6 X 10.5 Long Title.P65

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

6 X 10.5 Long Title.P65 Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-86386-5 - Arguing about Gods Graham Oppy Index More information Index absolute value, 355 beauty, 411 Adams, Bob, 70, 86, 89, 92, 328 begging the question, 5, 11, 30, 51, 52, 57, addition, successive, 142 58, 64, 67, 91, 101, 102, 106, 125, 142, adventitious ideas, 110 182, 229, 347, 354, 356, 364, 367 agnosticism, 37, 39, 53, 58, 129, 179, 231, behaviourism, 396 235, 244, 307, 333, 414, 416, 417 Behe, Michael, 187 Alston, William, 289, 309 belief: coherence, of, 9; and motivation, 40; Anderson, Tony, 70 web of, 8 Anselm, St., 65, 72, 88 Bergmann, Mike, 289, 304, 309 Aquinas, St. Thomas, xvi, 101, 120, 124, 329, big-bang cosmology, 101, 138, 149, 154, 158, 338; Five Ways, 98, 107, 130; The First 172 Way, 102, 103; The Second Way, 99, 102; Big Conjunctive Contingent Fact, 130, 132 The Third Way, 103, 107 Bigelow, John, 274 arguments from evil, xvii, 4, 103, 123, 208, Boyle lectures, 185, 230 259, 321, 328, 402; evidential arguments Brennan, Geoff, 284 from evil, 4, 289, 313; logical arguments Bridgewater treatises, 185, 230 from evil, 4, 262, 289 Bringsjord, Selmer, 395, 398 arguments, minor evidential, 4 brute contingency, 120, 134, 136, 160, 234, arguments, moral, see moral arguments 239 arguments, successful, 7, 10 Bugge, Thomas, 196 arguments, teleological, see teleological Burman, David, 333 arguments Byrne, Alex, 256 Armstrong, David, 274 atheism, 1, 15, 34, 37, 229, 246, 333 Campbell, Richard, 89 Augustine, 328 Cantor, Georg, 33, 139, 140 axiom of choice, 124 Carnap, Rudolf, 67 causation, 3, 97, 98, 99, 100, 101, 102, 170 background knowledge, 176, 177, 182, 209, central state materialism, 396 217, 218, 221, 224, 347, 391 Chalmers, Dave, 399 bacterial flagellum, 192, 195 Chambers, Timothy, 72, 88 Barbour, Ian, 175 Charlesworth, Max, 89 Barcan principle, 125 choice, axiom of, 124 Barnes, Jonathon, 89 Churchland, Pat, 384 Bayesianism, 8, 38, 202, 203, 204, 208, 209, Churchland, Paul, 384 212, 227, 296 Clark, Romane, 101 445 © Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-86386-5 - Arguing about Gods Graham Oppy Index More information 446 Index clear and distinct perception, 108 distributive pantheism, 61 Clifford, William, xviii, 416; Clifford’s divine hiddenness, 407 Principle, xviii, 416, 418, 420, 422, Doolittle, Russell, 196 425 doxastic conservatism, principle of, 15 Clifton, Rob, 132 Duff, Anthony, 254, 256 clutter avoidance, principle of, 29 COBE data, 145, 233 Earman, John, 146 cognitive basicality, 25 efficacy of prayer, 403 cognitive limitations, human, 310 Einstein, Albert, 135, 145, 416 coherence of beliefs, 9 eliminative materialism, 384 collective pantheism, 61 Engels, Friedrich, 360 Collins, Robin, 201 Euthyphro question, 354 combinatorial conception of sets, 139 evil, xvi, 17, 43, 62, 251, 260, 262. See also common consent, 4, 332, 336 arguments from evil Conjunctive Contingent Fact, Big, 130, expert testimony, xviii, 340, 343, 345 132 explanation: personal, 386, 387; scientific, conscience, 369, 371 376, 386, 387, 388, 394, 398; conservatism, principle of, 29 self-explanation, 120, 136, 389 constitution and identity, 68 explanatory filter, 211, 214 contingency, brute, see brute contingency extreme no-devil corollary, 73 converse Barcan principle, 125 Conway, John, 139, 256 fallibilist atheism, 15, 34 cosmological arguments, xv, xvi, 3, 57, 97, fictitious ideas, 110 173, 276, 289, 383 fideism, Wittgensteinian, 50 cosmological constant, 202 Fitch, Frederic, 131 cosmology, 172, 230, 236, 238; see also Fitelson, Branden, 211 big-bang cosmology flagellum, bacterial, 192, 195 costs of irreligion, 365 Flew, Tony, 315 