Renaissance Aristotelianism and Meteorology

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Renaissance Aristotelianism and Meteorology Craig Martin. Renaissance Meteorology: Pomponazzi to Descartes. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 2011. 224 pp. $50.00, cloth, ISBN 978-1-4214-0187-4. Reviewed by Arianna Borrelli Published on H-PhysicalSciences (September, 2014) Commissioned by Marta Jordi Taltavull (Max Planck Institute for the History of Science) Renaissance meteorology is a highly complex reassessment of the role of Aristotelianism in the cultural constellation comprising a broad range of scientific revolution, Martin aims at demonstrat‐ interconnected practices of observation, descrip‐ ing how Aristotelian philosophy of the sixteenth tion, explanation, prediction, and interpretation and seventeenth centuries was not a rigid tradi‐ of phenomena of (mostly) meteorological, clima‐ tion whose demise opened up the feld for innova‐ tological, or geophysical nature. Because of the tive forms of natural philosophy associated with economic, social, and political relevance of weath‐ names like Galileo Galilei or René Descartes, but er and climate in the early modern period, the im‐ was rather a heterogeneous, lively constellation of portance of Renaissance meteorology for histori‐ evolving methods and ideas, which both Aris‐ cal research can hardly be overestimated. None‐ totelian and non-Aristotelian authors could ap‐ theless, as Craig Martin notes, this fascinating sub‐ propriate and transform in different directions. ject has hitherto received little attention and Mar‐ Using chosen meteorological writings as exam‐ tin's book makes a valuable contribution to flling ples, Martin argues that in the Renaissance no this gap. clear-cut line could be drawn between Aris‐ The volume focuses on one important aspect totelianism and the "new" natural philosophies, of the little-explored landscape: the way in which and that Aristotelian ideas and methods provided during the Renaissance notions and methods a creative, necessary contribution to the scientific from Aristotelian epistemology and Aristotelian revolution. At the same time, he also convincingly meteorological theory were adapted to meet the makes the case that the growing interest in ex‐ philosophical and cultural challenges posed by plaining meteorological phenomena was a power‐ the historical developments usually referred to as ful inspiration and motivation for reforming the "the scientific revolution." Following Charles Aristotelian tradition. Schmitt and other authors who have pleaded for a H-Net Reviews Working from different perspectives, the au‐ more general treatment of the basic features of thor on the one side explores similarities between Aristotelian natural philosophy. Aristotelian meteorological theories and those by As a study of how Renaissance Aristotelian‐ non-Aristotelian authors, such as Giovan Battista ism transformed and was transformed by new ap‐ Della Porta and Descartes; on the other side, he proaches to the explanation of meteorological shows how self-described Aristotelian authors phenomena, Martin's book deserves much praise. heavily reshaped Aristotle's theory of weather However, the book is not a comprehensive treat‐ and climate in a process of active and creative re‐ ment of Renaissance meteorology, and the fact ception of theoretical and empirical results origi‐ that its author chose to present it as such regret‐ nating in rival, upcoming directions of natural tably detracts from its value. The claim of ad‐ philosophy. Although the case studies discussed in dressing Renaissance meteorology in all its the volume concern meteorology, Martin's inter‐ breadth is made not only in the title but also est is primarily focused on epistemological issues, throughout the introduction, where Martin and the explanations given by the historical ac‐ presents Aristotelian treatises of meteorology and tors for certain phenomena are analyzed not so commentaries to Aristotle's meteorology as consti‐ much as part of theories of weather and climate, tuting the bulk of Renaissance meteorology. This but rather as examples of more general views on disputable statement allows him to justify the fact the foundations, origins, and limits of knowledge that his study mainly discusses Italian authors by about nature. A particularly significant example claiming that "Renaissance Aristotelianism often in this sense is the meteorological treatise by Nic‐ leads discussions to Italy" (p. 20). colò Cabeo, which, although presented as a modi‐ To rectify this misleading presentation of a lit‐ fication of Aristotelian meteorology, was actually tle-known subject, I feel compelled to mention a highly innovative