965) once wrote that Stoicism is "the only real alternative to Christianity in the Western world."1 Affinities between these two Weltanschauungen not only make a comparison between their respective views of courage possible, but the same may be done with regard to their outlooks on happiness as well. In the popular imagination at least, Christians in general and Christian "saints" in particular are stereotypically imaged as "stoical," which, according to the dictionary, refers to those marked by "austere indifference to joy, grief, pleasure, or pain."2 Historically, this impression is neither unjustified nor wholly inaccurate, for views of Christian character have been greatly affected by interaction with the Stoic teaching throughout the centuries.3 For example, with only minor modification, Richard Tarnas' generic description of Stoicism could seemingly be applied to Christianity as well. In the Stoic view, all reality was pervaded by an intelligent divine force, the logos or universal reason which ordered all things. Man could achieve genuine happiness only by attuning his life and character to this all- powerful providential wisdom. To be free was to live in conformity with God's will, and what mattered finally in life was the virtuous state of the soul, not the circumstances of the outer life. The Stoic sage, marked by 1 Paul Tillich, The Courage To Be (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1952), p. 9. 2 Webster's New World Dictionary of the American Language, College Edition (1962), s.
    [Show full text]
  • LOGIC AROUND the WORLD on the Occasion of 5Th Annual Conference of the Iranian Association for Logic
    LOGIC AROUND THE WORLD On the Occasion of 5th Annual Conference of the Iranian Association for Logic Edited by: Massoud Pourmahdian Ali Sadegh Daghighi Department of Mathematics & Computer Science Amirkabir University of Technology In memory of Avicenna, the great Iranian medieval polymath who made a major contribution to logic. LOGIC AROUND THE WORLD On the Occasion of 5th Annual Conference of the Iranian Association for Logic Editors: Massoud Pourmahdian, Ali Sadegh Daghighi Cover Design: Ali Sadegh Daghighi Page Layout: Seyyed Ahmad Mirsanei Circulation: 500 Price: 6 $ ISBN: 978-600-6386-99-7 سرشناسه: کنفرانس ساﻻنه ی انجمن منطق ایران )پنجمین : ۷۱۰۲م.= ۰۹۳۱ : تهران( Annual Conference of the Iranian Association for Logic (5th : 2017 : Tehran) عنوان و نام پدیدآور: Logic around the World : On the Occasion of 5th Annual Conference of the Iranian Association for Logic / edited by Massoud Pourmahdian, Ali Sadegh Daghighi. مشخصات نشر: قم : اندیشه و فرهنگ جاویدان، ۶۹۳۱= ۷۱۶۲م. مشخصات ظاهری: ۷۵۱ ص. شابک: 978-600-6386-99-7 وضعیت فهرست نویسی: فیپا یادداشت: انگلیسی. موضوع: منطق ریاضی-- کنگره ها موضوع: Logic, Symbolic and Mathematical – Congresses شناسه افزوده: پورمهدیان، مسعود، ۶۹۳۱ -، ویراستار شناسه افزوده: Pourmahdian, Massoud شناسه افزوده: صادق دقیقی، علی، ۶۹۱۵ -، ویراستار شناسه افزوده: Sadegh Daghighi, Ali رده بندی کنگره: ۶۹۳۱ ۳ک/ BC ۶۹۵ رده بندی دیویی: ۵۶۶/۹ شماره کتابشناسی ملی: ۳۳۴۶۳۷۳ © 2017 A.F.J. Publishing This work is subject to copyright. All rights are reserved, whether the whole or part of the material is concerned, specifically the rights of translation, reprinting, reuse of illustrations, recitation, broadcasting, reproduction on microfilm or in any other way, and storage in data banks.
