Sets - June 24 Chapter 1 - Sets and Functions

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Sets - June 24 Chapter 1 - Sets and Functions Math 300 - Introduction to Mathematical reasoning Summer 2013 Lecture 1: Sets - June 24 Chapter 1 - Sets and Functions Definition and Examples Sets are a \well-defined” collection of objects. We shall not say what we mean by \well-defined” in this course. At an introductory level, it suffices to think of a Set as a collection of objects. Some examples of sets are - • Collection of students taking Math 300, • Collection of all possible speeds that your car can attain, • Collection of all matrices with real entries (Math 308). Examples We mention some mathematical examples which we shall use throughout the course. Keep these examples in mind. • N - the set of natural numbers. Here, N = f1; 2; 3;:::; g • Z - the set of integers. Here, Z = f;:::; −3; −2; −1; 0; 1; 2; 3;:::; g • Q - the set of rational numbers. The set of rational numbers can described as fractions, where the numerator and denominator of the fraction are both integers and the denominator is not equal to zero. • R - the set of real numbers. • R+ - the set of positive real numbers. The objects of the set are called elements, members or points of the set. Usually a set is denoted by a capital letter. The elements of the set are denoted by lowercase letters. The symbol 2 denotes the phrase \belongs to". Let A be a set and let x be an element of the set A. The statement x 2 A should be read as x belongs to the set A. For example, the statement \1 2 N" should be read as \1 belongs to the set of natural numbers". Recall that π is defined to be the ratio of the circumference of a circle to its diameter. The statement \π 2 R" should be read as \π belongs to the set of real numbers". Here are some more useful examples to keep in mind - • E - the set of even integers. Here, the set E = f;:::; −8; −6; −4; −2; 0; 2; 4; 6; 8;:::; g: • O - the set of odd integers. Here, the set O = f;:::; −9; −7; −5; −3; −1; 1; 3; 5; 7; 9;:::; g: 1-1 1-2 Lecture 1: Sets - June 24 Describing a set We mention various ways to describe a set. We will be slightly informal here. However, we hope that our examples are illustrative and convey our thoughts. Listing the elements One way of describing a set is to list all the elements of a set. We separate the elements of a set using commas and enclose the elements within curly brackets. For example, consider the statement A = f3:5; 6; π; 0g The statement says that there is a set A with 5 elements. The elements of this set A are 3; 5; 6; π and 0. The order in which you specify the elements is NOT important. For example, f0; π; 5; 3; 6g also denotes the same set A. Repeating an element is also NOT important. For example, fπ; π; 3; 3; 3; 0; 5; 6; 6; 6g also denotes the same set A. The symbol \2=" should be read as \does not belong to". In our example, 2 2= A, i.e. the element 2 does not belong to the set A. Listing the elements of a set can be done with infinite sets too. We wrote down the set of natural numbers as follows, N = f1; 2; 3;:::g. Here \:::" should be read as \and so on". Here, it is implicit what the phrase\and so on" should be interpreted as. We have given similar descriptions for the set of integers Z, the set of odd integers O and the set of even integers E. However, there might be some sets where it might not be possible to list down all the elements of the set. We need alternate ways to describe such sets. Think about it - Is there a possible way to list out all the elements of R - the set of real numbers ? The answer is NO. It is not possible to list the elements of the set of real numbers R as we had listed out the elements of the set of natural numbers N. Now, is there possible way to list out all the elements of Q ? This is a slightly subtle question. The answer is YES ! We hope to talk about both these questions more in Chapter 4. Conditional definition of a set An alternate way of describing a set is to specify some conditions, that allows us to pick elements from a larger set whose description is already available to us. We provide some illustrative examples. Throughout, we assume that we have already described the set of integers Z. We make use of the symbol \j" which should be read as \such that" Examples : • B = fn 2 Z j 0 < n < 4g. Intrepret the definition of B as follows \The set B is the set of integers n such that n is greater than 0 and less than 4". One can see that B can be written down as f1; 2; 3g. • The set of even integers, E = fa 2 Z j a is a multiple of 2g. Interpret this definition of E as follows - \The set E is the set of integers n such that n is a multiple of 2". • The set of odd integers O = fa 2 Z j a is not a multiple of 2g. Lecture 1: Sets - June 24 1-3 • The set of rational numbers Q = fx 2 R j x = a=b for some a; b 2 Zg. Constructive definition