Global Development and Its Discontents: Rethinking the Theory and Practice

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Global Development and Its Discontents: Rethinking the Theory and Practice GLOBAL DEVELOPMENT AND ITS DISCONTENTS: RETHINKING THE THEORY AND PRACTICE By Anna Malavisi A DISSERTATION Submitted to Michigan State University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree Philosophy – Doctor of Philosophy 2015 ABSTRACT GLOBAL DEVELOPMENT AND ITS DISCONTENTS: RETHINKING THE THEORY AND PRACTICE By Anna Malavisi Global development is comprised of a system of ideas, policies, institutions and individuals all concerned with the amelioration of the living conditions of those populations living in disadvantaged conditions. According to the Universal Declaration of Human Rights Article 25, Everyone has the right to a standard of living adequate for the health and well-being of himself and of his family, including food, clothing, housing and medical care and Article 22, Everyone is entitled to a social and international order in which the rights and freedoms set forth in this Declaration can be fully realized. So, in a way the system of global development has been set up as a way to respond to these two human rights, first to provide all children, women and men with the fulfillment of basic necessities and second to ensure that the social and international order responds appropriately. However, in the reality this is not so. I argue that if we are really serious about the impact of global development, then this requires a rethinking of the theory and practice. Despite efforts made to contribute to the amelioration of people’s lives in the name of development, human development indicators continue to be alarming: more than a billion people are malnourished, 884 million people do not have access to clean water, basic sanitation is denied to 2.5 billion people and 774 million people cannot read and write. Although the causes of these evident deprivations are not entirely due to development, it could be argued that due to the ineffectiveness of development these situations are not adequately addressed. Some of the problems particular to development include the implementation of inappropriate projects and programs; the dynamics of relationships between the multiple actors who play a role in development often entrenched in power and domination; and poor mechanisms of accountability. This has resulted in trillions of dollars invested in the name of development, but I would argue with poor results. In my dissertation I offer a more in-depth analysis and understanding of the current development paradigm, its theory and practice. There are two fundamental problems in development. First, there is a rather token and weak presence of an ethical dimension and second, the suppression of knowledge or what Boaventura de Sousa Santos calls, “a form of epistemicide.” There is another dimension to the way the global north has imposed a capitalist and imperial order on the global south that is often missed or blatantly ignored. This is epistemological. Therefore, I argue that implementing a strong ethical approach to development and understanding epistemic injustice in development will help to respond to severe global problems such as poverty and hunger in a different way. I particularly focus on neglected tropical diseases (NTD), a group of tropical diseases that occur all over the world but are markedly absent from the affluent countries. Using the example of NTD, I analyze how current development paradigms and approaches fail to address gross injustices such as the health disparities in the treatment and cure of these diseases. My ultimate aim is to offer an analysis of the problem of NTD from a development ethics perspective which intersects with feminist epistemology. From my own analysis which also draws on my experience, I venture to argue that one of the fundamental problems of development theory and practice is grounded in theoretical discussions of knowledge, and how this knowledge is then applied in the practice. First, I introduce an interpretation of global development from a theoretical standpoint as well as its practice. Second, I analyse the situation of NTD, and particularly Chagas Disease as a consequence of the failings of development. Third, I argue for a strong ethical approach in development and propose what a strong ethical approach should entail. Fourth, I discuss the notion of epistemic injustice in global development. Lastly, I offer some recommendations for the practice of development based on a strong ethical approach and epistemic justice. Copyright by ANNA MALAVISI 2015 ACKNOWLEDGMENTS This dissertation would not have been possible without the guidance and encouragement of my advisor, Stephen L. Esquith and my committee members Sandra Harding, Judith Andre and Kristie Dotson. I express my sincere gratitude to them, for their ongoing support and belief that I could actually do this. This dissertation would also not have been possible without the understanding