Aristotle's Rhetoric As Political Philosophy

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Aristotle's Rhetoric As Political Philosophy Founding Speech: Aristotle’s Rhetoric as Political Philosophy by Tina Rupcic A thesis submitted in conformity with the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Political Science University of Toronto © Copyright by Tina Rupcic 2017 Founding Speech: Aristotle’s Rhetoric as Political Philosophy Tina Rupcic Doctor of Philosophy Department of Political Science University of Toronto 2017 Abstract There is notoriously little agreement in the literature on Aristotle’s Rhetoric. While disputes about most every aspect of Aristotle’s argument abound, most scholars tend to agree on one general point. That is, most read the work as an attempt at discovering and describing the nature of rhetorical persuasion. The present study takes a different view: it maintains that the Rhetoric is better understood as an attempt at replacing the existing teaching and practice of rhetoric with one that is better suited for use within the deliberative institutions of political society. The Rhetoric, on this reading, is a work with a political project. This dissertation contributes to the literature in three distinct ways. First, it attempts to show that there is a significant rhetorical component to some of Aristotle’s most prominent arguments. It argues, among other things, that the first chapter of the work and the taxonomy of rhetoric presented in chapters two and three should not be taken at face value. Second, this study illustrates the extent to which concerns about legislation figure into Aristotle’s attempts at articulating an art of speech. Most readings conceptualize the problem of rhetoric as consisting in the relationship between rhetoric and collective judgment, taking the view that Aristotle’s solution lies in liberating judgment from a rhetorical practice that enmeshes it in some incongruous or inappropriate way. This study ii suggests that preserving the rule of law, protecting a state’s legislative institutions, and cultivating civic virtue, are among Aristotle’s chief concerns. Third, the present work also locates, what it considers to be, Aristotle’s non-rhetorical teaching about the nature of rhetorical persuasion. iii Acknowledgements I wish to thank the members of my committee, Clifford Orwin, Ryan Balot, Ronald Beiner, Edward Andrew, and Waller Newell. To my sisters, since I count you among my most important teachers, there is no better place for me to acknowledge my debt to you than on this page. Thank you for all that you have taught me over the years, and thank you for your unwavering support and encouragement. I dedicate this work to you. iv Table of Contents Chapter 1: Recovering the Politics of Aristotle’s Rhetoric 1 Reading the Rhetoric 9 The Problem of Aristotle’s Rhetoric 12 Rehabilitating the Rhetoric 16 Contemporary Readings: The Rhetoric as Philosophy 20 Contemporary Readings: Politics as Primary 25 The Rhetoric as Political Philosophy 28 Chapter 2: The Political Problem of Rhetoric 38 Stage One: Breaking With Plato 47 Stage Two: Discrediting the Teachers of Speech 53 Behind the Rhetoric 65 Rhetoric and Legislation 78 Rhetoric in the Courts 82 Rhetoric in the Assembly 88 Looking Forward: Putting Rhetoric in its Place 93 Chapter 3: Reconceiving Rhetoric 98 Defining Rhetoric 99 Aristotle’s Three Species of Rhetoric 109 A Moderated View 117 Chapter 4: Putting Rhetoric in the Service of Politics 120 Deliberative Rhetoric (Rhetoric, Chapters 1.4-8) 123 Epideictic Rhetoric (Rhetoric, Chapter 1.9) 143 Judicial Rhetoric (Rhetoric, Chapters 10-15) 160 v Towards a Political Rhetoric 182 Chapter 5: The Path to Persuasion: Aristotle on Human Motivation 187 The Art of Speech and the Causes of Persuasion 189 Movement in Aristotle’s Argument 199 Aristotle on Human Motivation 207 Advantage, Pleasure, and Aristotle's Art of Speech 215 Chapter 6: Conclusion 223 Works Cited 227 vi Chapter 1 Recovering the Politics of Aristotle’s Rhetoric Aristotle’s Rhetoric is a book about speech written at a time when the power of speech could not be underestimated. Citizens of ancient democracies understood that a handful of words properly arranged and aptly delivered could alter the fortunes of private men and determine the fate of entire human societies. Daily experience readily confirmed the former. It was evident to all that individuals skilled in speech could better defend their interests in courts of law and that they could better advance their personal agendas within a political assembly. As for the latter, here history, even if events of the moment did not, afforded ample evidence of the overwhelming influence that a single individual gifted in speech could exert over an entire political community. There is the example of Themistocles who prevailed against common opinion and succeeded in persuading Athenians to abandon their city and put their faith and their fate in their ships, thereby securing the preservation of their people.1 There is Pericles, who in his famous funeral oration inspired Athenians to hold their aggressive course in the war, even though a more moderate approach might have served them better.2 Then there is Peisistratus, a favorite example of Aristotle’s, who established himself as tyrant by successfully convincing Athenians to act against their own best interests.3 These are but three examples of individuals who bent cities to their will with their words. They illustrate that speech is a 1 Herodotus, The Histories, ed. Robert B. Strassler (New York: Anchor Books, 2007), 7.141. 