Book Reviews

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Book Reviews Book Reviews Robin ATTFIELD. Environmental Ethics: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2018. 137 pp. Robin Attfield’s Environmental Ethics: A Very Short Introduction is urgently needed at a time of climate change, the sixth mass extinction, destruction of the last remaining natural environments and the emergence of the Anthropocene. Attfield is a prominent scholar in environmental ethics and has contributed extensively to the field since the early 1980s, providing him with a long-term view of its development. His work ranges from biocen- trism to Christian attitudes, from global warming to loss of biodiversity. He is professor emeritus at Cardiff University and very qualified to write such an introduction. Attfield is successful in providing a comprehensive introduction to the key areas of environmental ethics. Instead of summarising all these themes and arguments here, I wish instead to explore the contents by raising two important themes that are promi- nent in the book. Firstly, raising and clarifying conceptual complexities is one of the key tasks of environmental ethics. Attfield recognises this and introduces the reader to important concepts such as ‘nature’, ‘the environment’, ‘moral standing’, and ‘value’, which are not as axiomatic as they might first seem and are open to different interpreta- tions. Thus, environmental ethics provides a more nuanced and careful analysis of envi- ronmental issues. Secondly, Attfield shows that the themes of environmental ethics are not only important philosophically, but also have significant real-world implications. Indeed, as Attfield puts it “[…] recognizing the moral standing of living creatures does not make moral decisions impossible, or morality impractical. Instead, it enriches our understanding of the context of action and of moral decision-making” (22). Attfield analyses the ability of main ethical theories (contract models, virtue ethics, deontology and consequentialism) to recognise and respond to environmental problems. Unlike the style of introductory literature in general, Attfield takes a clear stance on the type of environmental ethics approach he endorses, promoting biocentric consequentialism (according to which it is the state of affairs (e.g. flourishing) of all living organisms that matters) over the other ethical theories. However, he goes on to emphasise that “[e] nvironmental ethics is rather a dialogue between many stances and voices, and certainly not a single stance” (59). In addition, he emphasises that environmental ethics is not simply focused on non-humans, but is also concerned with the intersection between the environment and humans. One of the prominent issues is the moral standing of future ETHICAL PERSPECTIVES 26, no. 3 (2019): 535-552. © 2019 by Centre for Ethics, KU Leuven. All rights reserved. doi: 10.2143/EP.26.3.3287344 ETHICAL PERSPECTIVES – SEPTEMBER 2019 human generations and the many ways the environment contributes to human wellbeing. The key underlying message is that the broadening of our ethical realm is not only pos- sible but also necessary. The latter half of the book demonstrates this wide reach of environmental ethics and goes beyond intramural discussions to cover environmental policy and practice, social and political movements, and how religions across the world have affected envi- ronmental ethics. Among other things, Attfield provides an interesting analysis of the content of the UN Sustainable Development Goals, discusses the practice and limits of ecological preservation, evaluates ecofeminist theories (which explore the intersection of feminism and environmental thought), environmental justice movements (which rep- resent the battle of disadvantaged social groups against their disproportionate position in suffering from environmental burdens) and how theistic religions have promoted the idea of environmental stewardship. Finally, Attfield explores one of the defining prob- lems of humanity: climate change. As scientific consensus on climate change and its effects is intensifying, so too are the ethical theories provided by environmental ethics. Adaptation, mitigation and compensation strategies are explored and different tools for making sense of moral responsibility over climate change offered by philosophers are introduced. Importantly, Attfield not only looks at the responsibilities of humans (col- lective and individual), but also how the inclusion of non-human beings would fit and effect climate ethics. For Attfield, climate change is truly a test-case for environmental ethics displaying its practical relevance and importance. Despite the book being short, Attfield is successful in representing the great depth and volume of environmental ethics in a very concise space and in a balanced manner. Not only does the reader gain a good basic understanding of environmental ethics, but Attfield also manages to explain complex phenomena and theories with comprehensible ease. I do have a few minor critical remarks to make. Throughout the book, Attfield makes clear to the reader his position in environmental ethics, which is biocentric con- sequentialism. This approach can have both positive and negative aspects. On the pos- itive side, it provides the book with a clearer narrative as many of the ethical problems and dilemmas are not left out in the open without a clear ethical solution. This can be particularly helpful for those readers who are new to philosophy. At the same time, however, promoting one ethical standpoint or theory over another too overtly in an introductory work can leave little space for the reader to decide which