    [Show full text]
  • Professor Alan Kim's CV
    ALAN KIM Dept. of Philosophy Stony Brook University Stony Brook, NY 11794 [email protected] Appointments 2019-present Associate Professor of Philosophy, Stony Brook University 2013-2019 Assistant Professor of Philosophy, Stony Brook University 2011-2013 Senior Lecturer in Philosophy, Dartmouth College 2008-2011 Visiting Assistant Professor of Philosophy, Colgate University 2007-2008 Visiting Assistant Professor of Philosophy, Hamilton College 2000-2007 Assistant Professor of Philosophy, University of Memphis Education 1993-2001 Ph.D. in Philosophy (Dean’s Honor List), McGill University 1986-1990 B.A. in Philosophy (Departmental Honors), Haverford College 1998-2000 Fulbright Fellow, University of Heidelberg 1990-1991 Doctoral Student (East Asian Languages & Literatures), UCLA Dissertation “Original Fracture: Plato in the Philosophies of Paul Natorp and Martin Heidegger” Directors: Stephen Menn, Philip Buckley Areas of Specialization Ancient Philosophy, esp. Plato and Aristotle German Philosophy, esp. Kant, neo-Kantianism, Husserl, Heidegger Areas of Competence Existentialism, Philosophy of Technology, Philosophy of Literature, Classical Chinese Thought, History of Philosophy, Philosophy of Psychology Awards Fulbright Full Grant & seven-month renewal, Heidelberg, Germany (1998-2000) Stony Brook University AHLSS Faculty Research Award (2018) Colgate University Research Council Publication Grant (2009-10) Colgate University Research Council Discretionary Grant (2009-10) McGill University Dean’s Honor List (2001) KIM: 2/10 J.W. McConnell McGill Major Research Fellowship (1997) Gordon H. Eberts McGill Major Research Fellowship (1996) Publications Books • Selves in Dialogue: Authenticity, Autonomy, and the Socratic Art of Living. [Under contract with SUNY Press] • The Brill Companion to German Platonism. xii, 388 pp. Volume editor. Brill Publishing, Leiden, Netherlands (2019) The fourteen contributors include such leading scholars as Manfred Baum, Richard Bett, Francisco Gonzalez, André Laks, François Renaud, and Thomas Szlezák.
    [Show full text]
  • Deductions and Reductions Decoding Syllogistic Mnemonics
    Entelekya Logico-Metaphysical Review Vol 2 No 1 May 2018: 5-39 ___________________________________________________________ Deductions and Reductions Decoding Syllogistic Mnemonics JOHN CORCORAN SUNY: University at Buffalo DANIEL NOVOTNÝ University of South Bohemia KEVIN TRACY Christendom College Research Article Submitted: 12.05.2018Accepted: 21.06.2018 Abstract: The syllogistic mnemonic known by its first two words Barbara Celarent introduced a constellation of ter- Metaphysical Review minology still used today. This concatenation of nineteen - o words in four lines of verse made its stunning and almost unprecedented appearance around the beginning of the thirteenth century, before or during the lifetimes of the lo- gicians William of Sherwood and Peter of Spain, both of whom owe it their lasting places of honor in the history of syllogistic. The mnemonic, including the theory or theories it encoded, was prominent if not dominant in syllogistics for the next 700 years until a new paradigm was estab- Entelekya Logic lished in the 1950s by the great polymath Jan Łukasiewicz, ___________________________________________________________ JOHN CORCORAN University at Buffalo, College of Arts and Sciences, Department of Philosophy 119 Park Hall, Buffalo, NY 14260-4150, USA [[email protected]] [Corresponding Author] DANIEL NOVOTNÝ University of South Bohemia, Faculty of Theology, Department of Philosophy and Religious Studies České Budějovice, 370-01, CZ [[email protected]] KEVIN TRACY Christendom College, Department of Classical and Early Christian Studies Front Royal, VA 22630-6534, USA [[email protected]] 6 John Corcoran, Daniel Novotný, Kevin Tracy a scholar equally at home in philosophy, classics, mathe- matics, and logic. Perhaps surprisingly, the then-prominent syllogistic mnemonic played no role in the Łukasiewicz work.