2 Thucydides, The Landmark Thucydides: A Comprehensive Guide to the Peloponnesian War, ed. Robert B. Strassler (New York: Simon & Schuster, 1998), 1.4.13. 3 Aristotle, The Politics, trans. Carnes Lord (Chicago, Ill.: University of Chicago Press, 1984), 1035a20-25. 1 viable source of power and influence, and that it is not a skill to be spurned by anyone seeking influence within political society. The Greeks understood this. Hence, there would have been little need to persuade most Greeks in Aristotle’s day of the utility of developing a facility in public speech. For the older Greeks facility in speech was understood to be something that could not be taught. In the time of Hesiod and Homer eloquence was considered to be a divine gift, a talent bestowed by the gods upon a select few.4 Among these few were counted some of their greatest heroes. If Achilles could throw a spear faster, further, and with perfect accuracy, Odysseus was the man who could persuade the arrogant, the ignorant, and the otherwise intractable, to alter course when they could only see reasons to stay firm. The Greeks recognized the strength of the warrior as well as the strength of intelligence, which often manifested itself as an ability to move men with words. Beginning in the time of Socrates, and certainly by the time of Aristotle, the older view of speech had been entirely displaced by rhetoric, the teaching of which was said to have been invented in Syracuse in the fifth century after the tyrant Thrasybulus had been ejected and democracy was established in his stead.5 Before then, no one, as far as is known, taught speech. Of course, that does not preclude the possibility that some may have practiced rhetoric before that time. Even so, the so-called invention of rhetoric marks the moment when everything changed, because it was at that time that the first teachers of speech emerged. It was then that the gift of eloquence was wrested from the gods by a crop of orators who offered their fire to any man who could pay for it. The 4 Friedrich Solmsen, "The Gift of Speech in Homer and Hesiod," Transactions of the American Philological Association 85(1954); Richard Leo Enos, Greek Rhetoric before Aristotle (Anderson, South Carolina: Parlor Press, 2012). 5 Greek Rhetoric before Aristotle, 100. 2 teachers of rhetoric were in no way coy about precisely what it was they offered their students. They unabashedly offered their students a means of defending their interests and establishing their influence over others: they were celebrated, sought after, and paid well. Before Aristotle began writing the Rhetoric, Plato had already articulated some of the potential hazards of this new teaching.6 In the Gorgias, he makes these concerns clear. On the one hand, he argues that rhetoric is potentially dangerous for those who wield it because it weaves corruption into their souls. On the other hand, and perhaps still more worrisome for Plato, is its effect on its audience in which it implants a passion for injustice. Whether or not Aristotle was similarly concerned about the development of rhetoric is a thornier question. The debate over the value of rhetoric is said to have continued as a particular point of disagreement between Aristotle and Isocrates, a student of Gorgias and the most influential rhetorician of his day. If the reports of ancient chroniclers are to be believed, Aristotle had nothing but contempt for his teachings.7 So much so that he is said to have offered evening courses in rhetoric to the general public to serve as a counterpoint to Isocrates’s teachings. 8 Although these reports are not to be relied upon, one finds evidence of this dispute, and evidence of an anti-rhetorical position more generally, in some of Aristotle’s other writings. His interest in the subject was serious. In addition to 6 Edward Schiappa argues that Plato coined the term rētorikē while writing the Gorgias. He offers two arguments in support of this claim: “the first is that the surviving instances of the word (rētorikē) demonstrate that its use in Plato’s Gorgias is novel. The second is that Plato’s penchant for coining terms ending in (-ikē) makes it highly probable that (rētorikē), like most other terms denoting specific verbal arts, was originally coined by Plato.” Edward Schiappa, "Did Plato Coin Rhetorike," The American Journal of Philology 111, no.