arguments are most convincing to them. Of course, deontologists, virtue ethicists and ecocentrists disagree with Attfield’s position that biocentric consequentialism offers the best solu- tions for environmental problems. My critical remark is not directed towards the fact that Attfield clearly displays his environmental ethical position. On the contrary, I find that this works very well (and this is how environmental ethics works). I am simply pointing out that greater emphasis could have been placed on the fact that this is the writer’s position, that others (including the reader) might not agree, and that many of the competing theories have convincing (if not equally convincing) arguments, their point of focus often simply being different. In addition, I felt that the chapter on — 536 — Ethical Perspectives 26 (2019) 3 BOOK REVIEWS deontology in particular was slightly rushed compared to the other theories covered, which meant that environmental interpretations of deontology were not really discussed. Furthermore, I would have included the term ‘environmental ethics’ in the ‘some key concepts’ chapter. Defining ‘environmental ethics’ would have been useful, as another very similar term, ‘environmental philosophy’, is also being used by the philo- sophical community. Environmental philosophy is a broader field within philosophy under which environmental ethics belongs as a subfield. This categorisation is important because environmental ethics leaves other important evironmental topics such as phi- losophy of science, philosophy of technology, aesthetic and ontological evaluation of the environment outside its scope. Or has the field been misnamed altogether after the influential journal in the field called Environmental Ethics, as suggested by Eugene Har- grove in Foundations of Environmental Ethics (New Jersey: Prentice Hall,1989, 3)? Having some background information about the term ‘environmental ethics’ and its evolution would help any newcomers to better navigate the field. This short introduction is particularly timely and I would recommend it to anyone not yet familiar with environmental ethics and even to those more knowledgeable of the field, who simply wish to have a recap of the main issues. Books like these are particu- larly useful for such a purpose, as the subject area of environmental ethics is particularly broad. It is truly impressive how Attfield manages to condense such large issues so succinctly into such a short book. Linnea Luuppala University of Helsinki Russell BLACKFORD. The Tyranny of Opinion: Conformity and the Future of Liberalism. London: Bloomsbury Academic, 2019. 244 pp. Freedom of thought and freedom of expression are two of the oldest freedoms liberal- ism has fought for. It all began with the demand for freedom of religious beliefs and their expression, as far back as the 16th and 17th centuries. Politics, art and many other domains followed. Reasons for demanding respect for these basic freedoms are varied, and many philosophers have theorized them in influential books. One of these philoso- phers was John Stuart Mill, whose On Liberty was one of the most influential defences of the freedom of expression. Thus, it is not a surprise that Russell Blackford’s recently published book draws heavily on Mill, the less so as Blackford presents himself as an Enlightenment Liberal, a term which also fits Mill. Chapters 2, 3 and 4 of his book provide a good discussion of some of Mill’s main points and the problems they might pose, especially with regard to the correct interpretation of the famous ‘harm principle’. Blackford notices two blind spots in Mill’s analysis. On the one hand, Mill mainly, if not exclusively, insists on the expression of opinions, thus neglecting a great part of, for example, artistic expression. On the other hand, and this is more important for Blackford, Mill does not account sufficiently for informal and private
Recommended publications
  • A Synthetic Approach to the Ground of Global Justice
    ISSN 2392-0890, no 8/2017, pp. 54-62, DOI: 10.5604/01.3001.0012.0388 Modern Stoicism and the Responsibility for the Global Polis PIOTR STANKIEWICZ Institute of Philosophy, University of Warsaw, Krakowskie Przedmieście 3, 00-927 Warsaw, Poland, E-mail: [email protected] Abstract This article outlines the premises and promises of a modern comeback of Stoicism, particularly the question of reinterpretation of the original doctrine, the contemporary intricacies of the principle of “following nature,” and the foundations that modern Stoicism establishes for global responsibility. Key words: Stoicism, modern Stoicism, ethics, virtue ethics, political philosophy, cosmopolitanism, responsibility. There is no doubt today that Stoicism is coming back. The ancient philosophical school established by Zeno and Chrysippus, and immortalized by Seneca, Epictetus and Marcus Aurelius’ is enjoying its second youth. As Massimo Pigliucci puts it: The 21st century is seeing yet another revival of virtue ethics in general and of Stoicism in particular. [...] When it comes more specifically to Stoicism, new scholarly works and translations of classics, as well as biographies of prominent Stoics, keep appearing at a sustained rate. [...] In parallel with the above, Stoicism is, in some sense, returning to its roots as practical philosophy, as the ancient Stoics very clearly meant their system to be primarily of guidance for everyday life, not a theoretical exercise.(Pigliucci, Stoicism) Stankiewicz/Studies in Global Ethics and Global Education/ no 8/2017, pp. 54-62 Just as Pigliucci underscores, what is remarkable about the present boom of interest in Stoicism is that it is not confined to the academia.