counterfactuals, 155, 159, 277; of freedom, Forrest, Peter, 31, 33 267, 273, 276, 319 freedom, see libertarian freedom Craig, William Lane, 137, 154, 203, free-will defence, 103, 263, 268, 275, 280, 211 316, 321, 328 Craig’s library, 140 free-will theodicies, 103, 260, 316, 317, 321, credulity, principle of, 347 328 cumulative arguments, 5 Frege, Gottlob, 139 Freud, Sigmund, 360 Daniels, Charles, 41 FRW models, 145, 146 Darwin, Charles, 186, 192, 199, 230, 236, 239, 411; The Origin of Species, 232 G. E. Moore shift, 291 Davey, Ken, 132 Gaine, Simon, 316, 320 Dawkins, Richard, 186, 194, 229, 231 Gale, Richard, 50, 130, 262 deism, 31 Gaunilo, xvi, 73, 93 Dembski, William, 211, 216 general relativity, 141, 145, 146, 170, 172 depravity, transworld, 279, 319 Geroch, Robert, 146 ∗ Descartes, Ren´e, xvi, 93, 97, 107, 119; god , 35 Meditation III, 107, 118 god , 43 devil corollary, 73 G¨odel, Kurt, 70 Devine, Philip, 72 Godfrey-Smith, Peter, 284 disagreement between reasonable people, god-likeness, 70 7 gravitation, 201 dispositional theory of mind, 274 Gr¨unbaum,Adolf, 147, 148 dissective sentential operator, 131 Guy, Reed, 161 © Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-86386-5 - Arguing about Gods Graham Oppy Index More information Index 447 Hacking, Ian, 223 Kripke, Saul, 134 H´ajek, Alan, 256, 257 Kvanvig, Jonathon, 323 Hall, Barry, 196 Kwang, Cha, 403 happiness, 358, 361 Harman, Gilbert, 29 La Croix, Richard, 89 Harris, William, 403 Langtry, Bruce, 50 Hartle, Jim, 154 Lavine, Shaughan, 118 Hartle-Hawking cosmology, 160 law of the simplest beginning, 160 Hawking, Stephen, 154 Leibniz, Gottfried, xvi, 119, 124, 130 Hazen, Allen, 70 Leslie, John, 216, 239 heaven, 62, 250, 254, 256, 260, 314, 329, Lewis, David, 31, 32, 58, 89, 92, 163, 315 368 libertarian freedom, 102, 103, 113, 123, 152, Hempel, Peter, 387 265, 272, 275, 286, 316, 321, 327 Hick, John, 411 Locke, John, 382, 395 Hilbert’s Hotel, 140 logical conception of sets, 139 historical tradition, 336, 339 Howard-Snyder, Dan, 262, 289, 303, 309 Mackie, John, xvii, 229, 236, 262, 283, 288, human cognitive limitations, 310 333, 353, 371, 384, 398, 400 Hume, David, 183, 187, 228, 244, 333, 376, Malcolm, Norman, 89 379, 417; Dialogues Concerning Natural Mann, William, 89 Religion, xvii, 44, 231; Humeanism, 42 Manson, Neil, xvii, 202, 204 many gods objection, 250, 254 ideas: adventitious, 110; fictitious, 110 Markosian, Ned, 161, 163, 167 identity of arguments, 11 Martin, Charlie, 274 identity of indiscernibles, 220 Martin, Michael, 315, 321 illness, 403, 404 Marx, Karl, 360 indifference, principle of, 205 materialism, 384, 396 infinite regress, 3, 98, 101, 106, 117, 120, mathematical knowledge, 14, 109, 139, 404, 146, 148, 234 405 infinity, 96, 104, 114, 118, 141, 143, 168, Matson, Wallace, 186 169, 237, 240, 249, 254, 257, 329 McGrew, Tim, 205 information, xviii, 7, 26, 46, 61, 71, 122, 168, McLaughlin, Robert, 22 199, 210, 214, 250, 286, 287, 403, 409, mereological ontological argument, 49, 56, 410, 419 59, 69, 96 innate ideas, 110 meta-ethics, 42 innocent, 37 Meyer, Bob, 123 innocuity thesis, 80, 84 Miller, Kenneth, 196 inverse gambler’s fallacy, 216, 223 minor evidential arguments, 4 irreducible complexity, 188, 197 miracles, 4, 43, 331, 347, 350, 376, 381 modal interpretations, 92 Jackson, Frank, 397 modal logic, 59, 70, 103, 125, 126, 132 James, William, xviii, 418, 422 modal ontological arguments, 49, 374 Jesus, 406 modal principles, 125 justice, 363, 365, 373 modal realism, 31, 62, 66 modality, 3, 98, 100, 134, 171, 220, 272, 404 kala¯m cosmological arguments, 97, 101, 106, Molinism, 155, 319 124, 137, 153, 155 moral arguments, xviii, 4, 33, 331, 352, 356, Kant, Immanuel, 72, 97, 372; Classification 372, 375 of Arguments, 1, 2; First Antinomy, 144 