SCEPTICISM and DEPRAVITY By

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

SCEPTICISM and DEPRAVITY By THE WAGES OF THEISM: SCEPTICISM AND DEPRAVITY by Matthew Morgan Harrop Thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Degree of Bachelor of Arts with Honours in Philosophy Acadia University April, 2010 © Copyright by Matthew Morgan Harrop, 2010 This thesis by Matthew Morgan Harrop is accepted in its present form by the Department of Philosophy as satisfying the thesis requirements for the degree of Bachelor of Arts with Honours Approved by the Thesis Supervisor __________________________ ___________________ Dr. Stephen Maitzen Date Approved by the Head of the Department __________________________ ___________________ Dr. Paul Abela Date Approved by the Honours Committee __________________________ ___________________ Dr. Matthew Durant Date ii I, Matthew Morgan Harrop, grant permission to the University Librarian at Acadia University to reproduce, loan or distribute copies of my thesis in microform, paper or electronic formats on a non-profit basis. I however, retain the copyright in my thesis. ___________________________________ Signature of Author ___________________________________ Date iii Acknowledgements My supervisor, Dr. Stephen Maitzen, has been a tremendous help throughout the entire thesis writing process. He has improved my work by asking me stimulating questions, providing me with helpful information, and giving me immensely valuable suggestions. He stuck with me the whole time, pushing me whenever I needed motivation and giving me a break whenever I needed time. But Dr. Maitzen has been so much more than a dedicated supervisor, academic advisor, and professor. He has been my friend and mentor since my first week on campus. I am truly grateful for the fact that he has helped me improve not only my thesis, but also my intellect and character. During the latter stages of the writing process, Dr. Ian Wilks has been invaluable. His insightful comments and extremely close proofreading have been greatly beneficial— they‘ve helped me to improve the clarity of my arguments and eliminate many unsightly typographical errors. I couldn‘t have asked for a more astute and careful second reader. In general, the quality of my thesis was dramatically improved by the influence that all of the wonderful philosophy professors at Acadia University have had on my academic career. Dr. Paul Abela, Dr. Marc Ramsay, and Dr. Anna Wilks—and, of course, Dr. Ian Wilks and Dr. Stephen Maitzen—have pushed me to strive ever-harder to reach goals that didn‘t exist for me before I arrived in Wolfville. Their knowledge, personalities, and passion for teaching provided the impetus for many of the ideas that I‘ve tried to synthesize in my thesis. Additionally, their commitment to living the examined life has regularly provided me with inspiration. Finally, I would like to thank my parents for their ever-present support and love. They have given me everything I have ever truly needed. iv Contents Acknowledgements iv Abstract vi Introduction 1 Chapter One: Heaven, Killing, and Troubles for Ordinary Morality 7 I. Introduction 7 II. Killing According to Ordinary Morality 8 III. Accounts of the Wrongness of Killing 12 IV. Objections and Replies 19 V. Conclusion 27 Chapter Two: From Theism to Psychological Egoism and the Impossibility of Altruism 29 I. Introduction 29 II. Psychological Egoism 30 III. Constraints on Psychological Egoism 31 IV. Eschatological Moral Compensation‘s Implications for Theism 32 V. Heaven and Infinity 37 VI. Conclusion 40 Chapter Three: Theism, Libertarianism, and Another Conflict with Ordinary Morality 42 I. Introduction 42 II. Theism and Free Will 43 III. Theism and Soft Determinism 44 IV. Theism and Libertarianism 48 V. Divine Timelessness: A Possible Solution 50 VI. Another Conflict between Theism and Ordinary Morality 54 VII. Conclusion 56 Chapter Four: From Contextualism and Theism to Scepticism 57 I. Introduction 57 II. The Sceptical Possibility of a Deceptive God 58 III. Divine Deception and Epistemic Contexts 63 IV. Non-Theists‘ Immunity to this Sceptical Threat 65 V. Avoiding Semantic Descent 67 VI. Conclusion 68 Conclusion 70 Bibliography 75 v Abstract Historically, philosophers and theologians have argued for what remains a popular position—the view that atheism threatens morality and even knowledge. Contrary to historical custom and popular sentiment, I argue that morality and knowledge are actually threatened by theism. Throughout my thesis, I use ―theism‖ to refer to the proposition that an omnipotent, omniscient, and omnibenevolent God exists. Theists believe in the existence of God, while also commonly believing in the existence of heaven and the notion that we will ultimately be rewarded or punished depending on how laudable or blameworthy our earthly deeds are. I arrive at my conclusion—that theism threatens morality and knowledge—via four distinct, but related, arguments. My first argument attempts to show that theism‘s explanation of the wrongness of killing heaven- bound victims clashes with our ordinary moral intuitions. My second argument tries to force theists to admit that their beliefs imply either the impossibility of altruism and laudable self-sacrifice or the dissolution of our ordinary conception of morality. My third argument is based on the premise that theism implies the existence of libertarian free will. It concludes that theism once again comes into conflict with our ordinary moral practice and commitments. My fourth argument moves from morality to epistemology by arguing that, given the popular theory of epistemic contextualism, theists