of a set The other systematic way of describing a set is to give a formula or an algorithm to construct the elements of the set. We provide some illustrative examples. Example : • The set of rational numbers Q = fa=b j a; b 2 Zg. • The set of even integers E = f2 · aj a 2 Zg. • The set of odd integers O = f2 · a + 1 j a 2 Zg Set operations Universe : Let us be slightly informal here. In most of our questions, there will be a special distinguished set called the \universe" hovering the background. The elements of the sets in question will belong to this special set - the universe. Most often, we will denote the \Universe" by U. In most problems, we will not mention what the universe is and the existence of the universe will be quite implicit. Venn Diagrams Read about Venn diagrams in Wikipedia ! Subset Suppose we have two sets A and B. We say that A is a subset of B - we write A ⊂ B - if every element of A is an element of B. For example, we have N ⊂ Z ⊂ Q ⊂ R. A B 1-4 Lecture 1: Sets - June 24 Equality of sets We say that two sets A and B are equal to each other (and we write A = B) if every element of A is an element of B and every element of B is an element of A. Alternatively, two sets A and B are equal to each other if A ⊂ B and B ⊂ A. Example: Consider the two sets A = f2 · n + 1 j n 2 Zg and B = f2 · n − 1 j n 2 Zg We will prove that A = B. Proof: To prove that A = B, we need to show that A ⊂ B and B ⊂ A. 1. First we show that A ⊂ B. Choose an arbitrary element x 2 A. We will try to show that x 2 B. Since x was an arbitrarily chosen element of A, this would imply that every element of A is an element of B and hence that A ⊂ B. Since x 2 A, there is some integer n such that x = 2 · n + 1. x = 2 · n + 1 = 2 · (n + 1 − 1) + 1 = 2 · (n + 1) − 2 + 1 = 2 · (n + 1) − 1 Substitute m = n + 1, we get that x 2 B. Note that the variable n used in the definition of the sets A and B is just a dummy variable. We could have defined B = f2 · m − 1 j m 2 Zg. We have shown that A ⊂ B. 2. Now we have to show that B ⊂ A. Let x 2 B, i.e. we choose an arbitrary element x in B. This means that there is an integer n such that x = 2 · n − 1. We proceed similarly. x = 2 · n − 1 = 2 · (n − 1 + 1) − 1 = 2 · (n − 1) + 2 − 1 = 2 · (n − 1) + 1 Substitute m = n − 1, we get that x = 2 · m + 1. m is also an integer. Hence we can conclude that x 2 A. Since x was an arbitrary element in B, we can conclude that B ⊂ A. Empty set Another distinguished set is the empty set. In some sense, it is the opposite of the set we called the \Universe". The empty set is the unique set with no elements. The empty set is denoted by ;. Lecture 1: Sets - June 24 1-5 Union Suppose we have two sets A and B. Then we define the union of the sets A and B to be the set that consists of those elements that are either in A or in B. We denote the set by A [ B. We provide the following conditional definition A [ B = fx j x 2 A or x 2 Bg: Example E [ O = Z. A non-example- Let A = f1; 2; 3g and B = f1; 2g be two sets. Consider another set C = fA; Bg is another set, whose elements are sets themselves.
Recommended publications
  • Does the Category of Multisets Require a Larger Universe Than
    Pure Mathematical Sciences, Vol. 2, 2013, no. 3, 133 - 146 HIKARI Ltd, www.m-hikari.com Does the Category of Multisets Require a Larger Universe than that of the Category of Sets? Dasharath Singh (Former affiliation: Indian Institute of Technology Bombay) Department of Mathematics, Ahmadu Bello University, Zaria, Nigeria [email protected] Ahmed Ibrahim Isah Department of Mathematics Ahmadu Bello University, Zaria, Nigeria [email protected] Alhaji Jibril Alkali Department of Mathematics Ahmadu Bello University, Zaria, Nigeria [email protected] Copyright © 2013 Dasharath Singh et al. This is an open access article distributed under the Creative Commons Attribution License, which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original work is properly cited. Abstract In section 1, the concept of a category is briefly described. In section 2, it is elaborated how the concept of category is naturally intertwined with the existence of a universe of discourse much larger than what is otherwise sufficient for a large part of mathematics. It is also remarked that the extended universe for the category of sets is adequate for the category of multisets as well. In section 3, fundamentals required for adequately describing a category are extended to defining a multiset category, and some of its distinctive features are outlined. Mathematics Subject Classification: 18A05, 18A20, 18B99 134 Dasharath Singh et al. Keywords: Category, Universe, Multiset Category, objects. 1. Introduction to categories The history of science and that of mathematics, in particular, records that at times, a by- product may turn out to be of greater significance than the main objective of a research.