moral belief, 40 Kenny, Anthony, 98 moral evil, 260, 262, 280, 328 Koons, Rob, 97, 125, 130 moral knowledge, 40, 44 Kragh, Helge, 145 moral perfection, 77 © Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-86386-5 - Arguing about Gods Graham Oppy Index More information 448 Index morality, 122, 248, 278, 313, 352, 372, 405 principle of clutter avoidance, 29 mystery, 236, 408, 412 principle of conservatism, 29 mystical experience, 346, 347, 350 principle of credulity, 347 principle of doxastic conservatism, 15 negative undermining, principle of, 29 principle of indifference, 205 Newman, John, 369 principle of negative undermining, 29 Newton, Isaac, 233 principle of positive undermining, 29 Newtonian cosmology, 233 principle of sufficient reason, 119, 121, 130, nihilism, ontological, 60 137, 141, 152, 171, 275, 282 no-devil corollary, 73 principle of testimony, 348 Nolan, Daniel, 69 prior belief, 8 non-arbitrary improvement, 293, 294 prior probability, 8 non-evidential arguments, 5 proper function of arguments, 10 null part, 69 Proslogion, 65, 72 Proslogion II, 58, 89 objective chance, 163, 167, 170, 221, 223, providence, 401 224 Pruss, Alex, 130 objective values, 352, 356 observational selection effects, 209 quantifier-exchange fallacy, 60 Ockham, William of, 329 Quine, Willard, 8, 67 Ockham’s Razor, 20, 22, 29 ontological arguments, xv, 2, 3, 49, 96, 232 Rashdall, Hastings, 353 Ontological Arguments and Belief in God redundancy thesis, 77, 80 (Oppy), xvi, 35, 49, 96 regularity, 38, 246 ontological nihilism, 60 Rowe, William, 289 Oppenheimer, Paul, 89 Russell, Bertrand, 139, 363 Oppy, Graham, 49, 64, 70, 96, 133, 144, 206 Russell, Bruce, 308 Rutherford, Ernest, 381 Paley, William, 174, 187; Natural Theology, Ryle, Gilbert, 274 175, 187, 200 pantheism, 61 sceptical theism, 289 paradox of the preface, 35 scientific explanation, 376, 386, 387, 388, Parfit, Derek, 315 394, 398 parsimony, 212 scope, 391 Pascal, Blaise, 21; Pascal’s wager, 21, 258, Scott, Dana, 70 368; Pensees´ , 243 Scotus, Duns, 320, 329 Paul, Gregory, 357 scripture, xviii, 4, 17, 27, 35, 43, 259, 304, Penrose,
Recommended publications
  • Ontological Arguments
    Ontological Arguments Graham Oppy Ontological arguments are arguments, for the conclusion that God exists, from premises which are supposed to derive from some source other than observation of the world — e.g., from reason alone. In other words, ontological arguments are arguments from nothing but analytic, a priori and necessary premises to the conclusion that God exists. The first, and best-known, ontological argument was proposed by St. Anselm of Canterbury in the 11th. century A.D. In his Proslogion , St. Anselm claims to derive the existence of God from the concept of a being than which no greater can be conceived . St. Anselm reasoned that, if such a being fails to exist, then a greater being — namely, a being than which no greater can be conceived, and which exists — can be conceived. But this would be absurd: nothing can be greater than a being than which no greater can be conceived. So a being than which no greater can be conceived — i.e., God — exists. In the seventeenth century, René Descartes defended a family of similar arguments. For instance, in the Fifth Meditation , Descartes claims to provide a proof demonstrating the existence of God from the idea of a supremely perfect being. Descartes argues that there is no less contradiction in conceiving a supremely perfect being who lacks existence than there is in conceiving a triangle whose interior angles do not sum to 180 degrees. Hence, he supposes, since we do conceive a supremely perfect being — we do have the idea of a supremely perfect being — we must conclude that a supremely perfect being exists.