construct embedding very dif‐ here those elements of the multiform landscape of ferent epistemological and natural philosophical Renaissance meteorology that Martin either fails views, and a construct that, as Martin aptly to discuss or dismisses in a few words. First and demonstrates, was conceived by Cabeo as offering foremost, history of science is today a history of a new epistemic template for the development of both theoretical and empirical practices, and so a new "Aristotelian" philosophy of nature. any discussion of Renaissance meteorology The book is organized around six case studies should necessarily include the rich tradition of reproducing and expanding Martin's previous systematic weather observation and recording by publications and forming the core of the six chap‐ authors of most different social and cultural ex‐ ters of the book, so that, while partly building tractions, as well as the various meteorological in‐ upon each other, the chapters can also be read in‐ struments developed from the early seventeenth dependently. However, the exposition is, on the century onward, which came to be embedded in whole, somehow nonsystematic. For example, the observational tradition. Martin mentions nei‐ most chapters start with detailed discussions of ther these issues nor the relevant research litera‐ Aristotle's views on specific subjects (the status of ture, such as, to name only the most basic refer‐ meteorological knowledge, fnal causes, the caus‐ ences, Gustav Hellmann's collection of sources on es of earthquakes, the origin of inner fre of the medieval and early modern weather observations earth. For a reader not familiar with the details of reprinted as part of his Neudrucke von Schriften Aristotelianism, it would probably have been bet‐ und Karten über Meteorologie und Erdmag‐ ter if these discussions had been grouped together netismus (1892-1904) or William Edgar Knowles into an introductory chapter and embedded in a Middleton's monographs on the early modern ori‐ 2 H-Net Reviews gins of meteorological instruments like the ther‐ did not view all knowledge about nature as a "sci‐ mometer and barometer (1964, 1966, 1969). Sec‐ entia" based on syllogism, but saw it also as a cor‐ ond, when discussing the theoretical practices pus based on probable arguments which could be linked to meteorology, Martin devotes much at‐ integrated by experience. Chapter 2 discusses the tention to detailing the multiform character of Re‐ issue of fnal causes in Renaissance Aristotelian‐ naissance Aristotelian epistemology and meteo‐ ism using as a case study debates on the possible rology, but makes little or no effort to expound the aims of meteorological phenomena, especially de‐ equally complex views of other traditions of structive ones, and on their eventual nature as philosophical and meteorological thought with signs of God's will. Martin here details how Italian which, as Martin himself correctly points out, Re‐ (Pomponazzi, Agostino Nifo) and German Luther‐ naissance Aristotelianism interacted. Two of these an (Melanchton and his circle) authors variously traditions played a particularly central role in Re‐ tried to ft notions of divine providence with natu‐ naissance meteorology: the frst one is the "chemi‐ ral causations and ethics. In this context, taking cal philosophy" (in the sense of Allen G. Debus), in into account how astrology provided many of whose context extremely influential meteorologi‐ these scholars with a template for conceiving nat‐ cal writings were composed outside of Italy by the ural order would have been a valuable addition German-Swiss Paracelsus, the Dutchman Cor‐ in reconstructing the cultural context of the dis‐ nelius Drebbel, and the Englishman Robert Fludd, cussions.[1] and to which also Della Porta's treatise may be The subject of the third chapter is of particu‐ counted. These texts have, for example, been dis‐ lar cultural historical interest: the political use of cussed by Gustav Hellmann in his Beiträge zur (actual or predicted) natural catastrophes, like Geschichte der Meteorologie (1914-22) and in vari‐ floods, storms, or earthquakes. Martin's case ous works by Debus. The second tradition is as‐ study concerns the earthquakes that hit the city of trology, whose role in Renaissance culture and Ferrara in the years 1570-74 and that Pope Pius V natural philosophy was central, especially as far claimed were sent as a punishment to the city's as weather forecasts were concerned, and which ruler Alfonso II d'Este for having granted resi‐ was a main component of the worldview of some dence to Jews against the pope's orders. To argue authors whom Martin discusses at length: Philipp against the pope and also to counter claims that Melanchton and his Wittenberg circle, Pietro the earthquake had been predicted by astrologers, Pomponazzi, and Della Porta. Although Martin in a number of scholars at the Ferrara court com‐ his introductory remarks acknowledges that the posed dialogues on