and patience of my three daughters, Bianca, Adriana and Maya, but also my parents, Italo and Mafalda. I also need to express my sincere gratitude to the management and baristas of Grand River Café and Espresso Royale in East Lansing, for supplying me with the coffee and space which enabled me to complete this dissertation. v PREFACE My interest in pursuing a PhD in philosophy comes from a long trajectory working as a development practitioner for 16 years in Bolivia. Over the course of these years having worked in national and international Non-Government Organizations (NGO), and coordinated with other national and international NGOs, bilateral governments, multilateral institutions, corporations and community based organizations I became quite skeptical and despondent about the true impact of our work. Did we really make a difference? Who were the true beneficiaries of development projects? It seemed that so much money was being invested in the name of development with disproportionate results. That is, for the amount of money invested in development programs and projects this should be able to reduce extreme poverty, but in fact this is not the case. For me, one of the problems is the gross absence of ongoing critical analysis and reflection: thinking through some of the very complex issues that arise in development from a perspective grounded in ethical principles. Critical analysis and reflection just wasn’t taking place on the ground. It was frustrating to be part of a system of NGOs where one gets so caught up with writing grants and reports, executing projects, etc. that no time is dedicated to taking a step back, to think through if in fact the work is having any real impact. We had all become cogs in a machine responding to the requirements of the grant, the questions of a reviewer, or the question of where the next round of support will come from. What I also realized was that this kind of development work would continue, since it is so entrenched in the global economic system in which countries continue to invest large amounts of money via bilateral agencies or NGOs. Therefore, it is naïve to think that quashing development theory and practice, as post- and anti-development theorists suggest will lead to any desirable outcome. What is urgently needed is a paradigm shift in the way we approach development.1 More critical voices are 1 I have opted to use the term paradigm throughout my dissertation to best describe what is meant by development. I talk about the development paradigm. Paradigm in this sense is consistent with the dictionary’s definition: a vi needed which would allow for the analysis and reflection of development from an ethical perspective as well as a social, economic, political and cultural one. Bearing witness to the constant shortfalls and limitations of development, some successes but also the failures, I began to question development and to think about it more critically. My questioning highlighted the need for more critical analysis and reflection at large, and in particular, ethics, which was not taking place. This disquietude brought me to the United States to study philosophy! In a world where there is much affluence, there is also much suffering. There are millions of children, women and men who do not have access to clean running water, a safe and secure supply of food, electricity, education and the fulfillment of other human rights, and it is a moral failing on the part of individuals and institutions. For Thomas Pogge, as for me, to do philosophy is to better understand problems we are confronted with on a daily basis. In Pogge’s words, “I continue to believe that philosophers can illuminate what really matters. The best support for this belief comes not from abstract argument. It comes from showing by doing: from working through a problem so as to make evident its importance” (2010, 8). This is my aim; I will work through an aspect of the problem of global development “so as to make evident its importance.” And I write this on behalf of the millions of children, women and men who suffer undeservedly at the hands of a global economic order. But also, for the thousands of women and men working in development in any capacity, in an endeavor to kindle the desire to think beyond the given and the expected. I believe there is an urgent need to shed our complacencies and blinkered views. I entered development work as an idealist who believed that I could bring about some change in the world, who believed that through my work alongside children, women and men from a different culture and from more disadvantaged situations I could contribute to making their lives better. It wasn’t long before I realized the reality, that development is just one big business or a juggernaut as it has been framework containing the basic assumptions, ways of thinking and methodology that are commonly accepted by members of a scientific community. It is also consistent with Thomas Kuhn’s use of paradigm in his influential book; The Structure of Scientific Revolutions.