cannot accurately claim knowledge of the external-world for themselves or others. By combining these four arguments, I hope to repel both historical and popular criticism of atheists by showing that theists, not atheists, ought to bear the burden of explaining unacceptable moral and epistemological consequences. vi Introduction For thousands of years—from the birth of Judaism to the present day—classical monotheism has offered itself as a foundation for many valuable aspects of the human condition, including morality and knowledge. Presently and historically, theists popularly, and sometimes philosophically, invoke God as the only possible foundation for objective morality.1 Additionally, some of the giants of Enlightenment philosophy argue that acknowledging God‘s existence is necessary in order to avoid universal scepticism. I intend to dispute both of these positions. In contrast to these popular and philosophical views, I‘ll argue that monotheism (or, as I prefer, just ―theism‖) is, in fact, the enemy of morality and knowledge because of its implications for our moral commitments and practice and because it flirts dangerously with scepticism. As such, my project concludes that the ―wages of theism‖ (with apologies to St. Paul) are depravity and scepticism.2 Atheists, people who disbelieve in classical monotheism‘s God, face frequent attacks on their character from theists.3 In contemporary times, atheists are frequently viewed suspiciously due to the popular assumption among theists that atheism implies moral nihilism. In fact, atheists are the most distrusted minority group in the United States of America, according to survey results published in the American Sociological Review. When asked to explain this distrust, most respondents opined that only believers 1 By ―objective morality,‖ I‘m referring to moral standards that hold regardless of anyone‘s say-so. 2 Compare Romans 6:23a (KJV): ―For the wages of sin is death...‖. 3 It should be noted that, given my definition of ―theism‖—i.e., as classical monotheism—polytheists, animists, and others who hold similar beliefs are, strictly speaking, atheists (or at least non-theists): they deny the existence of monotheism‘s perfect God. 1 in God are morally trustworthy, implying that atheism is anathema to morality.4 Other, more philosophically sophisticated theists also accuse atheism of being unable to support objective morality. They target atheism by arguing that, while evolution can explain our actions, it cannot conclusively demonstrate that our actions are objectively moral or immoral. One of these sophisticated theists, William Lane Craig, concludes that if there is no God, then any basis for regarding the herd morality evolved by Homo sapiens as objectively true seems to have been removed. Some action— say, rape—may not be biologically or socially advantageous and so in the course of human evolution has become taboo; but on the atheistic view there‘s nothing really wrong about raping someone.5 In expressing his view, Craig affirms the popularly held belief that atheism is unable to underwrite the existence of objective morality, despite the fact that evolution and other naturalistic worldviews are able to explain our tendency to believe in objective morality. Indeed, the sentiment that theism is necessary to uphold objective morality, which remains strong today, has been expressed throughout the centuries. John Locke, one of the previously mentioned giants of the Enlightenment, professes: 4 Penny Edgell, Joseph Gerteis, and Douglas Hartmann. ―Atheists as ‗Other‘: Moral Boundaries and Cultural Membership in American Society,‖ American Sociological Review 71 (2006): 212. 5 William Lane Craig, ―The Kurtz/Craig Debate: Is Goodness without God Good Enough?,‖ in Is Goodness without God Good Enough?: A Debate on Faith, Secularism, and Ethics, edited by Robert K. Garcia and Nathan L. King (Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield Publishers, Inc., 2009), 32. 2 [T]hose are not at all to be tolerated
Recommended publications
  • Defending Options Author(S): Shelly Kagan Source: Ethics, Vol. 104, No. 2 (Jan., 1994), Pp
    Defending Options Author(s): Shelly Kagan Source: Ethics, Vol. 104, No. 2 (Jan., 1994), pp. 333-351 Published by: The University of Chicago Press Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2381581 Accessed: 13-08-2014 16:42 UTC Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. The University of Chicago Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Ethics. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded from 130.132.173.11 on Wed, 13 Aug 2014 16:42:57 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions Defending Options ShellyKagan Suppose some act would best promote the overall good, objectively speaking. Are we morallyrequired to do it? Not necessarily,says ordi- nary,commonsense morality: after all, the act in question mightviolate someone's rightsor run afoul of some otheragent-centered constraint. Well, then, are we at least morallyrequired to performthe act with the best resultsof those acts that are not otherwiseforbidden? Here, too, ordinarymorality says no: thereis no such general moral require- ment to promote the good (not even within the confines of moral constraints).Rather, ordinary morality claims that in a certainbroad, but not unlimited,range of cases, agents have moraloptions: although they are morallypermitted to performthe act with the best conse- quences overall,they are not morallyrequired to do so; on the contrary, they are also morallypermitted to performinstead acts that are less than optimal, such as pursuing theirown interests.