Recommended publications
  • Husserl's Phenomenological Reduction Revisited
    HUSSERL’S PHENOMENOLOGICAL REDUCTION REVISITED: AN ATTEMPT OF A RENEWED ACCOUNT SEBASTIAN L UFT This essay attempts a renewed, critical exposition of Husserl’s theory of the phenomenological reduction, incorporating manuscript material that has been published since the defining essays of the first generation of Husserl research. The discussion focuses on points that remain especially crucial, i. e. the concept of the natural attitude, the ways into the reduction, and the question of the “meaning of the reduction”. The reading attempted here leads to two, not necessarily related, focal points: a Cartesian and a Life-world tendency. In following these two paths, Husserl was consistent in pursuing two evident leads in his philosophical enterprise; however, he was at the same time unable to systematically unify these two strands. Thus, I am offering an interpretation which might be called a modified “departure from Cartesianism” reading that Landgrebe proposed in his famous essay from the nineteen-fifties (a reading that is still valid in many contemporary expositions of Husserl’s thought). This discussion should make apparent that Husserl’s theory of the phenome- nological reduction deserves a renewed look in light of material that has since appeared in the Husserliana and by incorporating the most important results of recent tendencies in Husserl research INTRODUCTION An author attempting an account of Husserl’s method of the phenomenological reduction finds himself in an ungratified position. This theme is one of the main topics in what is now more than sixty years of Husserl research 1. Furthermore, this theme has __________________________ 1. Whereas the first generation of Husserl research (E.
    [Show full text]
  • The Epistemic Value of 'Κατά Τόν Λόγον': Meteorology
    The epistemic value of ‘κατά τόν λόγον’: Meteorology 1.7 By Eleftheria Rotsia Dimou Submitted to Central European University Department of Philosophy In partial fulfillment of the requirements for the one year MA degree of Philosophy Supervisor: Associate Professor István Bodnár Budapest, Hungary 2018 CEU eTD Collection © Copyright by Eleftheria Rotsia Dimou, 2018 1 Τὸν μὲν οὖν Ἀναξαγόραν φασὶν ἀποκρίνασθαι πρός τινα διαποροῦντα τοιαῦτ ̓ ἄττα καὶ διερωτῶντα τίνος ἕνεκ ̓ ἄν τις ἕλοιτο γενέσθαι μᾶλλον ἢ μὴ γενέσθαι ‘τοῦ’ φάναι “θεωρῆσαι τὸν οὐρανὸν καὶ τὴν περὶ τὸν ὅλον κόσμον τάξιν”. (Aristotle, E.E Ι, 1216a12–14). CEU eTD Collection 2 Contents 1. Abstract ……………………………………………………….……4 2. Acknowledgments……………………………………..……………5 3. Introduction……………………………………………..…………..6 4. Part I: An Ontological Question…………………………...……….9 5. Part II: An Epistemological Question……………………………..14 6. Concluding Remarks…………………………………………..…..38 7. Bibliography………………………………………………………40 CEU eTD Collection 3 Abstract Ι will attempt to shed some light on the troubling matter of the obscure particulars ― treated by Aristotle in Meteorology ― (τῶν ἀφανῶν τῇ αἰσθήσει), that is, phenomena which are not apparent to the senses in their full extent (Meteorology 344a5). In the framework of the present paper, the aim is to highlight the use of κατά τόν λόγον which appears in the first lines of chapter I.7 of Aristotle’s Meteorology, by focusing on two philosophical questions: one ontological (what is the ontological status of obscure phenomena?) and one epistemological (can we come to the knowledge of such phenomena, and if so, in which way?). Aristotle proposes two answers to these questions in the text, respectively: The meteora (and therefore the comets discussed in chapter I.7 of Meteorology) are natural entities.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle's Poetics EPG Paathshala
    PAPER 10: MODULE 02: E-TEXT MHRD-UGC ePG Pathshala – English Principal Investigator & Affiliation: Prof. Tutun Mukherjee, University of Hyderabad Paper No & Title: Literary Criticism and Theory (Paper 10) Paper Coordinator & Affiliation: Dr. Anita Bhela, Delhi College of Arts and Commerce, University of Delhi Module Number & Title Aristotle’s Poetic Concept: An Analysis of Poetry (02) Content Writer's Name & Affiliation: Dr. Omana Antony, K. R. Mangalam University Name & Affiliation of Content Reviewer: Dr. Smita Banerjee, Associate Professor, University of Delhi Name & Affiliation of Content Editor: Dr. Anita Bhela, Delhi College of Arts and Commerce, University of Delhi “Knowing yourself is the beginning of all wisdom.” NAME: Aristotle OCCUPATION: philosopher BIRTH DATE: c. 384 BCE DEATH DATE: c. 322 BCE EDUCATION: Plato's Academy, Lyceum PLACE OF BIRTH: Stagira, Chalcidice, Greece PLACE OF DEATH: Chalcis, Euboea, Greece A Glimpse to Aristotle’s Life Aristotle ( the name means ‘ the best purpose’) was a philosopher and polymath from Greece. His father Nicomachus was the personal physician to King Amyntas of Macedon. Aristotle moved to Plato’s Academy while he was 18. Aristotle’s teacher was Plato, and Aristotle was the teacher of Alexander the Great. Aristotle married Pythias and she bore him a daughter, whom they also named Pythias. Aristotle was invited by Philip II of Macedon to become the tutor to his son Alexander in 343 BC.Aristotle was appointed as the head of the royal academy of Macedon. By 335 BC, Artistotle had returned to Athens, establishing his own school there known as the Lyceum. Aristotle conducted courses at the school for the next twelve years.
    [Show full text]
  • Space Science and Meteorology Spectrum Allocations in the UK
    Introduction ‘Space science’ is an umbrella term that covers both Earth observation and space related scientific research. Earth observation (EO) satellites observe the earth and its atmosphere, using visible light or radio spectrum from a unique vantage point. The information it provides is used for a wide range of purposes including weather forecasting, environmental monitoring, climate change research as well as a number of commercial activities. Radio astronomy and space research contribute to our knowledge of space and the evolution of the universe. The following services fall under this category: • Earth Exploration Satellite Service (EESS) Space Research Service (SRS) Space Operation Service (SOS) Radio Astronomy Service (RAS) Meteorological Satellite Service (MetSat) Meteorological Aids Service (Met-Aids) Radiolocation Service Note: this only for wind profiler and weather radars) Standard Time and Frequency signals) These services can be split in two broad categories: passive services (RAS, EESS and Space Research Service), that measure naturally- occurring radiation often at very low power levels. This information provides useful data to help further understand the Earth and universe. The frequency bands are often determined by the specific physical properties being investigated (e.g. molecular resonance). active services that make use of a variety of technologies (e.g. radiodetermination) to carryout measurements, observations or transfer the collected data. These active applications are relatively less sensitive to interference compared to passive sensors. Given the low levels of radiation being monitored these services often use very sensitive receivers. In most cases the equipment is not able to discriminate between these natural radiations and man-made radiations. For this reason, a number of bands have been harmonised across the world for the use by passive services only.
    [Show full text]
  • Perlow Lyric Ignorance
    LYRIC IGNORANCE: TECHNOLOGIES OF AMERICAN POETRY A Dissertation Presented to the Faculty of the Graduate School of Cornell University in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy by Seth Michael Perlow January 2013 © 2013 Seth Michael Perlow LYRIC IGNORANCE: TECHNOLOGIES OF AMERICAN POETRY Seth Michael Perlow, Ph.D. Cornell University 2013 This study argues that the rhetoric of ignorance has helped to define the lyric genre in US poetry and its criticism. It examines how differentiations between poetic thought and knowledge have informed recent responses to Emily Dickinson, Gertrude Stein, and Frank O’Hara—altering both their reputations as lyric poets and the material histories of their texts. Whereas new media scholars often link technology with rationality and information, “Lyric Ignorance” challenges critiques of the lyric by showing how textual equipment enables lyrical claims against knowledge. It thereby explores how the language of ignorance has informed the social and historical values of US lyric poetry in the postwar and contemporary periods. BIOGRAPHICAL SKETCH Seth Michael Perlow was raised in Atlanta, GA and attended college at Brown University, where he concentrated in Comparative Literature, earning an AB (2005) with Highest Honors and departmental honors. His undergraduate thesis, a translation of work by the Argentine poet Karina Macció, won the Rosalie Colie Prize in Comparative Literature. He then enrolled in the Master of Arts Program in the Humanities a the University of Chicago, earning an MA in Humanities (2006). A revision of his master’s thesis on Wallace Stevens’ early poetry, “The Other Harmonium: Toward a Minor Stevens,” appeared in The Wallace Stevens Journal 33.2 (Fall 2009).