Recommended publications
  • Dissertation Anthology 2019-20
    DissertatioN ANthology A CollectioN of Philosophy StudeNt DissertatioNs The UNiversity of Liverpool DepartmeNt of Philosophy 2019-20 Authors, Editors aNd Supervisors Authors StepheN Arkley Mia ReNshaw Ashley BoNNell ANNa Ross Joe BoylaNd Sarah Sharp Georgie Campbell JustiNe SolaNo Lucy Chambers Eddie Southcombe ANNa NuNez de Croker George Wood Harry DaymaN Sam WoottoN Marcus Desai Abi HamiltoN Alice GoodwiN Josh Hibbert Josef Grover Jemima HuNt LiNtoN NewtoN Editors Alice GoodwiN Dr Rachael WisemaN Supervisors Chris Bartley JaN JobliNg Rob Booth Ilias Markolefas Barry DaiNtoN RobiN McKeNNa Rebecca DavNall StepheN McLeod Richard GaskiN Thomas Schramme DaNiel Hill Vid SimoNiti PriNtiNg paid for by PhilSoc Table of CoNteNts Editor’s INtroductioN v DissertatioN ANthology vi SelliNg Harm or SelliNg Self: Is harm iNhereNt or coNtiNgeNt to the sex iNdustry? StepheN Arkley 1 BecomiNg EcosyNchroNus: A PromisiNg SolutioN to the CurreNt State of the ENviroNmeNt Ashley BoNNell 4 Self-Respect, Self-Authorship aNd the MeaNs of ProductioN: A Critique of Market Democracy Joe BoylaNd 7 CaN FemiNist EmpaNcipatory Speech be DiscrimiNatory? Georgie Campbell 10 A Critical ANalysis of SimoNe de Beauvoir’s Theory of WomeN’s OtherNess iN The SecoNd Sex Lucy Chambers 13 Why the NoN-ExisteNce of Extra-Terrestrial INtelligeNce is the most CohereNt ANswer to Fermi's Paradox Harry DaymaN 16 Does the Utility of PlaNtiNga’s Free Will DefeNce Need to be recoNsidered iN a way which reflects beliefs about the Diseases of the MiNd? Marcus Desai 19 AN ANswer to the Paradox
    [Show full text]
  • Indigenous Peoples and Epistemic Injustice: Science, Ethics, and Human Rights
    Washington Law Review Volume 87 Number 4 12-1-2012 Indigenous Peoples and Epistemic Injustice: Science, Ethics, and Human Rights Rebecca Tsosie Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.law.uw.edu/wlr Part of the Human Rights Law Commons, and the Indian and Aboriginal Law Commons Recommended Citation Rebecca Tsosie, Indigenous Peoples and Epistemic Injustice: Science, Ethics, and Human Rights, 87 Wash. L. Rev. 1133 (2012). Available at: https://digitalcommons.law.uw.edu/wlr/vol87/iss4/5 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Law Reviews and Journals at UW Law Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Washington Law Review by an authorized editor of UW Law Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. 07 - Tsosie Article.docx (Do Not Delete) 12/7/2012 7:38 PM INDIGENOUS PEOPLES AND EPISTEMIC INJUSTICE: SCIENCE, ETHICS, AND HUMAN RIGHTS Rebecca Tsosie Abstract: This Article explores the use of science as a tool of public policy and examines how science policy impacts indigenous peoples in the areas of environmental protection, public health, and repatriation. Professor Tsosie draws on Miranda Fricker’s account of “epistemic injustice” to show how indigenous peoples have been harmed by the domestic legal system and the policies that guide the implementation of the law in those three arenas. Professor Tsosie argues that the theme of “discovery,” which is pivotal to scientific inquiry, has governed the violation of indigenous peoples’ human rights since the colonial era. Today, science policy is overtly “neutral,” but it may still be utilized to the disadvantage of indigenous peoples.