Recommended publications
  • 2. Aristotle's Concept of the State
    Page No.13 2. Aristotle's concept of the state Olivera Z. Mijuskovic Full Member International Association of Greek Philosophy University of Athens, Greece ORCID iD: http://orcid.org/0000-0001-5950-7146 URL: http://worldphilosophynetwork.weebly.com E-Mail: [email protected] Abstract: In contrast to a little bit utopian standpoint offered by Plato in his teachings about the state or politeia where rulers aren`t “in love with power but in virtue”, Aristotle's teaching on the same subject seems very realistic and pragmatic. In his most important writing in this field called "Politics", Aristotle classified authority in the form of two main parts: the correct authority and moose authority. In this sense, correct forms of government are 1.basileus, 2.aristocracy and 3.politeia. These forms of government are based on the common good. Bad or moose forms of government are those that are based on the property of an individual or small governmental structures and they are: 1.tiranny, 2.oligarchy and 3.democracy. Also, Aristotle's political thinking is not separate from the ethical principles so he states that the government should be reflected in the true virtue that is "law" or the "golden mean". Keywords: Government; stat; , virtue; democracy; authority; politeia; golden mean. Vol. 4 No. 4 (2016) Issue- December ISSN 2347-6869 (E) & ISSN 2347-2146 (P) Aristotle's concept of the state by Olivera Z. Mijuskovic Page no. 13-20 Page No.14 Aristotle's concept of the state 1.1. Aristotle`s “Politics” Politics in its defined form becomes affirmed by the ancient Greek world.
    [Show full text]
  • “On Plato's Πολιτεία,” by Stephen Menn, Pp. 1- 55, in Proceedings of the Bosto
    CORRIGENDA Corrigenda belonging to “On Plato’s Πολιτεία,” by Stephen Menn, pp. 1- 55, in Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy, Volume XXI, 2005 (eds. J.J. Cleary and G.M. Gurtler, S.J.). 2006. ISBN 90 04 15353 5 (Pbk), ISBN 90 04 15391 8 (Bound). Due to a series of failures of regular and electronic mail, Stephen Menn’s contribution was printed without his having seen either first proofs or page proofs, and without the comments of Professor Sara Monoson (Northwest- ern). Menn refers to Monoson’s comments in his final footnote, on the assumption that they would be in the same volume. The editors apologize to Professor Menn and especially to Professor Monoson for these failures. Corrections: p.2 n2, “Proclus In rem publicam v.1 p.8. Kroll, citing unnamed earlier writers …” should be “Proclus In rem publicam v.1 p.8 Kroll, citing unnamed earlier writers …” p.4 line 13, “καλῶς ἔξειν” should be “καλῶς ἔχειν” p.4 line 24, after “περὶ πολιτείας” delete the quotation mark. p.4 line 27, after “περὶ πολιτείας” delete the quotation mark. p.5 n4 next to last line, “Πολιτείαι” should be “Πολιτεῖαι” p.5 n5 line 4, “πολιτεῖα” should be “πολιτεία” p.6 n8 first line, “τὸ βίβλιον” should be “τὸ βιβλίον” p.7 line 1, “ἤ” should be “ἢ” p.7 n10 line 4, “Θεόδορος” should be “Θεόδωρος” p.14 n21 line 5, “περὶ τῆς ἐν ἀρχῆς καταστάσεως” should be “περὶ τῆς ἐν ἀρχῇ καταστάσεως” p.18 line 5, after “πρὸς τὰς πολιτείας” delete the quotation mark.