    [Show full text]
  • 2014-PDF-Of-Philosophy-News
    UNIVERSITY OF TORONTO DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSO PHY FALL 2014 IAN HACKI NG WSEI E NPAGS E 3BALZAN PRIZ E! PRACT ICAL ETH ICS – SHEL LY KAG AN ON SPECIESISM By Ellen Roseman Shelly Kagan, the Clark Professor of Philosophy at Yale University, drew a capacity crowd to the Roseman Lecture in Practical Ethics last fall. He is an engaging, funny and whip- smart speaker. And he chose an intriguing topic, one that is not usually explored in mainstream philosophy courses. The title: What’s wrong with speciesism? In a bestselling 1975 book, Animal Liberation , Australian philosopher Peter Singer claimed that most of us Shelly Kagan with Ellen Roseman are “speciesists” in our attitude toward, and treatment of, animals. Singer, now a bioethics professor than persuasive. “People have rights. Animals don’t,” he tells Speciesism is supposed to be a kind at Princeton University, created me after the lecture. “There’s a of morally unjustified prejudice, akin a splash when he called for an huge crowd of people working to racism or sexism, Kagan said in animal rights movement. Kagan on this issue. I thought a lot of his notes for the lecture. “Although read the book while in graduate the arguments were weak.” I found that charge compelling for school. He became a vegetarian. years, I now find that I have my But in a second reading of the Kagan thinks the crucial concept doubts,” he explained. “It now seems book in 2011, while preparing is to define the meaning of a to me that most people are not actu - to give an animal ethics seminar “person.” Going back to British ally speciesists at all, but something to Yale students, Kagan found philosopher John Locke’s work rather different.” some of Singer’s arguments less ...continued on Page 2 We wish to thank the generous donors to the Department of Philosophy, without whom Philosophy News would not be possible.
    [Show full text]
  • Metaethics and the Autonomy of Morality
    Philosophers’ volume8,no.6 july2008 Imprint 1. Introduction SincethepublicationofG.E.Moore’sPrincipia Ethicaithasbecome commonplace for philosophers to distinguish between questions in metaethics and those in normative ethics.1 A sympathetic character- Metaethics izationofthecenturyofself-consciouslymetaethicalresearchthatfol- lowedwouldemphasizetheextraordinarydevelopmentbothinour understandingofthecentralmetaethicalproblemsandinthesophis- ticationofthetheorieselaboratedtomeetthem.However,someare & notsosympathetic.Inthispaper,Iexamineonesourceofdistrustin metaethicalresearch:itsapparenttensionwiththenotionthatmoral- ityisautonomous. Tobegin,IbrieflysketchhowIamthinkingofmetaethics,ofthe the Autonomy of autonomyofmorality,andofthetensionthatcanappeartoexistbe- tweenthem.Onetraditionalconceptionofmetaethicstakesittocon- cern only the analysis of moral language.2 However, contemporary philosophers typically use the term more expansively.3 Here, I use Morality the term to pick out elements common to these contemporary dis- cussions.Thiscommoncoreencompassesmoralontologyandmoral psychologyaswellasmoralsemantics.Bycontrast,normativeethics (sometimesalsocalled‘substantiveethics’)concernsthestructureand contentofthecorrectmoralevaluationofagents,statesofaffairs,and actions.Normativeethicaltheoriestypicallyofferaccountsofmoral valueandmoralreasons,ofvirtuouscharactertraits,ofrightness,and Tristram McPherson oftherelationshipsbetweenthese. 1. The word ‘metaethics’ came into regular philosophical usage much later. University of Minnesota Duluth
    [Show full text]
  • Ethics and the Future -- Assigned Readings
    Ethics and the Future -- Assigned Readings Note: This is a list of the readings that I assigned (or recommended) to the students (a mix of undergraduates and graduate students) for my seminar, “Ethics and the Future,” taught at Yale in Spring 2021. As the reading list was prepared only for the students in the course, I’m afraid I didn’t include links for any papers that I was including in the course pack, though I believe all of these readings can be easily found online, with the exception, of course, of Ord’s The Precipice, and Parfit’s Reasons and Persons. I am making the reading list publicly available at the request of Pablo Stafforini. In choosing suitable readings I was aided tremendously by the list of readings selected