    [Show full text]
  • Uncaused Beginnings" Revisited
    Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers Volume 32 Issue 2 Article 8 4-1-2015 "Uncaused Beginnings" Revisited Graham Oppy Follow this and additional works at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy Recommended Citation Oppy, Graham (2015) ""Uncaused Beginnings" Revisited," Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers: Vol. 32 : Iss. 2 , Article 8. DOI: 10.5840/faithphil20154932 Available at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy/vol32/iss2/8 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers by an authorized editor of ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. "UNCAUSED BEGINNINGS" REVISITED Graham Oppy William Lane Craig's "Reflections on 'Uncaused Beginnings" is a sustained critique of my "Uncaused Beginnings." 1 argue that the central arguments of my essay survive that critique unscathed. When we make a fair and accurate comparison of naturalist and theist claims about global causal reality, we see that considerations about causation and the shape of causal reality do not decide between naturalism and theism. Moreover, the Edwards/Prior/Craig objection does not rule out the view that there is an initial global causal state involving none but contingently existing entities. 1 Compare two views about global causal reality. Both views suppose that there is a contingent initial global causal state involving at least one neces• sarily existent entity. Both views suppose that the initial global causal state is the only global causal state that has no cause; both views also suppose that the only further causal states that have no cause are initial states of en• tities that belong to and/or are sub-states of the initial global causal state.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy for Us
    Philosophy for Us First Edition Edited By Lenny Clapp Northern Illinois University Bassim Hamadeh, CEO and Publisher Kassie Graves, Director of Acquisitions and Sales Jamie Giganti, Senior Managing Editor Jess Estrella, Senior Graphic Designer Angela Schultz, Acquisitions Editor Michelle Piehl, Project Editor Trey Soto, Licensing Associate Christian Berk, Associate Production Editor Bryan Mok, Interior Designer Copyright © 2018 by Cognella, Inc. All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be re- printed, reproduced, transmitted, or utilized in any form or by any electronic, mechanical, or other means, now known or hereafter invented, including photocopying, microfilming, and recording, or in any information retrieval system without the written permission of Cognella, Inc. For inquiries regarding permissions, translations, foreign rights, audio rights, and any other forms of reproduction, please contact the Cognella Licensing Department at [email protected]. Trademark Notice: Product or corporate names may be trademarks or registered trademarks, and are used only for identification and explanation without intent to infringe. Cover image copyright © 2014 iStockphoto LP/alvarez. Printed in the United States of America. ISBN: 978-1-63487-487-8 (pbk) / 978-1-63487-488-5 (br) This book is dedicated to my friend and mentor Tomis Kapitan. Tomis believed that philosophy could improve the lives of everyone, and this belief influenced not only his teaching, but his courageous approach to life. This book is inspired by his example. Contents Part I: Does God Exist? 1 1. An Argument for Atheism from Naturalism ..............................................3 by Graham Oppy, Monash University 2. The Case for Divine Creation from Cosmic Fine-tuning .......................................................................................................15 by Robin Collins, Messiah College 3.