    [Show full text]
  • Ancient Economic Thought, Volume 1
    ANCIENT ECONOMIC THOUGHT This collection explores the interrelationship between economic practice and intellectual constructs in a number of ancient cultures. Each chapter presents a new, richer understanding of the preoccupation of the ancients with specific economic problems including distribution, civic pride, management and uncertainty and how they were trying to resolve them. The research is based around the different artifacts and texts of the ancient East Indian, Hebraic, Greek, Hellenistic, Roman and emerging European cultures which remain for our consideration today: religious works, instruction manuals, literary and historical writings, epigrapha and legal documents. In looking at such items it becomes clear what a different exercise it is to look forward, from the earliest texts and artifacts of any culture, to measure the achievements of thinking in the areas of economics, than it is to take the more frequent route and look backward, beginning with the modern conception of economic systems and theory creation. Presenting fascinating insights into the economic thinking of ancient cultures, this volume will enhance the reawakening of interest in ancient economic history and thought. It will be of great interest to scholars of economic thought and the history of ideas. B.B.Price is Professor of Ancient and Medieval History at York University, Toronto, and is currently doing research and teaching as visiting professor at Massachusetts Institute of Technology. ROUTLEDGE STUDIES IN THE HISTORY OF ECONOMICS 1 Economics as Literature
    [Show full text]
  • The Appeal to Easiness in Aristotle's Protrepticus
    THE APPEAL TO EASINESS IN ARISTOTLE’S PROTREPTICUS Matthew D. Walker [Uncorrected draft. To be published in Ancient Philosophy 39 (2019). Please cite only the final published version.] Aristotle’s Protrepticus sought to exhort its audience to engage in philosophy (filosofi&a), i.e., the “acquisition and use of wisdom” (kth~si&v te kai_ xrh~siv sofi&av: 6, 40.2-3/B53; cf. 6, 37.7-9/B8).1 The Protrepticus is now lost. But work by D.S. Hutchinson and Monte Ransome Johnson (2005) has confirmed earlier speculation – initiated by Ingram Bywater (1869) – that Iamblichus preserves large passages of the work in his own Protrepticus. Hutchinson and Johnson 2018 argue that significant portions of the Protrepticus also appear in Iamblichus’ De Communi Mathematica Scientia (DCMS), and that the Protrepticus was originally a dialogue. In passages preserved in Chapter 6 of Iamblichus’ Protrepticus (at 40.15-41.2/B55- 56), Aristotle offers three linked arguments for the claim that philosophy is easy. (I number the arguments in the translation that follows.) [1] For, with no pay coming from people to those who philosophize, on account of which [the latter] would have labored strenuously in this way, and with a great lead extended to the other arts, nevertheless their passing [the other arts] in exactness despite running a short time seems to me to be a sign of the easiness about philosophy. [2] And further, everybody’s feeling at home in it and wishing to occupy leisure with it, leaving aside all else, is no small sign that the close attention comes with pleasure; for no one is willing to labor for a long time.
    [Show full text]
  • Athenaion Politeia and Aristotle’S Political Theory
    4. The Athenaion Politeia and Aristotle’s Political Theory Lucio Bertelli DOI – http://dx.doi.org/10.7359/852-2018-bert ABSTRACT – This contribution addresses the issue of the mutual influence between the Athenaion Politeia and Aristotle’s political theory as developed in the Politics and elsewhere. It surveys previous approaches to this issue, analysing problems both with deterministic approaches and with those approaches that deny any influence of theory on the historical treatment of the Ath. Pol. It focuses in particular on the theory of the metabole and on the constitutional transitions in the Ath. Pol., and examines in detail the various metabolai of Athens vis-à-vis the treatment of Politics V and VI. It argues that the influence of Aristotle’s political theory in the Ath. Pol. is clear and detectable, but not deterministic. Theory is used as a key aid to understanding the logic of events. KEYWORDS – Aristotle’s political theory; Athens; metabole; stasis – Atene; metabole; sta­ sis; teoria politica di Aristotele. 1. SUMMARY OF THE IssUE The issue has been partially created by Aristotle himself when, in the sketchy outline of the Politics in EN X 9 (1181b 16-20), he announced: «First, then, if there is anything that has been correctly said by our pre- decessors on some part of the subject, let us try to go through it and then, on the basis of the collection of constitutions, try to get a theoretical grasp on what sorts of things preserve and destroy cities, what sorts of things preserve or destroy each sort of constitution, and what causes some cities to be well governed and others the opposite.