by William MacAskill and Christian Tarsney for their own seminar taught at Oxford in 2019, and especially by the potential syllabus that Joshua Monrad wrote up for my benefit. (Since it was Joshua who rightly insisted to me that this would make an interesting and important topic for a seminar, I am doubly in his debt.) The readings are organized by topic. We spent a week on each. --Shelly Kagan Background on Existential Risks: 1. Toby Ord, The Precipice, Chapters 3-6 and Appendices C and D (about 124 pages) The Basic Case for Longtermism: 1. Perhaps start with this very brief overview: Todd, “Future Generations and Their Moral Significance” (about 7 pages), which can be found online at: https://80000hours.org/articles/future-generations/ 2. Then look at the somewhat longer (but still breezy) exposition in Ord, The Precipice, Intro and Chapters 1-2, and Appendix E (65 pgs.) 3.
    [Show full text]
  • Hedonism (For International Encyclopedia of Ethics)
    Hedonism Word Count: 4,488 Hedonism is among the oldest, simplest, and most widely discussed theories of value – theories that tell us what makes the world better or what makes a person’s life go better. Hedonism, in a word, is the view that “pleasure is the good.” In its most comprehensive form, hedonism about value holds that the only thing that ultimately ever makes the world, or a life, better is its containing more pleasure or less pain. The term ‘hedonism’ is also sometimes used to refer to doctrines about other topics. ‘Universal hedonism’ sometimes stands for the view that we ought to bring the greatest balance of pleasure over pain into the world that we can (see UTILITARIANISM), and ‘psychological hedonism’ the view that all human behavior is motivated ultimately by desires to obtain pleasure or avoid pain. Our topic here is hedonism about value. 1. What is hedonism about value? a. What is hedonism a theory of? An important distinction among kinds of value is the distinction between something’s being good for some person (or other subject), and something’s simply being a good thing (see GOOD AND GOOD FOR). The former kind of value – called ‘welfare’ or ‘well-being’ – makes our lives better, or makes things go better for us (see WELL-BEING), while the latter kind of value makes the world better. Typically, whenever a person receives some benefit, or has his life made better, this also makes the world better. But it is at least conceivable that the two come apart, as when an undeserving person receives some benefit, making things go better for him 1 without perhaps making the world better.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy 1 Philosophy
    Philosophy 1 Philosophy Connecticut Hall, 203.432.1665 http://philosophy.yale.edu M.A., M.Phil., Ph.D. Acting Chair Kenneth Winkler Director of Graduate Studies Stephen Darwall ([email protected]) Professors David Charles, Stephen Darwall, Michael Della Rocca, Keith DeRose, Paul Franks, Tamar Gendler, John Hare, Verity Harte, Brad Inwood, Shelly Kagan, Joshua Knobe, Laurie Paul, Thomas Pogge, Scott Shapiro, Sun-Joo Shin, Steven Smith, Jason Stanley, Zoltán Szabó, Kenneth Winkler, Gideon Yaffe Associate Professors Daniel Greco, John Pittard Assistant Professors Robin Dembroff, Manon Garcia Fields of Study The department offers a wide range of courses in various traditions of philosophy, with strengths and a well-established reputation in the history of philosophy, ethics, philosophy of law, epistemology, philosophy of language, and philosophy of religion as well as other central topics. Special Requirements for the Ph.D. Degree 1. In the first two years all students must complete a total of twelve term courses. Graduate courses are grouped: (1) metaphysics, theory of knowledge, philosophy of mind, philosophy of language, philosophy of science; (2) ethics, aesthetics, philosophy of religion, political philosophy, philosophy of law, and theory of value; (3) history of philosophy. No more than six of the twelve and no fewer than two courses may be taken in each group. At least one of the twelve courses taken must be logic (unless the logic requirement is satisfied in some other way), and this course does not count toward the required minimum of two within any of the three categories. 2. Two qualifying papers must be submitted, one in the history of philosophy, the other in another distribution area.