    [Show full text]
  • Marcus Aurelius Was a Roman Emperor From
    Marcus Aurelius Roman Emperor and Philosopher Marcus Aurelius was a Roman Emperor from 161-180 A.D, at a time when to be a Roman Emperor really meant being an emperor of almost all of the known world, for Rome’s territory then was at its most expansive. Therefore his job was not a small one. And yet at the same time as ruling the empire, and campaigning against troublesome tribes in what is now central and middle Europe (do you remember him from the start of the Gilm Gladiator?), he was also a philosopher. This did not mean that he just sat around thinking lofty thoughts in his spare time. Rather, the philosophy he chose to study was aimed at helping the individual to live life better, that is with values and a focussed mind. Marcus never wanted any glory – his own writings tell us that the last thing he desired was to be ‘treated like a Caesar’. All he wanted was to perform his duty admirably to his own people, family and, indeed, to himself. It was his favourite philosophy as a way of life, Stoicism, which enabled him to do this. Stoicism was a philosophy practised across the Ancient World for around half a millennium since its foundation by Zeno in the 4th century B.C. Nowadays, of course, we still have the word ‘stoic’ in our own language. It tends to mean someone who ‘ just gets on with things’ and who is rather ‘inGlexible, rigid and even emotionless.’ But, as history obscures so many things from the past, this could not be further from the truth.
    [Show full text]
  • Epictetus Slave and Philosopher
    Epictetus Slave and Philosopher Epictetus was born in modern-day Turkey in 55 A.D. He was born a slave (in fact, his name literally means the ‘one who is owned by another’) and lived in Rome, serving in a wealthy household to Epaphroditus who was the tyrannical Nero’s secretary. Not only was Epictetus a slave, but he was also a cripple. Life must have been difHicult and it was perhaps for this reason that he started to study philosophy and, like Marcus Aurelius, his preferred philosophy was Stoicism. It was in this philosophy that Epictetus found ‘freedom’. Not the kind of freedom one gets from being recognized as no longer being a slave, but the kind of ‘freedom’ which comes from have a purposeful and calm mind. As he studied more and more philosophy, he became the student of a leading Stoic teacher in Rome at that time, called Musonius Rufus. And, before long, Epictetus was teaching Stoicism himself, a fact which greatly annoyed the paranoid and deranged emperor Domitian who, in 93 A.D., banished all philosophers from Rome in case they ever discussed any ideas against his authoritarian rule. Epictetus decided to spend his exile in a town called Nicopolis which is in modern-day Albania, and he certainly kept active, founding his own philosophical school there. This was a place where anyone could come and seek advice about what was troubling him or her in life. Many of Epictetus’ teachings were written down, word for word, by one of his pupils and these are called the Discourses.
    [Show full text]
  • Stoicism, Friendship, and Grief: a Response to Johnson
    Reason Papers Vol. 40, no. 1 Stoicism, Friendship, and Grief: A Response to Johnson Massimo Pigliucci City College of New York Brian Johnson, in his commentary on my effort to update Stoicism,1 provides a cogent critique of ancient Stoicism and a reasonable suggestion for my attempt to define modern Stoicism. I do not (much) disagree with him in terms of his conclusions, which he applies to the specific cases of friendship and grief, but which also hold for all of the Stoic “preferred indifferents.” I do, however, want to push back on two points: (1) the path he takes to arrive at those conclusions, and (2) the notion that all ancient Stoics would have proposed the same approach to friendship and grief that Epictetus takes. To begin with, Johnson points out that, for the Stoics, only virtue is good (agathos), while everything else is either worthy (axia) of choice or to be rejected.2 Hence the famous Stoic distinction between virtue, on the one hand, and preferred and dispreferred “indifferents” (i.e., everything else), on the other hand. However jarring the word “indifferent” may sound to modern ears, we need to be clear about what it means on the Stoic view. Things like wealth, health, education, friendship, love, and so forth are indifferents in the specific sense that they do not make us morally better or worse persons. The Stoic project is, fundamentally, one of moral self- improvement. This can be seen, for instance, in Epictetus: “What decides whether a sum of money is good? The money is not going to tell you; it must be the faculty that makes use of such impressions— reason” (Discourses I, 1.5).