    [Show full text]
  • EXCAVATING the IMAGINATION: the ARABIC AFTERLIFE of ARISTOTLE's PHANTASIA by Jessica L. Radin a Thesis Submitted in Conformity
    EXCAVATING THE IMAGINATION: THE ARABIC AFTERLIFE OF ARISTOTLE’S PHANTASIA By Jessica L. Radin A thesis submitted in conformity with the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of the Study of Religion University of Toronto @Copyright by Jessica L. Radin 2018 EXCAVATING THE IMAGINATION: THE ARABIC AFTERLIFE OF ARISTOTLE’S PHANTASIA Jessica L. Radin Doctor of Philosophy Department for the Study of Religion University of Toronto 2018 ABSTRACT : This dissertation focuses on the afterlife of Aristotle’s work on the imagination, specifically in the work of al-Farabi, Ibn Rushd, and Maimonides. Drawing on previous scholarship that has investigated the philosophical and psychological role of the imagination in Aristotle, this dissertation considers the role that Aristotle’s Rhetoric had to play in later Arabic readings of Aristotle. This dissertation demonstrates that it wasthe rich life of Aristotle’s Rhetoric in the Arabic world that lead to a slow-burning association of imagination and politics. For al-Farabi, Ibn Rushd, and Maimonides, the imagination is the psychological feature of human beings that make us susceptible to persuasive speech. Since the images of imagination in human beings are restrained and directed by the rational faculty, they can also be directed, although not restrained, by the power of persuasive speech. The imagination allows human beings to imagine the world differently from the way it is, but at the same time it is not intrinsically capable of ascertaining which future or change is good. But human reason, with its deliberative powers, allows us to distinguish between persuasion based on emotional triggers and habitual desires and the truly remarkable innovations that can stem only from the partnership between imagination and reason.
    [Show full text]
  • Giorgio Agamben: Introductory Note on the Concept of Democracy
    Giorgio Agamben: Introductory Note on the Concept of Democracy From Theory & Event. Vol. 13, No. 1, 2010. Any discussion of the term “democracy” today is distorted by a preliminary ambiguity that condemns those who use it to misunderstanding. Of what do we speak when we speak about democracy? To what form of rationality does this term actually pertain? A slightly more attentive observation would show that those who discuss democracy today understand this term sometimes as a form of the body politic’s constitution, sometimes as a technique of government. The term thus refers both to the conceptuality of public law and to that of administrative practice: it designates power’s form of legitimation as well as the modalities of its exercise. Since it is obvious to everybody that, in contemporary political discourse, this term is more often related to a technique of government – which, as such, has nothing especially reassuring about it – one understands the malaise of those who continue to use it in the first sense in entirely good faith. That the interlacing of these two conceptualities – juridico- political on the one hand, economico-managerial on the other – has deep roots and is not easily disentangled will appear clearly in the following example. When we find the word politeia in the classics of Greek political thought (often within the context of a discussion about the different forms of politeia : monarchy, oligarchy, democracy, as well as their parekbaseis or deviations), we see the translators render this word sometimes as “constitution,”
    [Show full text]
  • In Search of Democracy 4.0
    Brook Manville and Josiah Ober here are plenty of indicators of doom: Donald Trump rid- ing roughshod over U.S. con- stitutional norms; the rise of high-handed strongmen across Europe supported by ethno-centric crowds; free press and free voting under attack by cyber ma- Tnipulation. Add mass migration threatening bor- ders and national identities; rising wealth in- equality; politics gridlocked by strife about rights, benefits, and duties, amidst growing re- sentment of “global elites” and new would-be cit- izens; and evolving confusion about the nature of the “common good” [1] –[5]. But others argue that democracy’s glass is still half-full. Global levels of freedom-embracing governance are at an all-time high [6], and look- ing back several decades, there’s been substan- tial (if uneven) spread of democracy to more parts of the world [7]. Yes, autocrats are rising here and there, but so are movements against In Search of Democracy 4.0 Is Democracy as We Know It Destined to Die? Digital Object Identifier 10.1109/MTS.2019.2894458 Date of publication: 6 March 2019 32 1932-4529/19©2019IEEE IEEE TECHNOLOGY AND SOCIETY MAGAZINE ∕ MARCH 2019 doomed but most versions of it today are indeed struggling to do what citizens expect it to do, and be what it is supposed to be. History suggests that, as an enduring human construct, democracy has a good chance of persisting, but not necessarily in its familiar guise: We will show that democ- racy cycled through several phases of evo- lutionary adaptation; it could be on the brink of another reinvention.