    [Show full text]
  • Century Atheism, in the History of Western Philosophy of Religion : V
    This is the published version Oppy, Graham and Trakakis, Nick 2009, Late-twentieth-century atheism, in The history of western philosophy of religion : v. 5. Twentieth-century philosophy of religion, Acumen Publishing Ltd, Durham, England, pp.301-312. Available from Deakin Research Online http://hdl.handle.net/10536/DRO/DU:30022451 Every reasonable effort has been made to ensure that permission has been obtained for items included in Deakin Research Online. If you believe that your rights have been infringed by this repository, please contact [email protected] Copyright: 2009, Acumen Publishing 24 LATE-TWENTIETH -CENTURY ATHEISM Graham Oppy and Nick Trakakis In 1948, the BBC broadcast a debate between Bertrand Russell and Father Frederick Copleston on the existence of God (Russell & Copleston 1957). In that debate, Copleston claims: (i) that the existence of God can be proved by a meta­ physical argument from contingency; and (ii) that only the postulation of the existence of God can make sense of our religious and moral experience. Russell replies by giving diverse reasons for thinking that these two claims are incorrect: there are various ways in which Copleston's argument from contingency fails to be persuasive, and there are more plausible alternative explanations of our religious and moral experience. While there are many significant changes of detail, it is fair to say that the debate between Russell and Copleston typifies exchanges between theists and atheists in the second half of the twentieth century, and it is also fair to say that Russell's contribution to this debate typifies the approaches of late twen­ tieth-centuryatheists.
    [Show full text]
  • Inscrutable Evils, Skeptical Theism, and the Epistemology of Religious Trust
    University of Tennessee, Knoxville TRACE: Tennessee Research and Creative Exchange Doctoral Dissertations Graduate School 8-2013 Inscrutable Evils, Skeptical Theism, and the Epistemology of Religious Trust John David McClellan [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://trace.tennessee.edu/utk_graddiss Part of the Epistemology Commons Recommended Citation McClellan, John David, "Inscrutable Evils, Skeptical Theism, and the Epistemology of Religious Trust. " PhD diss., University of Tennessee, 2013. https://trace.tennessee.edu/utk_graddiss/2459 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at TRACE: Tennessee Research and Creative Exchange. It has been accepted for inclusion in Doctoral Dissertations by an authorized administrator of TRACE: Tennessee Research and Creative Exchange. For more information, please contact [email protected]. To the Graduate Council: I am submitting herewith a dissertation written by John David McClellan entitled "Inscrutable Evils, Skeptical Theism, and the Epistemology of Religious Trust." I have examined the final electronic copy of this dissertation for form and content and recommend that it be accepted in partial fulfillment of the equirr ements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy, with a major in Philosophy. E. J. Coffman, Major Professor We have read this dissertation and recommend its acceptance: Richard E. Aquila, John E. Nolt, Carl G. Wagner Accepted for the Council: Carolyn R. Hodges Vice Provost and Dean of the Graduate School (Original signatures are on file with official studentecor r ds.) Inscrutable Evils, Skeptical Theism, and the Epistemology of Religious Trust A Dissertation Presented for the Doctor of Philosophy Degree The University of Tennessee, Knoxville John David McClellan August 2013 Copyright © 2013 by John David McClellan All rights reserved.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter *** Philosophy, Religion, and Worldview Graham Oppy This
    Chapter *** Philosophy, Religion, and Worldview Graham Oppy This chapter consists of a series of reflections on widely endorsed claims about Christian philosophy and, in particular, Christian philosophy of religion. It begins with consideration of some claims about how (Christian) philosophy of religion currently is, and then moves on to consideration of some claims about how (Christian) philosophy of religion ought to be. The Triumphalist Narrative An oft-told triumphalist narrative holds that we are currently in a golden age for Christian philosophy of religion. While the details of the narrative vary, the central thread is that the bad old days have been replaced by good times. In the bad old days, philosophy of religion was in the doldrums, Christian philosophers were not pursuing philosophy of religion, Christian philosophers were hiding their Christian credentials under a bushel, Christian philosophers were held in contempt by ‘establishment’ philosophers, philosophy of religion had low status, philosophy of religion was not published in high-status generalist journals, philosophy of religion had no presence in major philosophy conferences, major presses were not taking on books in philosophy of religion, and philosophy of religion was not being taught in the higher education sector. But good times have returned: philosophy of religion is booming, Christian philosophers are pursuing Christian philosophy of religion, Christian philosophers are proudly proclaiming their Christianity to the academy and the world at large, philosophy of religion has high status, philosophy of religion is published in high-status generalist journals, philosophy of religion has a significant presence in major philosophy 1 conferences, major presses are publishing loads of books in philosophy of religion, and philosophy of religion is widely taught in the higher education sector.