    [Show full text]
  • The Good Life: a Defense of Attitudinal Hedonism
    from Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 65 (2002): 604-628 first presented at the Chisholm Memorial Conference Brown University, November 10, 2000 The Good Life: A Defense of Attitudinal Hedonism Fred Feldman University of Massachusetts, Amherst 1. The Good Life The students and colleagues of Roderick Chisholm admired and respected Chisholm. Many were filled not only with admiration, but with affection and gratitude for Chisholm throughout the time we knew him. Even now that he is dead, we continue to wish him well. Under the circumstances, many of us probably think that that wish amounts to no more than this: we hope that things went well for him when he lived; we hope that he had a good life. But reflection on this hope may lead some of us to ask a question: precisely what feature must Chisholm’s life have had in order for that life to have been a good one? What would have made his life one well worth living? On this question there is much puzzlement and many suggested answers. Nowadays one of the most popular answers is that a person’s life goes well if he gets what he wants.1 (Or perhaps that he gets what he really would have wanted if he had thought about it carefully.) According to a currently somewhat less popular answer, what makes a person’s life go well is that he enjoys what he gets. On this view, it does not matter essentially whether the person had any desire for the things he enjoyed prior to his receipt of them, nor does it matter whether he even would have had a desire for them if he had reflected on them.
    [Show full text]
  • The Additive Fallacy Author(S): Shelly Kagan Source: Ethics, Vol. 99, No. 1 (Oct., 1988), Pp
    The Additive Fallacy Author(s): Shelly Kagan Source: Ethics, Vol. 99, No. 1 (Oct., 1988), pp. 5-31 Published by: The University of Chicago Press Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2380927 Accessed: 13-08-2014 16:16 UTC Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. The University of Chicago Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Ethics. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded from 130.132.173.11 on Wed, 13 Aug 2014 16:16:18 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions The Additive Fallacy Shelly Kagan I. CONTRAST ARGUMENTS Much moral philosophy is concerned with defending or attacking the moral relevance of various distinctions. Thus consequentialists disagree with deontologists, and deontologists disagree among themselves, over whether any moral weight should be given to such distinctions as that between what one does and what one merely allows, or to the distinction between what one intends as a means, and what one merely foresees as a side-effect, and so on. Similarly, there is disagreement over the moral relevance of such factors as the motive of the agent, the consequences of a given act, or the guilt of those who may be harmed.
    [Show full text]
  • Normative Ethics
    Philosophy 34: Normative Ethics Matthew Silverstein Spring 2008 Contact Information Office: 204 Cooper House Office Hours: Tuesday, 2:00–5:00 pm, and by appointment Email: [email protected] Phone: (413) 542-8310 Course Description Is anything to be said in a principled way about right and wrong, or good and bad? We will examine a number of positive and negative answers to this question. Our primary focus will be on three of the central traditions of Western ethical philosophy, typified by Aristotle, Immanuel Kant, and John Stuart Mill. We will also study one of modern morality’s harshest critics: Friedrich Nietzsche. Along the way, we will look at contemporary discussions of the relation between the demands of morality and those personal obligations that spring from friendships, as well as recent views about the nature of well-being. Course Requirements There will be one short expository paper (2–3 pages) and two longer critical papers (6–8 pages). Preparation and active participation also count towards your grade. Your final grade will be determined as follows: 20% Short Paper 35% Long Paper 1 35% Long Paper 2 5% Preparation 5% Participation Your preparation grade will be a function of unannounced, in-class ten-minute essay assignments. There will be several such assignments over the course of the semester. Their purpose is to ensure that everyone has studied the assigned reading and to encourage thoughtful discussion in class. Though they will not be graded, I will collect them at the end of class. These essays cannot be made up, and unsatisfactory work will receive no credit.