    [Show full text]
  • Cantor, God, and Inconsistent Multiplicities*
    STUDIES IN LOGIC, GRAMMAR AND RHETORIC 44 (57) 2016 DOI: 10.1515/slgr-2016-0008 Aaron R. Thomas-Bolduc University of Calgary CANTOR, GOD, AND INCONSISTENT MULTIPLICITIES* Abstract. The importance of Georg Cantor’s religious convictions is often ne- glected in discussions of his mathematics and metaphysics. Herein I argue, pace Jan´e(1995), that due to the importance of Christianity to Cantor, he would have never thought of absolutely infinite collections/inconsistent multiplicities, as being merely potential, or as being purely mathematical entities. I begin by considering and rejecting two arguments due to Ignacio Jan´e based on letters to Hilbert and the generating principles for ordinals, respectively, showing that my reading of Cantor is consistent with that evidence. I then argue that evidence from Cantor’s later writings shows that he was still very religious later in his career, and thus would not have given up on the reality of the absolute, as that would imply an imperfection on the part of God. The theological acceptance of his set theory was very important to Can- tor. Despite this, the influence of theology on his conception of absolutely infinite collections, or inconsistent multiplicities, is often ignored in contem- porary literature.1 I will be arguing that due in part to his religious convic- tions, and despite an apparent tension between his earlier and later writings, Cantor would never have considered inconsistent multiplicities (similar to what we now call proper classes) as completed in a mathematical sense, though they are completed in Intellectus Divino. Before delving into the issue of the actuality or otherwise of certain infinite collections, it will be informative to give an explanation of Cantor’s terminology, as well a sketch of Cantor’s relationship with religion and reli- gious figures.
    [Show full text]
  • Review of Set-Theoretic Notations and Terminology A.J
    Math 347 Review of Set-theoretic Notations and Terminology A.J. Hildebrand Review of Set-theoretic Notations and Terminology • Sets: A set is an unordered collection of objects, called the elements of the set. The standard notation for a set is the brace notation f::: g, with the elements of the set listed inside the pair of braces. • Set builder notation: Notation of the form f::: : ::: g, where the colon (:) has the meaning of \such that", the dots to the left of the colon indicate the generic form of the element in the set and the dots to 2 the right of the colon denote any constraints on the element. E.g., fx 2 R : x < 4g stands for \the set of 2 all x 2 R such that x < 4"; this is the same as the interval (−2; 2). Other examples of this notation are f2k : k 2 Zg (set of all even integers), fx : x 2 A and x 2 Bg (intersection of A and B, A \ B). 2 Note: Instead of a colon (:), one can also use a vertical bar (j) as a separator; e.g., fx 2 R j x < 4g. Both notations are equally acceptable. • Equality of sets: Two sets are equal if they contain the same elements. E.g., the sets f3; 4; 7g, f4; 3; 7g, f3; 3; 4; 7g are all equal since they contain the same three elements, namely 3, 4, 7. • Some special sets: • Empty set: ; (or fg) • \Double bar" sets: 1 ∗ Natural numbers: N = f1; 2;::: g (note that 0 is not an element of N) ∗ Integers: Z = f:::; −2; −1; 0; 1; 2;::: g ∗ Rational numbers: Q = fp=q : p; q 2 Z; q 6= 0g ∗ Real numbers: R • Intervals: ∗ Open interval: (a; b) = fx 2 R : a < x < bg ∗ Closed interval: [a; b] = fx 2 R : a ≤ x ≤ bg ∗ Half-open interval: [a; b) = fx 2 R : a ≤ x < bg • Universe: U (\universe", a \superset" of which all sets under consideration are assumed to be a subset).
    [Show full text]
  • A Multiverse Perspective in Mathematics and Set Theory: Does Every Mathematical Statement Have a Definite Truth Value?