    [Show full text]
  • From Classical to Intuitionistic Probability 1 Introduction
    From Classical to Intuitionistic Probability Brian Weatherson Abstract We generalize the Kolmogorov axioms for probability calculus to obtain conditions defining, for any given logic, a class of probability functions relative to that logic, coinciding with the standard probability functions in the special case of classical logic but allowing consideration of other classes of “essentially Kolmogorovian” probability functions relative to other logics. We take a broad view of the Bayesian approach as dictating inter alia that from the perspective of a given logic, rational degrees of be- lief are those representable by probability functions from the class appro- priate to that logic. Classical Bayesianism, which fixes the logic as classi- cal logic, is only one version of this general approach. Another, which we call Intuitionistic Bayesianism, selects intuitionistic logic as the preferred logic and the associated class of probability functions as the right class of candidate representions of epistemic states (rational allocations of de- grees of belief). Various objections to classical Bayesianism are, we argue, best met by passing to intuitionistic Bayesianism – in which the proba- bility functions are taken relative to intuitionistic logic – rather than by adopting a radically non-Kolmogorovian, e.g. non-additive, conception of (or substitute for) probability functions, in spite of the popularity of the latter response amongst those who have raised these objections. The interest of intuitionistic Bayesianism is further enhanced by the availabil- ity of a Dutch Book argument justifying the selection of intuitionistic probability functions as guides to rational betting behaviour when due consideration is paid to the fact that bets are settled only when/if the outcome betted on becomes known.
    [Show full text]
  • Bibliography
    BIBLIOGRAPHY Abraham, William J., and Steven W. Holtzer (eds). The Rationality of Religious Belief: Essays in Honour of Basil Mitchell. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1987. Adams, Marilyn McCord. “Redemptive Suffering: A Christian Solution to the Problem of Evil,” in Audi and Wainwright (eds), Rationality, Religious Belief, and Moral Commitment, 1986, pp. 248–67. ———. “Problems of Evil: More Advice to Christian Philosophers,” Faith and Philosophy 5 (1988): 121–43. ———. “Theodicy Without Blame,” Philosophical Topics 16 (1988): 215–45. ———. “Horrendous Evils and the Goodness of God,” The Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 63 (1989): 297–310. ———. “God and Evil: Polarities of a Problem,” Philosophical Studies 69 (1993): 167–86. ———. “Evil, Problem of,” in Craig (ed.), Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy, vol.3, 1998, pp. 466–72. ———. Horrendous Evils and the Goodness of God. Melbourne: Melbourne University Press, 1999. Adams, Marilyn McCord, and Robert Merrihew Adams (eds). The Problem of Evil. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990. Adams, Robert Merrihew. “A Modified Divine Command Theory of Ethical Wrongness,” in Outka and Reeder (eds), Religion and Morality, 1973, pp. 318–47. ———. “Divine Command Metaethics Modified Again,” Journal of Religious Ethics 7 (1979): 66–79. ———. “Plantinga on the Problem of Evil,” in Tomberlin and van Inwagen (eds), Alvin Plantinga, 1985, pp. 225–55. ———. The Virtue of Faith and Other Essays in Philosophical Theology. New York: Oxford University Press, 1987. Ahern, M.B. The Problem of Evil. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1971. Allen, Robert Francis. “St. Augustine’s Free Will Theodicy and Natural Evil,” Ars Disputandi: The Online Journal for Philosophy of Religion 3 (2003), URL ϭϽhttp://www.ArsDisputandi.orgϾ.