    [Show full text]
  • View of Things
    Stoicisminplainenglish Ancient Stoic texts in modern English Thecompleteworksofepictetus(5volumes) and action? • Your goal is happiness and good StoicFoundations • Is there a choice between knowledge fortune. (DiscoursesBook1) and anxiety? Stoic Foundations revolves around 10 themes • Should you study logic? Why? which are also repeated in other places • Choose to be faithful. StoicFreedom throughout Discourses. These are: • Choose habits that fight impressions. • Concern yourself with only what is in • Show yourself to be worthy. (DiscoursesBook4) • Choose to be skillful. In Stoic Freedom, Epictetus shows us how to your power achieve freedom. How to be free • Be content to let things happen as they StoicTraining irrespective of what happens to us? In these do brilliant discourses, Epictetus shows us how • Your thinking, not the externals, drives (DiscoursesBook 3) to be free and what a free person looks like. your behaviour Stoic Training shows how to train ourselves • A free person is not in conflict with • Do not place value on external things in Stoic philosophy. anyone. • Don't give in to your anger or animal • Stoic training aims to make you • A free person is patient. instincts excellent as a human being. • A free person is not envious. • You can handle anything; always act • Stoic training consists of three • A free person is not anxious. your best disciplines: desire, action, and assent. • A free person is pure. • Learn to think properly and logically • Stoic training consists only of dealing • A free person is steadfast. • Practice, not knowledge, results in with one’s choices. • A free person chooses what to reveal progress • Train your mind to want whatever about themselves and when.
    [Show full text]
  • Manual of Reformed Stoicism
    Manual of Reformed Stoicism Piotr Stankiewicz Series in Philosophy Copyright © 2020 Vernon Press, an imprint of Vernon Art and Science Inc, on behalf of the author. All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording, or otherwise, without the prior permission of Vernon Art and Science Inc. www.vernonpress.com In the Americas: In the rest of the world: Vernon Press Vernon Press 1000 N West Street, C/Sancti Espiritu 17, Suite 1200, Wilmington, Malaga, 29006 Delaware 19801 Spain United States Series in Philosophy Library of Congress Control Number: 2019957903 ISBN: 978-1-62273-648-5 DISCLAIMER This is a philosophical book – it’s purpose is to educate. It is not intended as a substitute for psychological counseling. If you need help, please do not hesitate to see a mental health professional. The author and publisher disclaim any responsibility or liability resulting from the actions advocated or discussed in this book. The purchaser of this book assumes the responsibility for the decisions they take during and/or after reading the book, based on the information in the book. Product and company names mentioned in this work are the trademarks of their respective owners. While every care has been taken in preparing this work, neither the authors nor Vernon Art and Science Inc. may be held responsible for any loss or damage caused or alleged to be caused directly or indirectly by the information contained in it. Every effort has been made to trace all copyright holders, but if any have been inadvertently overlooked the publisher will be pleased to include any necessary credits in any subsequent reprint or edition.
    [Show full text]
  • APA Eastern Division 2018 Meeting Program
    The American Philosophical Association EASTERN DIVISION ONE HUNDRED FOURTEENTH ANNUAL MEETING PROGRAM SAVANNAH CONVENTION CENTER SAVANNAH, GEORGIA JANUARY 3 – 6, 2018 Visit our table at APA Eastern. Offering a 20% pb / 40% hc discount with free shipping to the contiguous U.S. for orders www.sunypress.edu placed at the conference. Lessing and the Enlightenment Failing Desire His Philosophy of Religion Karmen MacKendrick and Its Relation to Eighteenth- Century Thought Unmaking The Making of Americans Henry E. Allison Toward an Aesthetic Ontology E. L. McCallum Satan and Apocalypse And Other Essays in Political The Symbolic Order of the Mother Theology Luisa Muraro Thomas J. J. Altizer Translated by Francesca Novello Edited and with an Introduction Aristotle on God’s Life-Generating by Timothy S. Murphy Power and on Pneuma as Its Vehicle Foreword by Alison Stone Abraham P. Bos Defining Religion Having a Word with Angus Graham Essays in Philosophy of Religion At Twenty-Five Years into His Robert Cummings Neville Immortality The Last Fortress of Metaphysics Carine Defoort and Roger T. Ames, Jacques Derrida and the editors Deconstruction of Architecture March 2018 Francesco Vitale Inheritance in Psychoanalysis Translated by Mauro Senatore Joel Goldbach and James A. Godley, editors Author Meets Critics Session Mystery 101 Friday, January 8th, An Introduction to the 7:00 – 10:00 pm Big Questions and the Limits The Good Is One, of Human Knowledge Its Manifestations Many Richard H. Jones Confucian Essays on Metaphysics, Morals, For Foucault Rituals, Institutions, Against Normative and Genders Political Theory Robert Cummings Neville Mark G. E. Kelly IMPORTANT NOTICES FOR MEETING ATTENDEES SESSION LOCATIONS Please note: this online version of the program does not include session locations.