    The universe view The multiverse view Dream Solution of CH is unattainable Further topics Multiverse Mathematics A multiverse perspective in mathematics and set theory: does every mathematical statement have a definite truth value? Joel David Hamkins The City University of New York Mathematics, Philosophy, Computer Science College of Staten Island of CUNY The CUNY Graduate Center Meta-Meta Workshop: Metamathematics and Metaphysics Fudan University, Shanghai June 15, 2013 Meta-Meta Workshop, Shanghai June 15, 2013 Joel David Hamkins, New York The universe view The multiverse view Dream Solution of CH is unattainable Further topics Multiverse Mathematics The theme The theme of this talk is the question: Does every mathematical problem have a definite answer? I shall be particularly interested in this question as it arises in the case of set theory: Does every set-theoretic assertion have a definite truth value? Meta-Meta Workshop, Shanghai June 15, 2013 Joel David Hamkins, New York The universe view The multiverse view Dream Solution of CH is unattainable Further topics Multiverse Mathematics Set theory as Ontological Foundation A traditional view in set theory is that it serves as an ontological foundation for the rest of mathematics, in the sense that other abstract mathematical objects can be construed fundamentally as sets. On this view, mathematical objects—functions, real numbers, spaces—are sets. Being precise in mathematics amounts to specifying an object in set theory. In this way, the set-theoretic universe becomes the realm of all mathematics. Having a common foundation was important for the unity of mathematics. A weaker position remains compatible with structuralism.
    [Show full text]
  • Set Notation and Concepts
    Appendix Set Notation and Concepts “In mathematics you don’t understand things. You just get used to them.” John von Neumann (1903–1957) This appendix is primarily a brief run-through of basic concepts from set theory, but it also in Sect. A.4 mentions set equations, which are not always covered when introducing set theory. A.1 Basic Concepts and Notation A set is a collection of items. You can write a set by listing its elements (the items it contains) inside curly braces. For example, the set that contains the numbers 1, 2 and 3 can be written as {1, 2, 3}. The order of elements do not matter in a set, so the same set can be written as {2, 1, 3}, {2, 3, 1} or using any permutation of the elements. The number of occurrences also does not matter, so we could also write the set as {2, 1, 2, 3, 1, 1} or in an infinity of other ways. All of these describe the same set. We will normally write sets without repetition, but the fact that repetitions do not matter is important to understand the operations on sets. We will typically use uppercase letters to denote sets and lowercase letters to denote elements in a set, so we could write M ={2, 1, 3} and x = 2 as an element of M. The empty set can be written either as an empty list of elements ({})orusing the special symbol ∅. The latter is more common in mathematical texts. A.1.1 Operations and Predicates We will often need to check if an element belongs to a set or select an element from a set.
    [Show full text]
  • Warren Goldfarb, Notes on Metamathematics
    Notes on Metamathematics Warren Goldfarb W.B. Pearson Professor of Modern Mathematics and Mathematical Logic Department of Philosophy Harvard University DRAFT: January 1, 2018 In Memory of Burton Dreben (1927{1999), whose spirited teaching on G¨odeliantopics provided the original inspiration for these Notes. Contents 1 Axiomatics 1 1.1 Formal languages . 1 1.2 Axioms and rules of inference . 5 1.3 Natural numbers: the successor function . 9 1.4 General notions . 13 1.5 Peano Arithmetic. 15 1.6 Basic laws of arithmetic . 18 2 G¨odel'sProof 23 2.1 G¨odelnumbering . 23 2.2 Primitive recursive functions and relations . 25 2.3 Arithmetization of syntax . 30 2.4 Numeralwise representability . 35 2.5 Proof of incompleteness . 37 2.6 `I am not derivable' . 40 3 Formalized Metamathematics 43 3.1 The Fixed Point Lemma . 43 3.2 G¨odel'sSecond Incompleteness Theorem . 47 3.3 The First Incompleteness Theorem Sharpened . 52 3.4 L¨ob'sTheorem . 55 4 Formalizing Primitive Recursion 59 4.1 ∆0,Σ1, and Π1 formulas . 59 4.2 Σ1-completeness and Σ1-soundness . 61 4.3 Proof of Representability . 63 3 5 Formalized Semantics 69 5.1 Tarski's Theorem . 69 5.2 Defining truth for LPA .......................... 72 5.3 Uses of the truth-definition . 74 5.4 Second-order Arithmetic . 76 5.5 Partial truth predicates . 79 5.6 Truth for other languages . 81 6 Computability 85 6.1 Computability . 85 6.2 Recursive and partial recursive functions . 87 6.3 The Normal Form Theorem and the Halting Problem . 91 6.4 Turing Machines .