    [Show full text]
  • European Journal for Philosophy of Religion
    EUROPEAN JOURNAL FOR PHILOSOPHY OF RELIGION VOLUME 6 NUMBER 4 WINTER 2014 ARTICLES C.A.J. COADY Communal and Institutional Trust: Authority in Religion and Politics 1 John COTTINGHAM Authority and Trust: Reflections on Linda Zagzebski’s Epistemic Authority 25 Duncan PRITCHARD & Shane RYAN Zagzebski on Rationality 39 Trent DOUGHERTY Zagzebski, Authority, and Faith 47 Arnon KEREN Zagzebski on Authority and Preemption in the Domain of Belief 61 Jacek WOJTYSIAK Zagzebski on Models of Revelation 77 Charity ANDERSON Epistemic Authority and Conscientious Belief 91 Benjamin MCMYLER Epistemic Authority, Preemption, and Normative Power 101 John SCHWENKLER Tradition as Transmission: A Partial Defense 121 Matthew A. BENTON Believing on Authority 133 Damian LESZCZYŃSKI Inconsistency, Uncertainty and Epistemic Authority 145 Joshue OROZCO & Nathan L. KING Conscientious Self-reflection to the Rescue? 155 Linda ZAGZEBSKI Epistemic Authority and Its Critics 169 BOOK REVIEWS AND NOTICES Paolo Diego Bubbio & Philip Andrew Quadrio (eds). The Relationship of Philosophy to Religion Today Reviewed by Mark Manolopoulos 189 Justin Barrett. Born Believers: The Science of Children’s Religious Belief Reviewed by Aku Visala 193 Charles Taliaferro, Dialogues about God Reviewed by Ulrich Schmidt 199 Fraser Watts (ed.). Creation: Law and Probability Reviewed by Graham Wood 205 COMMUNAL AND INSTITUTIONAL TRUST: AUTHORITY IN RELIGION AND POLITICS C.A.J. COADY University of Melbourne Linda Zagzebski’s book on epistemic authority is an impressive and stimulating treatment of an important topic.1 I admire the way she manages to combine imagination, originality and argumentative control. Her work has the further considerable merit of bringing analytic thinking and abstract theory to bear upon areas of concrete human concern, such as the attitudes one should have towards moral and religious authority.
    [Show full text]
  • Truth, Testimony, and Epistemic Injustice in International Criminal Law
    Emiliano J. Buis (editors) Emiliano J. Morten Bergsmo and Publication Series No. 35 (2019): Editors of this volume: Philosophical Foundations of International Criminal Law: Morten Bergsmo is Director of the Cen- Foundational Concepts tre for International Law Research and Policy Morten Bergsmo and Emiliano J. Buis (editors) (CILRAP). Emiliano J. Buis is Professor at the Facul- This second volume in the series ‘Philosophical Foundations of International Crimi- tad de Derecho and the Facultad de Filosofía nal Law’ zooms in on some of the foundational concepts or principles of the disci- y Letras, Universidad de Buenos Aires, and pline of international criminal law, with a view to exploring their Hinterland beyond holds several teaching and research positions the traditional doctrinal discourse. It contains eight chapters on concepts such as at other academic institutions in Argentina. sovereignty, global criminal justice, international criminal responsibility for individu- als, punishment, impunity and truth. Among the authors in this book are Christoph The Torkel Opsahl Academic EPublisher Concepts Foundational of International Criminal Law: Philosophical Foundations (TOAEP) furthers the objective of excellence Burchard, Christopher B. Mahony, Milinda Banerjee, CHAO Yi, Javier Dondé-Matute, in research, scholarship and education by pub- Barrie Sander, Max Pensky and Shannon E. Fyfe. lishing worldwide in print and through the Internet. As a non-profit publisher, it is firmly The first volume in the series – Philosophical Foundations of International Criminal committed to open access publishing. Law: Correlating Thinkers – correlates the writings of leading philosophers with inter- national criminal law, including chapters on Plato, Cicero, Ulpian, Aquinas, Grotius, TOAEP is named after late Professor Torkel Opsahl (1931–1993), a leading interna- Hobbes, Locke, Vattel, Kant, Bentham, Hegel, Durkheim, Gandhi, Kelsen, Wittgenstein, tional and constitutional law expert in Europe Lemkin, Arendt and Foucault.
    [Show full text]
  • “It Ignores Lived Experience”
    What’s Wrong with “You Say You’re Happy, but ... ” Reasoning? Jason Marsh St. Olaf College In The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy and Disability Edited by David T. Wasserman and Adam Cureton, 2019. Disability-positive philosophers often note a troubling tendency to dismiss what disabled people say about their well-being.1 Here is an example from Elizabeth Barnes: It’s fair to say that most people today think it’s ‘common sense’ that being disabled is less good than being non-disabled ... But most people in the 1950’s thought that it was ‘common sense’ that being gay was less good than being straight. And Europeans in the 1200’s probably would have thought that it was ‘common sense’ that being female was less good than being male ... In her groundbreaking book Epistemic Injustice, Miranda Fricker characterizes ways in which prejudice can cause uniquely epistemic types of harm. One of the main such forms of harm she highlights is testimonial injustice. In cases of testimonial injustice, a speaker is not believed or given due credence (where others would be) specifically because they are a member of a group that is the subject of stigma. (Barnes 2016, 134–135) In effect, Barnes argues that failing to believe physically2 disabled persons when they make positive claims about their well-being often is to commit epistemic injustice. Similarly, Sara Goering notes a “troubling tendency in much mainstream bioethics to discount the views of disabled people” (Goering 2008, 126). According to both authors, then, there is something deeply wrong with common forms of “you say you’re happy, but ..