    [Show full text]
  • Is a Philosophical Belief in Stoicism a Protected Belief Under Section 10 of the Equality Act? Yes It Is, Says London South Employment Tribunal
    Is a philosophical belief in Stoicism a protected belief under section 10 of the Equality Act? Yes it is, says London South Employment Tribunal By Charlotte Hadfield 3PB Barristers Mr S Jackson v Lidl Great Britain Ltd, Case Number 2302259/2019/V Exciting developments in all things Equality Act 2010 from West Croydon, and we’re not talking about the return of the much-missed jerk chicken van. Facts C was dismissed for refusing to apologise for offending his colleagues. C’s position was that he had mixed up his words due to his dyslexia. The offence that he had caused was unintentional. He had refused to apologise, or to apologise sufficiently, for that reason. He asserted that he was being required to communicate in a way that could not be misinterpreted, and that as a Stoic this was something that he could not do. C presented claims of direct disability discrimination and direct discrimination because of religion or belief. C’s case was that he had a strong interest in philosophy and a thorough knowledge of the principles of Stoicism. He told the Tribunal that he believes that there is an objective moral reality to which we are subject and that there are several ethical “values” (wisdom, courage, moderation and justice) to which he must adhere as a consequence of this belief. An important part of his belief is that he is not a “consequentialist”, i.e. the consequences of what he says and does do not prevent him from saying or doing that thing. His evidence, which was accepted by the Tribunal, was that he was striving towards what Stoics call “apatheia”, or a state of equanimity.
    [Show full text]
  • Stoicism and the Art of Happiness (Teach Yourself)
    Donald Robertson is a cognitive-behavioural psychotherapist who specializes in evidence-based approaches to the treatment of anxiety, and the relationship between ancient philosophy and modern psychotherapy, particularly Stoicism and cognitive-behavioural therapy (CBT). He is the author of five books on philosophy and psychotherapy, including Build your Resilience (Hodder & Stoughton, 2012) in the Teach Yourself series and The Philosophy of Cognitive-Behavioural Therapy: Stoic Philosophy as Rational and Cognitive Psychotherapy (Karnac, 2010). Donald was born in Scotland, and lived in England for many years where he ran a busy Harley Street therapy practice, before emigrating to Nova Scotia in Canada. Stoicism and the Art of Happiness Donald Robertson Acknowledgements I’d like to dedicate this book to my wife, Mandy, and to our beautiful daughter, Poppy Louise Robertson. I love you both. I’d also like to thank everyone involved with Stoic Week and the projects initiated by Professor Christopher Gill and Patrick Ussher at the University of Exeter, for their advice, support, and ideas. The Metaphor of the Tree Why, then, do you wonder that good men are shaken in order that they may grow strong? No tree becomes rooted and sturdy unless many a wind assails it. For by its very tossing it tightens its grip and plants its roots more securely; the fragile trees are those that have grown in a sunny valley. It is, therefore, to the advantage even of good men, to the end that they may be unafraid, to live constantly amidst alarms and to bear with patience the happenings which are ills to him only who ill supports them.