    [Show full text]
  • A Consequentialist Response to the Demandingness Objection
    1 A CONSEQUENTIALIST RESPONSE TO THE DEMANDINGNESS OBJECTION Nicholas R. Baker, Lee University INTRODUCTION We usually believe that morality has limits; that is, that there is some limit to what morality may reasonably demand of moral agents. We suppose that there are supererog­ atory actions that are just that, supererogatory. We often think that while morality may require some positive and negative obligations, there are at least some actions that are simply permissible.1 This is what the demandingness objection to consequentialism is about; it draws upon our intuitions on these issues in order to show how counter-intuitive the implications of some versions of normative ethics can be. In this paper I will outline and defend the demandingness objection as it applies to act-consequentialism (hereafter AC), then I will argue that rule-consequentialism (hereafter RC), as conceived of by Brad Hooker, is also susceptible to this objection; finally, I will attempt to amend RC so that it may escape the demandingness objection. THE DEMANDS OF ACT CONSEQUENTIALISM Shelly Kagan states in the early parts of his text, The Limits of Morality, that, “[T]here are [. .] what we might think of as limits imposed on morality – for it is typically believed that there are limits to what morality can demand of us.”2 He goes on to further suggest that, “[I]t is generally held that although morality does sometimes require us to make sacrifices, we are not morally required to make our greatest possible contributions to the overall good. There is a limit to moral requirement.”3 While Kagan himself argues for a withholding of judgement as to whether or not these limits do exist, I will be arguing that these limits do, in fact, exist.
    [Show full text]
  • Original Print
    Winter 2001 Published by the American Academy of Religion Vol. 16, No.1 Annual Meeting AAR awarded $1.2 million Denver 2001 Details on page 2 Grant from Pew Charitable Trusts Page 3 Media referral center and scholars database INSIDE to be established THIS ISSUE Annual Meeting News New affiliation Call for Papers Update . .2 with Departments and Programs Page 3 New Program Units Approved . .23 AAR to offer a formal affiliation and expanded New Annual services to departments, programs, and schools Meeting policy . .2 Public intellectual in the schools . .23 New Vice President elected Page 3 Employment Information Robert Orsi joins presidential line Services Center Report . .23 Around the Quadrangle . .8 In Memoriam . .10 Annual Meeting Chairs Workshop a success Page 4 Assessing and Advancing the Religion Department In the Field Regional Meetings . .12 draws chairs to Nashville Grants/Awards . .27 Calendar . .28 Census of Religion and Theology Programs Page 4 Has your program been counted? Features The FBI at the Department Meeting . .16 AAR Annual Meeting in Nashville Page 5 A conversation with Sharon Coggan, University of Colorado, Denver Sensitizing law enforcement officials to religious Beyond the Annual Meeting . .18 Rebecca Alpert discusses the work of the issues. A report on a crisis simulation Committee on the Status of Women in the Profession Teaching beyond the borders Page 7 The Electronic Classroom . .17 Email and students in the religion classroon A report from the Lilly-Luce Teaching Workshop Member-at-Large . .19 Tina Pippin on receiving the Excellence in Teaching Award Research grants awarded Page 13 The Public Interest .
    [Show full text]
  • Professor Shelly Kagan
    Death: Lecture 4 Transcript Chapter 1. Introduction to Plato's Phaedo [00:00:00] Professor Shelly Kagan: We've been talking about the question, "What arguments might be offered for the existence of a soul?" And the family of arguments that we're considering initially are arguments that get known as inference or inferences to the best explanation. The thought is that there's something about us that needs explaining. We can't explain it in terms of… in purely physical terms. And so we need to appeal to, we need to posit, the existence of, a soul. Now, I'll come back to that sort of argument in just a minute, but let me bracket that for a moment and say something about Plato. Starting next week, we're going to be looking at Plato's dialogue, the Phaedo. And so although I'll be saying a great deal about the Phaedo once we turn to it, I want to just take a minute or two and say a couple of introductory remarks. I don't know how many of you have not read any Plato before, but for those of you who haven't, I actually think you're in for a treat. Plato is not only one of the greatest philosophers in history, he wrote his philosophy in the form of dialogues. That is to say, plays, in which various characters sit around or stand around and argue about philosophical positions. The particular dialogue that we're going to be reading, the Phaedo, is set at the death scene of Socrates.
    [Show full text]