    [Show full text]
  • “Knower” As an Ethical Concept: from Epistemic Agency to Mutual Recognition
    Feminist Philosophy Quarterly Volume 4 | Issue 4 Article 2 2018 “Knower” as an Ethical Concept: From Epistemic Agency to Mutual Recognition Matthew Congdon Vanderbilt University [email protected] Recommended Citation Congdon, Matthew. 2018. “‘Knower’ as an Ethical Concept: From Epistemic Agency to Mutual Recognition.” Feminist Philosophy Quarterly 4 (4). Article 2. Congdon – “Knower” as an Ethical Concept: From Epistemic Agency to Mutual Recognition “Knower” as an Ethical Concept: From Epistemic Agency to Mutual Recognition1 Matthew Congdon Abstract Recent discussions in critical social epistemology have raised the idea that the concept “knower” is not only an epistemological concept but an ethical concept as well. Though this idea plays a central role in these discussions, the theoretical underpinnings of the claim have not received extended scrutiny. This paper explores the idea that “knower” is an irreducibly ethical concept in an effort to defend its use as a critical concept. In section 1, I begin with the claim that “knower” is an irreducibly normative and social concept, drawing from some ideas in Wilfrid Sellars. In section 2, I argue that one’s being a knower involves demands for various sorts of ethically laden recognition. I develop this thought by arguing that Axel Honneth’s threefold typology of recognition—love, respect, and esteem—finds clear expression within the context of socio-epistemic practice. I conclude in section 3 by arguing that Miranda Fricker’s proposed “analogy” between epistemic and moral perception should be modified to indicate a closer relationship than mere analogy. Keywords: ethics, social epistemology, feminist epistemology, recognition, epistemic injustice What is a “knower”? There is a strand of ancient thought for which this is an essentially ethical question.
    [Show full text]
  • Negative Epistemic Exemplars
    1 Negative Epistemic Exemplars to appear in Sherman & Gouen (eds.), Overcoming Epistemic Injustice: Social and Psychological Perspectives . Rowman & Littlefield. Emily Sullivan, Delft University of Technology Mark Alfano, Delft University of Technology & Australian Catholic University Abstract In this chapter, we address the roles that exemplars might play in a comprehensive response to epistemic injustice. Fricker defines epistemic injustices as harms people suffer specifically in their capacity as (potential) knowers. We focus on testimonial epistemic injustice, which occurs when someone’s assertoric speech acts are systematically met with either too little or too much credence by a biased audience. Fricker recommends a virtue­theoretic response: people who do not suffer from biases should try to maintain their disposition towards naive testimonial justice, and those who find themselves already biased should cultivate corrective testimonial justice by systematically adjusting their credence in testimony up or down depending on whether they are hearing from someone whom they may be biased against or in favor of. We doubt that the prominent admiration­emulation model of exemplarism will be much use in this connection, so we propose two ways of learning from negative exemplars to better conduct one’s epistemic affairs. In the admiration­emulation model, both the identification of what a virtue is and the cultivation of virtues identified thusly proceed through the admiration of virtuous exemplars. We show that this model has serious flaws and argue for two alternatives: the envy­agonism model and the ambivalence­avoidance model. Keywords epistemic virtue, epistemic exemplar, admiration, envy, ambivalence, epistemic injustice Word count: 6285 (6500 maximum) 2 Introduction In this chapter, we address the roles that exemplars might play in a comprehensive response to epistemic injustice.1 Fricker (2007) defines epistemic injustices as harms people suffer specifically in their capacity as (potential) knowers.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Place of Feminist Epistemology in Philosophy of Education