    [Show full text]
  • Rhetoric in European Culture and Beyond KAROLINUM Culture Andbeyond Ineuropean Rhetoric Jiří Kraus Jiří Chateau Park Inlysá Nad Labem, Nearprague
    Prof. PhDr. Jiří Kraus, DrSc. Rhetoric in European and World Culture traces the position of rhetoric in cultural Cover image: Allegory of Rhetoric. (1935) and educational systems from ancient times to the present. Here, Jiří Kraus examines František Václav Adámek ( 1713–1779), Professor Kraus lectures at the Faculty of Social Sciences, rhetoric’s decline in importance during a period of rationalism and enlightenment, from the Matthias Bernard Braun school. Charles University in Prague. Between 1963–2002 he worked presents the causes of negative connotations of rhetoric, and explains why rhetoric Rhetoric in European Chateau park in Lysá nad Labem, near Prague. in the Czech Language Institute of the Academy of Sciences, in the twentieth century regained its prestige. Kraus demonstrates that the reputation where he pursued mathematical linguistics prior to changing of rhetoric falls when it is reduced to a refined method for deceiving the public and his focus onto language culture and rhetoric. He is a member increases when it is seen as a scientific discipline throughout the humanities. In this Culture and Beyond of the editorial boards of prominent Czech linguistic journals sense, the author argues, rhetoric strives for universal recognition and the cultivation and of Charles University’s science council. After the cold of rhetorical expression, spoken and written, including not only its production but also war era, he became a member of the International Society for reception and interpretation. the History of Rhetoric, striking personal relations with leading Apart from classical and medieval rhetoric the book presents the condensed history world representatives in the field, particularly with Professor of rhetoric in France, Spain, Italy, Germany, England and Scotland as well as in the C.
    [Show full text]
  • THE KRATOS in DÊMOKRATIA* Daniela Cammack Yale University Paper Prepared for Presentation at the 2018 Meeting of the American
    THE KRATOS IN DÊMOKRATIA* Daniela Cammack Yale University Paper prepared for presentation at the 2018 meeting of the American Political Science Association, Boston MA Dêmokratia is at the same time one of the simplest words in the ancient Greek lexicon to translate and one of the most difficult to understand.1 It suggests ‘democracy’, but what did that imply two and a half thousand years ago? As is often observed, dêmos meant ‘people’, kratos ‘power’ or ‘rule’, leading to the conventional glosses ‘rule by the people’ or ‘people- power’.2 But these glosses raise further questions. ‘People’ defined how? ‘Ruling’ or ‘exercising power’ in what way? In previous work, I have tackled the first question, arguing— against the prevailing view that dêmos in this context denoted ‘people’ in the sense of the entire citizen body—that the dêmos in dêmokratia indicated, first and foremost, the common people formally constituted as a political body, that is to say, a popular assembly.3 Dêmokratia, on this interpretation, indicated rule by, or the power of, the assembly, in contradisinction from that of a council or single man. In this paper I turn to the second question. What did, and did not, kratos imply in the classical democratic context? I focus here on our most important source, the Aristotelian Athênaiôn Politeia or ‘Constitution of the Athenians’, rediscovered only in 1890 and whose full impact on the interpretation of Athenian democracy has arguably not yet been felt.4 Establishing the meaning of kratos requires distinguishing it from two proximate ‘power’ terms: archê, usually translated ‘rule’, ‘government’ or ‘empire’, and to kuros, ‘authority’ or ‘sovereignty’ (adjective kurios, ‘authoritative’ or ‘sovereign’), and one advantage of the Athênaiôn Politeia is that it contains these and cognate terms in abundance.