    [Show full text]
  • 2.5. INFINITE SETS Now That We Have Covered the Basics of Elementary
    2.5. INFINITE SETS Now that we have covered the basics of elementary set theory in the previous sections, we are ready to turn to infinite sets and some more advanced concepts in this area. Shortly after Georg Cantor laid out the core principles of his new theory of sets in the late 19th century, his work led him to a trove of controversial and groundbreaking results related to the cardinalities of infinite sets. We will explore some of these extraordinary findings, including Cantor’s eponymous theorem on power sets and his famous diagonal argument, both of which imply that infinite sets come in different “sizes.” We also present one of the grandest problems in all of mathematics – the Continuum Hypothesis, which posits that the cardinality of the continuum (i.e. the set of all points on a line) is equal to that of the power set of the set of natural numbers. Lastly, we conclude this section with a foray into transfinite arithmetic, an extension of the usual arithmetic with finite numbers that includes operations with so-called aleph numbers – the cardinal numbers of infinite sets. If all of this sounds rather outlandish at the moment, don’t be surprised. The properties of infinite sets can be highly counter-intuitive and you may likely be in total disbelief after encountering some of Cantor’s theorems for the first time. Cantor himself said it best: after deducing that there are just as many points on the unit interval (0,1) as there are in n-dimensional space1, he wrote to his friend and colleague Richard Dedekind: “I see it, but I don’t believe it!” The Tricky Nature of Infinity Throughout the ages, human beings have always wondered about infinity and the notion of uncountability.
    [Show full text]
  • How Gödel Transformed Set Theory, Volume 53, Number 4
    How Gödel Transformed Set Theory Juliet Floyd and Akihiro Kanamori urt Gödel (1906–1978), with his work on of reals and the like. He stipulated that two sets the constructible universe L, established have the same power if there is a bijection between the relative consistency of the Axiom of them, and, implicitly at first, that one set has a Choice and the Continuum Hypothesis. higher power than another if there is an injection KMore broadly, he secured the cumulative of the latter into the first but no bijection. In an hierarchy view of the universe of sets and ensured 1878 publication he showed that R, the plane R × R, the ascendancy of first-order logic as the framework and generally Rn are all of the same power, but for set theory. Gödel thereby transformed set the- there were still only the two infinite powers as set ory and launched it with structured subject mat- out by his 1873 proof. At the end of the publica- ter and specific methods of proof as a distinctive tion Cantor asserted a dichotomy: field of mathematics. What follows is a survey of prior developments in set theory and logic in- Every infinite set of real numbers ei- tended to set the stage, an account of how Gödel ther is countable or has the power of the marshaled the ideas and constructions to formu- continuum. late L and establish his results, and a description This was the Continuum Hypothesis (CH) in its of subsequent developments in set theory that res- nascent context, and the continuum problem, to re- onated with his speculations.
    [Show full text]
  • Black Hole Math Is Designed to Be Used As a Supplement for Teaching Mathematical Topics
    National Aeronautics and Space Administration andSpace Aeronautics National ole M a th B lack H i This collection of activities, updated in February, 2019, is based on a weekly series of space science problems distributed to thousands of teachers during the 2004-2013 school years. They were intended as supplementary problems for students looking for additional challenges in the math and physical science curriculum in grades 10 through 12. The problems are designed to be ‘one-pagers’ consisting of a Student Page, and Teacher’s Answer Key. This compact form was deemed very popular by participating teachers. The topic for this collection is Black Holes, which is a very popular, and mysterious subject among students hearing about astronomy. Students have endless questions about these exciting and exotic objects as many of you may realize! Amazingly enough, many aspects of black holes can be understood by using simple algebra and pre-algebra mathematical skills. This booklet fills the gap by presenting black hole concepts in their simplest mathematical form. General Approach: The activities are organized according to progressive difficulty in mathematics. Students need to be familiar with scientific notation, and it is assumed that they can perform simple algebraic computations involving exponentiation, square-roots, and have some facility with calculators. The assumed level is that of Grade 10-12 Algebra II, although some problems can be worked by Algebra I students. Some of the issues of energy, force, space and time may be appropriate for students taking high school Physics. For more weekly classroom activities about astronomy and space visit the NASA website, http://spacemath.gsfc.nasa.gov Add your email address to our mailing list by contacting Dr.