    education sciences Article Knowledge for a Common World? On the Place of Feminist Epistemology in Philosophy of Education Claudia Schumann Department of Education, Stockholm University, Stockholm S-106 91, Sweden; [email protected]; Tel.: +46-816-2000 Academic Editor: Andrew Stables Received: 7 January 2016; Accepted: 3 March 2016; Published: 9 March 2016 Abstract: The paper discusses the place of feminist epistemology in philosophy of education. Against frequently raised criticisms, the paper argues that the issues raised by feminist standpoint theory lead neither to a reduction of questions of knowledge to questions of power or politics nor to the endorsement of relativism. Within the on-going discussion in feminist epistemology, we can find lines of argument which provide the grounds for a far more radical critique of the traditional, narrow notion of objectivity, revealing it as inherently flawed and inconsistent and allowing for the defense of a re-worked, broader, more accurate understanding of objectivity. This is also in the interest of developing a strong basis for a feminist critique of problematically biased and repressive epistemological practices which can further be extended to shed light on the way in which knowledge has become distorted through the repression of other non-dominant epistemic standpoints. Thus, requiring a thorough re-thinking of our conceptions of objectivity and rationality, feminist epistemologies need to be carefully considered in order to improve our understanding of what knowledge for a common world implies in the pluralistic and diverse societies of post-traditional modernity in the 21st century. Keywords: feminist epistemology; situated knowledge; objectivity; relativism 1.
    [Show full text]
  • Epistemic Justice and Epistemic Participation Kate C.S
    Washington University in St. Louis Washington University Open Scholarship Arts & Sciences Electronic Theses and Dissertations Arts & Sciences Spring 5-15-2019 Epistemic Justice and Epistemic Participation Kate C.S. Schmidt Washington University in St. Louis Follow this and additional works at: https://openscholarship.wustl.edu/art_sci_etds Part of the Epistemology Commons, and the Ethics and Political Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Schmidt, Kate C.S., "Epistemic Justice and Epistemic Participation" (2019). Arts & Sciences Electronic Theses and Dissertations. 1787. https://openscholarship.wustl.edu/art_sci_etds/1787 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Arts & Sciences at Washington University Open Scholarship. It has been accepted for inclusion in Arts & Sciences Electronic Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Washington University Open Scholarship. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Washington University in St. Louis Department of Philosophy Program in Philosophy-Neuroscience-Psychology Dissertation Examination Committee: Julia Driver, Chair Anne Margaret Baxley Miranda Fricker Ron Mallon Kit Wellman Epistemic Justice and Epistemic Participation by Kathryn C.S. Schmidt A dissertation presented to The Graduate School of Washington University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy May 2019 Saint Louis, Missouri ©2019, Kathryn C.S. Schmidt Table of Contents Acknowledgments :::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::: v Abstract :::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::: vi Preface ::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::::: ix 1 What's Unjust about \Testimonial Injustice"? :::::::::::::::: 1 1.0.1 Introduction . 1 1.0.2 Criteria . 3 1.1 The Phenomenon of Interest . 5 1.1.1 The Cases . 5 1.1.2 The Disagreement . 6 1.2 Epistemic Injustice as Distributive Injustice . 8 1.2.1 Assessing a Distributive Account .