    [Show full text]
  • The Aristotelian Athenaion Politeia As 'Poor History'?
    Histos 13 (2019) 129–45 THE ARISTOTELIAN ATHENAION POLITEIA AS ‘POOR HISTORY’? HISTORIOGRAPHY, RHETORIC, AND THE CONTROVERSIES ABOUT SOLON IN THE FOURTH CENTURY* Abstract: This article examines the kind of historiographical thought that the Aristotelian Athenaion Politeia reveals in its use of sources, especially in chapters 2–17, which deal with Solon’s political activity. It confronts the scholarly view of the Athenaion Politeia as poor history and argues that its historical reasoning employs the same kind of rhetorical argumentation that would have been acceptable in the intellectual context of fourth-century Greek historiography. Keywords: ancient historiography, rhetoric, Solon, Aristotle, Athenian Constitution 1. Introduction he historical thought and methodology of the Aristotelian Athenaion Politeia have received some attention over the years in studies often T linked to the debate over its authorship.1 For those who ascribed the Ath. Pol. to Aristotle, his ideas about history as less philosophical and serious than poetry (Poetics 1451b),2 as well as presumed contradictions within the text or with other works,3 reaffirmed the absence in the work of historical accuracy and original research.4 Even when scholars thought otherwise and the value of Aristotle’s history was acknowledged, the Ath. Pol. was often dismissed as not being a proper historiographical work. I include here the explicit beliefs of * I am grateful to Francisco Marshall, Jose Carlos Baracat Junior, and Delfim Ferreira Leão for their help at different stages of this investigation, and to the institutions which supported it: CNPq (Conselho Nacional de Desenvolvimento Científico e Tecnológico), UFRGS (Universidade Federal do Rio Grande do Sul), and UFRB (Universidade Federal do Recôncavo da Bahia).
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle on Money and on Economy
    Review of Business and Economics Studies Volume 5, Number 3, 2017 Aristotle on Money and on Economy: First remarks1 Catherine BRÉGIANNI PhD on Modern History, Research Director Modern Greek History Research Centre, Hellenic Academy of Science [Academy of Athens] Associated Member (external), LaDéHis/CRH-EHESS [email protected] Abstract. This proposed paper (being a part of a work in progress on money and on monetary/ economic crises’ conceptualization) examines the institutional facet and the symbolic function of money as its diachronical qualities; this global perception of money and of monetary phenomena is integrated, thus, in the assumption that objective functions inheres in them, corresponding to respective historical conjuncture. The obvious outcome is that each historical period accentuates the different economic concepts—and their philosophical representation or their synthesis—according to the existing stage of the market’s evolution. In this methodological framework, in the first part will be examined the variable historical phases in the process of monetary integration, as far as the different characteristics of monetary globalization—in historical perspective—are specified. It is then useless to state that the “global” concept is referred not only to an interdisciplinary approach of money but equally to the diversified levels of globalization, the latest perceived as historical phases in market’s evolution. The past experience of monetary “integration” being briefly presented, in the second part of the article are depicted Aristotle’s notions on institutional characteristics and social/symbolic functions of money. Secondly, Plato’s Politeia offers to the research a systemic differentiation on parallel monetary units, i. e. the simultaneous function of local and global monetary systems.
    [Show full text]