    [Show full text]
  • Universe Design Tool User Guide Content
    SAP BusinessObjects Business Intelligence platform Document Version: 4.2 – 2015-11-12 Universe Design Tool User Guide Content 1 Document History.............................................................13 2 Introducing the universe design tool...............................................14 2.1 Overview.....................................................................14 2.2 Universe design tool and universe fundamentals.........................................14 What is a universe?...........................................................14 What is the role of a universe?...................................................15 What does a universe contain?...................................................15 About the universe window..................................................... 17 Universe design tool install root path...............................................17 2.3 How do you use the universe design tool to create universes?...............................18 How do objects generate SQL?...................................................18 What types of database schema are supported?......................................19 How are universes used?.......................................................19 2.4 Who is the universe designer?..................................................... 20 Required skills and knowledge...................................................20 What are the tasks of the universe designer?.........................................21 2.5 The basic steps to create a universe................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Large Universe Subset Predicate Encryption Based on Static Assumption (Without Random Oracle)
    Large Universe Subset Predicate Encryption Based on Static Assumption (without Random Oracle) Sanjit Chatterjee and Sayantan Mukherjee Department of Computer Science and Automation, Indian Institute of Science, Bangalore fsanjit,[email protected] Abstract. In a recent work, Katz et al. (CANS'17) generalized the notion of Broadcast Encryption to define Subset Predicate Encryption (SPE) that emulates subset containment predicate in the encrypted do- main. They proposed two selectively secure constructions of SPE in the small universe setting. Their first construction is based on a parameter- ized assumption while the second one is based on DBDH. Both achieve constant-size secret key while the ciphertext size depends on the size of the privileged set. They also showed some black-box transformation of SPE to well-known primitives like WIBE and ABE to establish the richness of the SPE structure. This work investigates the question of large universe realization of SPE scheme based on static assumption in the standard model. We pro- pose two constructions both of which achieve constant-size secret key. First construction SPE1, instantiated in composite order bilinear groups, achieves constant-size ciphertext and is proven secure in a restricted ver- sion of selective security model under the subgroup decision assumption (SDP). Our main construction SPE2 is adaptively secure in the prime order bilinear group under the symmetric external Diffie-Hellman as- sumption (SXDH). Thus SPE2 is the first large universe instantiation of SPE to achieve adaptive security without random oracle. Both of our constructions have efficient decryption function suggesting their practical applicability. Thus primitives like WIBE and ABE resulting through the black-box transformation of our constructions become more practical.
    [Show full text]
  • Cantor’S Paradise and the Parable of Frozen Time
    Cybernetics and Human Knowing. Vol. 16, nos. 1-2, pp. xx-xx Virtual Logic Cantor’s Paradise and the Parable of Frozen Time Louis H. Kauffman1 I. Introduction Georg Cantor (Cantor, 1941; Dauben, 1990) is well-known to mathematicians as the inventor/discoverer of the arithmetic and ordering of mathematical infinity. Cantor discovered the theory of transfinite numbers, and an infinite hierarchy of ever-larger infinities. To the uninitiated this Cantorian notion of larger and larger infinities must seem prolix and astonishing, given that it is difficult enough to imagine infinity, much less an infinite structure of infinities. Who has not wondered about the vastness of interstellar space, or the possibility of worlds within worlds forever, as we descend into the microworld? It is part of our heritage as observers of ourselves and our universe that we are interested in infinity. Infinity in the sense of unending process and unbounded space is our intuition of life, action and sense of being. In this column we discuss infinity, first from a Cantorian point of view. We prove Cantor's Key Theorem about the power set of a set. Given a set X, the power set P(X) is the set of all subsets of X. Cantor's Theorem states that P(X) is always larger than X, even when X itself is infinite. What can it mean for one infinity to be larger than another? Along with proving his very surprising theorem, Cantor found a way to compare infinities. It is a way that generalizes how we compare finite sets. We will discuss this generalization of size in the first section of the column below.
    [Show full text]