    [Show full text]
  • Intro to Meteorology & Astronomy (Teacher Guide)
    Includes Student Includes: Answer Keys TEACHER GUIDE Worksheets Weekly Lesson Schedule Worksheets 7th –8th Grade Science Quizzes & Tests Intro to Meteorology & Astronomy First printing: April 2016 Copyright © 2016 by Master Books®. All rights reserved. No part of this book may be used or reproduced in any manner whatsoever without written permission of the publisher, except in the case of brief quotations in articles and reviews. For information write: Master Books®, P.O. Box 726, Green Forest, AR 72638 Master Books® is a division of the New Leaf Publishing Group, Inc. ISBN: 978-0-89051-964-6 Unless otherwise noted, Scripture quotations are from the New King James Version of the Bible. Printed in the United States of America Please visit our website for other great titles: www.masterbooks.com For information regarding author interviews, please contact the publicity department at (870) 438-5288 Permission is granted for copies of reproducible pages from this text to be made for use within your own homeschooling family activities or for small classrooms of ten or fewer students. Material may not be posted online, Faith Grower distributed digitally, or made available as a download. Permission for any other use of the material must be requested prior to use by email to the publisher at [email protected]. Table of Contents Using this Teacher Guide .......................................................................................................................... 4 Course Description ..................................................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • PHIL 210: Seminar on Greek Philosophy Aristotle’S Philosophy of Science
    PHIL 210: Seminar on Greek Philosophy Aristotle’s Philosophy of Science UC, San Diego Fall 2012 W 3-5:50 Professor Monte Johnson [email protected] HSS 7058 (by appointment) Seminar Description: This seminar is designed to help graduate students learn how to conduct research into Aristotle. We will aim to review Aristotle's logic and scientific method, exercise the ability to read and criticize diverse parts of his corpus, and develop other research interests by relating them to his thought. The Professor will offer an overview of Aristotle’s life and works (including both the Aristotle Corpus and lost works), and his scientific method, as developed in the Organon, especially the Posterior Analytics, and in scientific practice, in works such as On the Heavens, On the Soul, On the Parts of Animals, Mechanical Problems, Metaphysics, Ethics, Politics, Rhetorics, and Poetics. The rest of the participants will choose a specific subject that relates to their research interests (on any topic, including ethical and political subjects), and select (in consultation with the Professor) about 20-25 pages in English translation on the subject to be read and discussed by the seminar (along with recommended secondary sources). After the third meeting, each meeting will consist of two parts. In the first part, we will have a roundtable discussion of the progress of each seminarian’s research, followed by general comments by the Professor on the status of contemporary research in the specific subject area. In the second part, the Seminarian will lead the seminar through a philosophical discussion of her subject area on the basis of her selected readings and handouts.