    [Show full text]
  • Stoic Pragmatist Ethics in the Time of Pandemic Krzysztof Piotr
    Ethics & Bioethics (in Central Europe), 2021, 11 (1–2), 82–91 DOI:10.2478/ebce-2021-0010 Stoic pragmatist ethics in the time of pandemic Krzysztof Piotr Skowroński1 Abstract The present paper is a response, of sorts, to the challenges of the coronavirus pandemic (COVID) and lockdown that we all must face. We have an idea of what doctors, nurses, teachers, among many of the other professions, do for the general public, but one may ask whether there is something substantial that philosophers and ethicists can offer in these circumstances. The thesis of this paper is that the stoic attitude towards times of trouble and the pragmatist way of finding out what is possible to elevate the Quality of living against all odds, if skilfully interwoven, could be an important tool in keeping mental health in good shape and, additionally, could contribute to the cultural scene at large. If this is the case, stoic pragmatists can indeed offer an interesting example of practical philosophy for many audiences, especially during the pandemic lockdown and, perhaps, for other serious difficulties or problems. To be effective in delivering their message, stoic pragmatists, as most with philosophers today, should enrich their textual and oral modes of traditional transmission of knowledge and become digital- culture public intellectuals that can recognize and reach more general audiences by, among other things, visual modes of digital communication. Keywords: stoic pragmatism, ethics, pandemic, digital culture Stoic ethics and pragmatist ethics: Any points in common? There must be something exceptional in Stoic ethics (in this text, capital “S” refers to the historical Stoicism, small “s” to its contemporary trajectories, and “SP” to stoic pragmatism).
    [Show full text]
  • Theory and Training in Epictetus' Program of Moral Education
    THEORY AND TRAINING IN EPICTETUS’ PROGRAM OF MORAL EDUCATION by Michael Tremblay A thesis submitted to the Department of Philosophy In conformity with the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Queen’s University Kingston, Ontario, Canada (May, 2021) Copyright ©Michael Tremblay, 2021 Abstract This dissertation examines the educational function of training, as contrasted with the study of theory, within Epictetus’ program of moral education. The motivation for this research is that there exists an apparent tension in Epictetus’ moral philosophy. According to Stoicism, knowledge is sufficient for virtue; however, many students of Stoicism have learnt that virtue is the only good, and endorsed this claim as true, and yet fail to act appropriately. Epictetus seems to resolve this problem through the introduction of applied exercises. That Epictetus requires his students to train themselves in this way seems in potential conflict with his moral psychology. In this dissertation, I resolve this tension through three contributions: (1) First, I develop an account of why Epictetus believes moral failure occurs in dedicated students of Stoicism who wish to achieve virtue. It occurs primarily because of two factors, precipitancy and weakness, which impede the progressing student of Stoicism from properly reflecting upon a situation. (2) Second, I argue for a novel explanation of the function of training in Epictetus. Epictetus tells us that training is necessary to ‘digest’ our theory. Building upon this neglected metaphor, I argue that the ‘digestion’ of theory is the process by which students move from weak commitments to general principles (i.e., virtue is the only good), which are vulnerable to instances of precipitancy or weakness, to specific actionable beliefs (i.e., I should not desire this bribe because is not an instance of virtue).
    [Show full text]
  • Stoic Week 2018 Report Part 3: Impact on Well-Being Tim Lebon Overall Findings Impact on Flourishing
    Stoic Week 2018 Report Part 3: Impact on Well-being Tim LeBon This report forms the third part of the report on Stoic Week 2018. Over 600 participants completed a set of questionnaires both at the beginning and end of Stoic week, allowing us to assess the impact of doing Stoic Week on self-reports on well-being and on levels of Stoicism. For the first time we were using SABS 4.0, a longer and more comprehensive measure of a participant’s degree of Stoicism. Overall Findings In terms of improvements in well-being over Stoic Week, the results were similar to previous years, though slightly reduced on some measures. The completion rate was also broadly comparable with previous years. Stoic Stoic Stoic Stoic Stoic Week Week Week Week Week 2018 2017 2016 2015 2014 No of 3702 2870 1803 2503 1953 participants at start Valid 852 689 270 726 566 questionnaires completed at end Increase in 8% 10% 10% 10% 10% Flourishing Increase in 12% 14% 15% 15% 16% Satisfaction with Life Increase in 9.5% 11% 10% 10% 11% Positive Emotions Reduction in 14% 14% 14% 14% 16% Negative Emotions Increase In Stoic 10% 9% 11% 13% 12% Attitudes and Behaviours Completion Rate 23% 24% 15% 29% 29% Table 1: Overall Findings Impact on Flourishing Participants reported on average a 8% overall increase in Flourishingi Table 2 below shows the impact of Stoicism which on each element of Flourishing. 2018 2017% 2016 2015 2014 2013 Flourishing Scale Item % % % % Theme 1. I lead a purposeful and 12 15 15 16 Purpose and meaningful life.
    [Show full text]