    [Show full text]
  • Front Matter
    Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-11355-7 - Ancient Models of Mind: Studies in Human and Divine Rationality Edited by Andrea Nightingale and David Sedley Frontmatter More information ANCIENT MODELS OF MIND How does god think? How, ideally, does a human mind function? Must a gap remain between these two paradigms of rationality? Such questions exercised the greatest ancient philosophers, including those featured in this book: Socrates, Plato, Aristotle, the Stoics and Ploti- nus. This volume encompasses a series of studies by leading scholars, revisiting key moments of ancient philosophy and highlighting the theme of human and divine rationality in both moral and cognitive psychology. It is a tribute to Professor A. A. Long, and reflects multiple themes of his own work. andrea nightingale is Professor of Classics and Comparative Literature at Stanford University. She is the author of Genres in Dia- logue: Plato and the Construct of Philosophy (1995), Spectacles of Truth in Classical Greek Philosophy: Theoria in its Cultural Context (2004), and “Once out of Nature”: Augustine on Time and the Body (forthcom- ing). She has won a Guggenheim Fellowship, an ACLS Fellowship, and a fellowship at the Stanford Humanities Center. She has been a Stanford Fellow (2004–6) and is presently serving as a Harvard Senior Fellow of the Hellenic Center (2009–2013). david sedley is Laurence Professor of Ancient Philosophy at the University of Cambridge, where he is also a Fellow of Christ’s College. He is the author of The Hellenistic Philosophers (1987,with A. A. Long), Lucretius and the Transformation of Greek Wisdom (1998), Plato’s Cratylus (2003), The Midwife of Platonism: Text and Subtext in Plato’s Theaetetus (2004), and Creationism and its Critics in Antiquity (2007), based on his 2004 Sather Lectures.
    [Show full text]
  • Space in Hellenistic Philosophy
    Graziano Ranocchia, Christoph Helmig, Christoph Horn (Eds.) Space in Hellenistic Philosophy Space in Hellenistic Philosophy Critical Studies in Ancient Physics Edited by Graziano Ranocchia Christoph Helmig Christoph Horn ISBN 978-3-11-036495-8 e-ISBN 978-3-11-036585-6 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data A CIP catalog record for this book has been applied for at the Library of Congress. Bibliographic information published by the Deutsche Nationalbibliothek The Deutsche Nationalbibliothek lists this publication in the Deutsche Nationalbibliografie; detailed bibliographic data are available on the Internet at http://dnb.dnb.de. © 2014 Walter de Gruyter GmbH, Berlin/Boston Printing and binding: CPI books GmbH, Leck ♾ Printed on acid-free paper Printed in Germany www.degruyter.com Acknowledgements This volume has been published with the financial support of the European Research Council (ERC) and the National Research Council of Italy (CNR). Thanks are due to Aurora Corti for her editorial work and to Sergio Knipe for the linguis- tic revision of the manuscript. Table of Contents Abbreviations IX Introduction 1 Keimpe Algra Aristotle’s Conception of Place and its Reception in the Hellenistic Period 11 Michele Alessandrelli Aspects and Problems of Chrysippus’ Conception of Space 53 Teun Tieleman Posidonius on the Void. A Controversial Case of Divergence Revisited 69 David Konstan Epicurus on the Void 83 Holger Essler Space and Movement in Philodemus’ De dis 3: an Anti-Aristotelian Account 101 Carlos Lévy Roman Philosophy under
    [Show full text]
  • Ancient Skepticism: Pyrrhonism Diego E
    Philosophy Compass 6/4 (2011): 246–258, 10.1111/j.1747-9991.2011.00391.x Ancient Skepticism: Pyrrhonism Diego E. Machuca* Consejo Nacional de Investigaciones Cientı´ficas y Te´cnicas Abstract Pyrrhonism was one of the two main ancient skeptical traditions. In this second paper of the three-part series devoted to ancient skepticism, I present and discuss some of the issues on Pyrrho- nian skepticism which have been the focus of much attention in the recent literature. The topics to be addressed concern the outlooks of Pyrrho, Aenesidemus, and Sextus Empiricus. In the first paper of this three-part series on ancient skepticism, I offered a general pre- sentation of the ancient skeptical traditions as well as an overview of recent translations and general studies. With this framework in place, the present paper deals with some vexed questions concerning the stances of Pyrrho, Aenesidemus, and Sextus Empiricus. For reasons of space, the discussion will be selective and it will not always be possible to go into detail about the issues tackled. 1. Pyrrho Most recent scholarship on Pyrrho of Elis (360–270 BC) continues to divide between two main interpretations of his outlook, which may be called ‘practical’ and ‘theoretical’. The first interpretation affirms that Pyrrho’s motivation was exclusively or mainly ethi- cal.1 This view finds support in some passages in Diogenes Laertius and particularly in Cicero, who does not refer to Pyrrho as a skeptic, but invariably portrays him as a moral- ist – as someone who considered virtue as the only good and who was admired for his lifestyle (Academica II 130; On Moral Ends III 11–2, IV 43, 49, 60; On Duties I 6).