    [Show full text]
  • Johann Lambert's Scientific Tool Kit
    Johann Lambert’s Scientific Tool Kit. Maarten Bullynck To cite this version: Maarten Bullynck. Johann Lambert’s Scientific Tool Kit.: Exemplified by the Measurement of Humidity. Science in Context, Cambridge University Press (CUP), 2010, 23 (1), pp.65-89. 10.1017/S026988970999024X. halshs-00663305 HAL Id: halshs-00663305 https://halshs.archives-ouvertes.fr/halshs-00663305 Submitted on 26 Jan 2012 HAL is a multi-disciplinary open access L’archive ouverte pluridisciplinaire HAL, est archive for the deposit and dissemination of sci- destinée au dépôt et à la diffusion de documents entific research documents, whether they are pub- scientifiques de niveau recherche, publiés ou non, lished or not. The documents may come from émanant des établissements d’enseignement et de teaching and research institutions in France or recherche français ou étrangers, des laboratoires abroad, or from public or private research centers. publics ou privés. Maarten Bullynck Université Paris 8 Vincennes à St.-Denis Département d'Histoire / Mathématiques & Histoire des Sciences 2 rue de la Liberté, 93526 Saint-Denis Adress: Krijgslaan 57, 9000 Gent, Belgium Email: [email protected] Telephone: 0032-484 634495 Title of the paper: J.H. Lambert’s Scientific Tool Kit. (Exemplified by Lambert’s Measurement of Humidity, 1769–1772) Abstract: J.H. Lambert (1728-1777) developed a very detailed theory of science and experiment. Using Lambert's hygrometric studies, this article provides an introduction into Lambert's theory and its practice. Of special interest in Lambert's theory are a well-founded theory on the emergence and definition of concepts and his neat neat eye for heuristics that should ultimately lead up to a mathematization of physical phenomena.
    [Show full text]
  • Craig Martin CAUSATION in DESCARTES' LES MÉTÉORES
    Craig Martin CAUSATION IN DESCARTES’ LES MÉTÉORES AND LATE RENAISSANCE ARISTOTELIAN METEOROLOGY INTRODUCTION Over seventy years ago, Étienne Gilson showed the parallels between Descartes’ Les météores and the Coimbrans’ textbook that was based on Aristotle’s Meteorology. The topics treated in Descartes’ work follow those found in the frequently-taught Jesuit textbook. They both discussed the formation of clouds, rain, rainbows and other lights in the sky, minerals and salts, and the cause of winds and earthquakes.1 The similarities do not end at the structure and topics treated that Gilson pointed out but extend to large portions of the treatises’ content. To be sure, differences appear, but many Aristotelian meteorological concepts are found throughout Descartes’ treatise without being changed at all or only in a minor way. Descartes’ Les météores was neither revolutionary, nor was it intended to be revolutionary. Les météores was first published in 1637 together with the Discours de la méthode, La géométrie, and La dioptrique. Some recent studies on Descartes’ physics and the Les météores have emphasized the eighth discourse where Descartes explained the rainbow through a geometrical analysis of refraction.2 This emphasis has given the appearance that his study on meteorology was part of Descartes’ larger goal of applying mathematics to natural philosophy as he did in the accompanying La dioptrique. Other studies, however, have emphasized the physical aspects of his account on the rainbow and how the deductive method Descartes used
    [Show full text]
  • Husserl's Theory of the Phenomenological Reduction
    Marquette University e-Publications@Marquette Philosophy Faculty Research and Publications Philosophy, Department of 1-1-2004 Husserl’s Theory of the Phenomenological Reduction: Between Life-World and Cartesianism Sebastian Luft Marquette University, [email protected] Accepted version. Research in Phenomenology, Vol. 34, No. 1 (2004): 198-234. DOI. © 2004 Brill Academic Publishers. Used with permission. Husserl’s Theory of the Phenomenological Reduction: Between Life- World and Cartesianism Author : Sebastian Luft Abstract : This essay attempts a renewed, critical exposition of Husserl’s theory of the phenomenological reduction, incorporating manuscript material that has been published since the defining essays of the first generation of Husserl research. The discussion focuses on points that remain especially crucial, i.e., the concept of the natural attitude, the ways into the reduction (and their systematics), and finally the question of the “meaning of the reduction.” Indeed, in the reading attempted here, this final question leads to two, not necessarily related, focal points: a Cartesian and a Life-world tendency. It is my claim that in following these two paths, Husserl was consistent in pursuing two evident leads in his philosophical enterprise; however, he was at the same time unable to systematically unify these two strands. Thus, I am offering an interpretation which might be called a modified “departure from Cartesianism” reading that Landgrebe proposed in his famous essay from the 1950s, in which he was clearly influenced by Heidegger (a reading that is still valid in many contemporary expositions of Husserl’s thought). This discussion should make apparent that Husserl’s theory of the phenomenological reduction deserves a renewed look both in light of material that has since appeared in the Husserliana and in light of a new incorporation of the most important results of recent tendencies in Husserl research.