    [Show full text]
  • REP Knowledge
    Knowledge, Concept of Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy Michael Hannon University of Nottingham Keywords: knowledge; ignorance; justification; scepticism Article Summary The word ‘know’ is exceptional for a number of reasons. It is one of the 10 most commonly used verbs in English, alongside basic verbs like ‘be,’ ‘do,’ ‘say,’ ‘have,’ and ‘go.’ It is also the most frequently used term in epistemic evaluation: we speak of ‘knowing’ far more often than we speak of ‘justification,’ ‘reliability,’ ‘understanding,’ ‘wisdom,’ and other intellectual traits or epistemic properties. Perhaps most strikingly, the word ‘know’ allegedly has a meaning-equivalent in every human language. Unlike almost every other word in English, linguists have identified ‘know’ as one of a very small number of words that are culturally universal (Goddard 2010). These facts suggest that knowledge is deeply important to human life. Knowledge has also held a central place in epistemology. Indeed, the word ‘epistemology’ comes from the Greek word epistêmê, which is often translated as ‘knowledge.’ This is not to say that epistemologists are only interested in knowledge. They also investigate epistemic virtues like open- mindedness and intellectual humility, as well as properties of belief like being rational and justified (among many other things). Still, the enterprise of epistemology has largely been an investigation into the nature, significance, sources, and extent of human knowledge. But what is knowledge? Why do we value it? How is it acquired? And how much of it do we have? In the late 20th century, one of the central questions asked by epistemologists was: When does a true belief count as knowledge? It was widely assumed that knowledge is a form of true belief plus some additional requirement(s), such as justification or reliability.
    [Show full text]
  • Epistemic Injustice and Security
    MASARYK UNIVERSITY Faculty of Social Sciences Department of Political Science Epistemic Injustice and Security Master Thesis David Rypel Supervisor: Mgr. Pavel Dufek, Ph.D. UČO: 415064 Field of Study: Security and Strategic Studies Matriculation Year: 2015 Brno, 2018 Declaration of Originality and Compliance of Academic Ethics I hereby declare that this thesis is my own work. I have identified all material in this text which is not my own work through appropriate referencing and acknowledgement. Where I have quoted from the work of others, I have included the source in the references. Signed: Date: May 30, 2018 Acknowledgements I would like to thank: - Pavel Dufek, supervisor of my thesis, that he trusted me that the topic I selected makes sense. - Debbie Lisle for kindly opening the abyss of critical security studies for me. Without her introduction to margins of international relations, I would have taken the path which led to this thesis much later or never at all. - My parents who allowed me to focus on my studies rather than survival without ever questioning what I do. (I think they do not know that I wrote a bachelor thesis on morality of terrorism.) - My partner for being around and helping me with the list of figures in this thesis. - EU taxpayers and Masaryk University scholarship policy which allowed me to spend almost two years of my studies abroad. Abstract This thesis is concerned with potential benefits of application of the theory of epistemic injustice on cases pertinent to security studies. Its goal was twofold: First, to present the theory of epistemic injustice in the way that will be easily understandable for readers with no background in epistemology.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction: Epistemic Injustice and Recognition Theory
    Feminist Philosophy Quarterly Volume 4 | Issue 4 Introduction 2018 Introduction: Epistemic Injustice and Recognition Theory Paul Giladi Manchester Metropolitan University [email protected] Nicola MicMillan Lancaster University [email protected] Recommended Citation Giladi, Paul, and Nicola McMillan. 2018. “Introduction: Epistemic Injustice and Recognition Theory.” Feminist Philosophy Quarterly 4 (4). Introduction. Giladi and McMillan – Introduction: Epistemic Injustice and Recognition Theory Introduction: Epistemic Injustice and Recognition Theory Paul Giladi and Nicola McMillan First, we would like to thank the editors of Feminist Philosophy Quarterly for allowing us to guest edit a special issue of this exciting journal. The papers comprising this special issue, along with Miranda Fricker’s afterword, were born of an effort by us to start a much-needed conversation between two immensely rich and relevant philosophical traditions: critical social epistemology and recognition theory. We are proud that Feminist Philosophy Quarterly is the venue for the first ever sustained collaboration of research on epistemic injustice and recognition theory. And our coedited volume, titled Epistemic Injustice and the Philosophy of Recognition, is scheduled to appear in print in 2021 with Routledge. It will be the first book on the subject. An important development in contemporary Anglo-American feminist epistemology has been the concept of epistemic injustice, which, as articulated for example by Miranda Fricker, has emerged out of and reinvigorated a rich line of work in feminist epistemology on epistemic exclusion, silencing, subordination, and motivated ignorance, including work by Linda Alcoff, Kristie Dotson, Ishani Maitra, José Medina, and Charles Mills. Another important development in social philosophy, especially in the Continental tradition, has been the philosophy of recognition.
    [Show full text]