    [Show full text]
  • A History of Quantification
    A History of Quantification Daniel Bonevac September 15, 2011 Aristotle (384–322 BC), the founder of the discipline of logic, also founded the study of quantification. Normally, Aristotle begins a topic by reviewing the common opinions, including the opinions of his chief predecessors. In logic, however, he could not adopt the same strategy; before him, he reports, “there was nothing at all” (Sophistical Refu- tations 183b34–36). Aristotle’s theory dominated logical approaches to quantification until the nineteenth century. That is not to say that others did not make important contributions. Medieval lo- gicians elaborated Aristotle’s theory, structuring it in the form familiar to us today. They also contemplated a series of problems the theory generated, devising increas- ingly complex theories of semantic relations to account for them. Textbook treatments of quantification in the seventeenth and nineteenth centuries made important contribu- tions while also advancing some peculiar theories based on medieval contributions. Modern quantification theory emerged from mathematical insights in the middle and late nineteenth century, displacing Aristotelian logic as the dominant theory of quantifiers for roughly a century. It has become common to see the history of logic as little more than a prelude to what we now call classical first-order logic, the logic of Frege, Peirce, and their successors. Aristotle’s theory of quantification is nevertheless in some respects more powerful than its modern replacement. Aristotle’s theory com- bines a relational conception of quantifiers with a monadic conception of terms. The modern theory combines a monadic conception of quantifiers with a relational theory of terms.
    [Show full text]
  • Department Newsletter, 2012
    Yale Department of Classics Summer 2012 Greetings from the Chair — Anne Amory and Beautiful New England weather has finally arrived. Life in Phelps Hall has slowed to a walking pace, Adam Parry Lecture and we were delighted, on May 21, to put on The Department of Classics, in academic finery and celebrate the graduation of 10 partnership with Yale Comparative hard working seniors, 5 new PhDs, and a bumper Literature, announces a new lecture crop of new MAs and MPhils. series named for Anne Amory Parry and The year began, in July, with a conference Adam Parry, who were (respectively) organized by Egbert Bakker on the theme members of the Departments of Classics “Authorship, Authority, and Authenticity in at UMass Amherst and Yale at the time Archaic and Classical Greek Song”; March of their deaths in France in June 1971. wrapped up with a three-day symposium on Each an accomplished scholar of Homer, “Marginality, Canonicity, Passion,” in which Irene with wide-ranging interests in literature, Peirano and Pauline Leven, together with many both classical and beyond, the Parrys Yale alumni and other distinguished scholars, gave papers. The emphasis was were supporters of literary culture and on conversation as much as on listening: Jay Fisher, John Matthews, Barbara of women’s education. They bequeathed Shailor, Kirk Freudenburg, and I helped moderate, and all joined in a rich their library to the Department of discussion pondering both what we do, as Classicists, and what it means Comparative Literature, where it is now (p. 3). We also hosted several events in the “Cultures of the Classical” series housed in Bingham Hall.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle's Syllogistic As a Deductive System
    axioms Article Aristotle’s Syllogistic as a Deductive System Piotr Kulicki Institute of Philosophy, The John Paul II Catholic University of Lublin, 20-950 Lublin, Poland; [email protected] Received: 9 April 2020; Accepted: 15 May 2020; Published: 19 May 2020 Abstract: Aristotle’s syllogistic is the first ever deductive system. After centuries, Aristotle’s ideas are still interesting for logicians who develop Aristotle’s work and draw inspiration from his results and even more from his methods. In the paper we discuss the essential elements of the Aristotelian system of syllogistic and Łukasiewicz’s reconstruction of it based on the tools of modern formal logic. We pay special attention to the notion of completeness of a deductive system as discussed by both authors. We describe in detail how completeness can be defined and proved with the use of an axiomatic refutation system. Finally, we apply this methodology to different axiomatizations of syllogistic presented by Łukasiewicz, Lemmon and Shepherdson. Keywords: Aristotle’s logic; syllogistic; Jan Łukasiewicz; axiomatic system; axiomatic refutation; completeness 1. Introduction Deductive systems of different kinds are the heart of contemporary logic. One could even state that logic itself, as it is understood nowadays, is just a collection of deductive systems appropriate for different kinds of reasoning. Even when ways of reasoning that are usually distinguished from deduction, such as induction or abduction, are considered, they are finally presented in a deduction-like form of a strict system. The theory and methodology of deductive systems is established and well developed, and so is the folklore spread through the community of logicians.
    [Show full text]