    [Show full text]
  • The Ends of Weather: Teleology in Renaissance Meteorology
    The Ends of Weather: Teleology in Renaissance Meteorology CRAIG MArtIN* 1 . the divide between the prominence of final causes inA ristotelian natural phi- losophy and the rejection or severe limitation of final causation as an acceptable explanation of the natural world by figures such as Bacon, Descartes, and Spinoza during the seventeenth century has been considered a distinguishing mark between pre-modern and modern science.1 Admittedly, proponents of the mechanical and corpuscular philosophies of the seventeenth century were not necessarily stark opponents of teleology. Pierre Gassendi and Robert Boyle endorsed teleology, Leibniz embraced entelechies, and they creep into Descartes’s natural philoso- phy, despite his adamant attempts to eliminate them.2 Nonetheless, critiques of ends in natural philosophy resonated throughout seventeenth-century natural philosophy and beyond. Enlightenment figures such as Jean le Rond D’Alembert ridiculed the use of teleology to explain the natural world.3 Dennis Des Chene, 1F. Bacon, De augmentis scientiis, in Works, ed. J. Spedding, R. L. Ellis, and D. D. Heath (London: Longman, 1857), 1:571; R. Descartes, Principia philosophiae I.28, in Œuvres, ed. C. Adam and P. Tan- nery (Paris: J. Vrin, 1986), 8-1:15; B. Spinoza, Appendix to Ethics I, in The Collected Works of Spinoza, trans. and ed. E. Curley (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1985), 439. For the importance of the rejection of final causes in the historiography of the Scientific Revolution, see Alexandre Koyré, Newtonian Studies (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1965), 7–8; Steven Shapin, The Scientific Revolution (Chicago: Chicago University Press, 1996), 28–30. For an overview of the Scientific Revo- lution and scholastic views of teleology see Monte Ransome Johnson, Aristotle on Teleology (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005), 23–30.
    [Show full text]
  • Early Modern Clouds and the Poetics of Meteorology: an Introduction
    Romance Quarterly ISSN: (Print) (Online) Journal homepage: https://www.tandfonline.com/loi/vroq20 Early modern clouds and the poetics of meteorology: An Introduction Jeffrey N. Peters & Katharina N. Piechocki To cite this article: Jeffrey N. Peters & Katharina N. Piechocki (2021): Early modern clouds and the poetics of meteorology: An Introduction, Romance Quarterly, DOI: 10.1080/08831157.2021.1900690 To link to this article: https://doi.org/10.1080/08831157.2021.1900690 Published online: 08 Apr 2021. Submit your article to this journal View related articles View Crossmark data Full Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at https://www.tandfonline.com/action/journalInformation?journalCode=vroq20 ROMANCE QUARTERLY https://doi.org/10.1080/08831157.2021.1900690 Early modern clouds and the poetics of meteorology: An Introduction Jeffrey N. Petersa and Katharina N. Piechockib aFrench and Francophone Studies, Department of Modern and Classical Languages, Literatures, and Cultures, University of Kentucky, Lexington, Kentucky, USA; bDepartment of Comparative Literature, Harvard University, Cambridge, Massachusetts, USA ABSTRACT KEYWORDS Since antiquity, philosophers and poets have understood clouds to be Clouds; poetics; cosmology; principles of generation and procreation. They can turn, Aristophanes tells gender; mediation us, “into anything they want.” They are bound up with the act of beget- ting and giving birth, of bringing into being the new – hollow vessels, as Seneca would later put it, with solid walls. And yet the creative force of clouds is a strange, even counterintuitive, one: what they generate and bring forth is often evanescent, incorporeal, and unsubstantial. In this essay, we explore a poetics of clouds as a site of tension between the empty and the procreative, the material and the immaterial, the percep- tible and the imperceptible.
    [Show full text]