    [Show full text]
  • Metaphysical Naturalism and the Ignorance of Categorical Properties
    Copyright © 2017 by Lok-Chi Chan Thesis supervisor: Professor David Braddon-Mitchell Department of Philosophy, The University of Sydney Cover design: Chan Man Yuk i Declaration I certify that the intellectual content of this thesis is the product of my own work. Assistance received in preparing this thesis and sources have been acknowledged. Lok-Chi Chan ii Abstract The purpose of this dissertation is to investigate the connections between metaphysical naturalism and the categorical ignorance thesis – offered by Rae Langton (1998), David Lewis (2009), Frank Jackson (1998), and Simon Blackburn (1990) – and determine whether the latter will challenge the former. According to metaphysical naturalism, the actual world contains only metaphysically natural things. According to the categorical ignorance thesis, all we can know about things are their dispositional properties, but the categorical properties that bear these properties remain in principle unknowable. In this dissertation, I will determine whether the ignorance of categorical properties – as Rae Langton (1998), David Braddon-Mitchell and Frank Jackson (2007), John Foster (1993) and Alyssa Ney (2007) argue (or worry about) – is consistent with metaphysical naturalism (or physicalism), and whether it will lead to a scepticism about the metaphysical naturalness of categorical properties, which will, in turn, significantly decrease the probability that metaphysical naturalism is true. Being attracted to metaphysical naturalism, the categorical ignorance thesis, and also the philosophical position that the two theses are consistent, I will argue that the answer to the former question is yes, and that the answer to the latter question is no. Russellian Monism, an influential doctrine in philosophy of mind that is relevant to the topic, will also be considered.
    [Show full text]
  • The University of Chicago the Ontological Argument, Its Criticisms and Consequences a Dissertation Submitted to the Faculty of T
    THE UNIVERSITY OF CHICAGO THE ONTOLOGICAL ARGUMENT, ITS CRITICISMS AND CONSEQUENCES A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE FACULTY OF THE DIVINITY SCHOOL IN CANDIDACY FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY BY JASON GRANT CATHER CHICAGO, ILLINOIS AUGUST 2017 Copyright c 2017 by Jason Grant Cather All Rights Reserved TABLE OF CONTENTS ACKNOWLEDGMENTS . vi 1 NEOCLASSICAL METAPHYSICS FOR THE ONTOLOGICAL ARGUMENT . 1 1.1 Overview . .1 1.2 The Appeal of the Ontological Argument . .2 1.3 On the Nature of Argument . .5 1.4 The Appeal of Neoclassical Metaphysics . .5 1.5 How to Think About Divine Greatness . .9 1.5.1 The Ontological Principle . .9 1.5.2 Actual Entities . .9 1.5.3 Societies . 10 1.5.4 Eternal Objects . 11 1.5.5 God . 12 1.6 Neoclassical Metaphysics as a Modal Metaphysics . 13 1.7 Neoclassical Understandings of Existential Statements . 14 1.8 Conclusion . 16 2 WHAT MAKES AN ARGUMENT ONTOLOGICAL? . 18 2.1 Overview . 18 2.2 Identifying Arguments as Ontological . 19 2.3 An Absurdly Brief History of the Debate Surrounding the Argument . 22 2.4 Parameters for Successful Arguments, or What Can We Expect an Argument toDo?....................................... 33 2.5 What Does a Parody Do? . 36 2.6 Are the Parodies Ontological? . 39 2.7 From Parody to Parity . 41 2.8 Conclusion . 42 3 ON FORMULATIONS OF ONTOLOGICAL ARGUMENTS . 43 3.1 Overview . 43 3.2 From Parody to Caricature . 43 3.3 Two Interpretations . 45 3.4 Is the Argument Just for Theists? . 51 3.5 Ontologically Neutral Formulations . 53 3.5.1 Is Neutrality Really Desirable? .
    [Show full text]
  • Graham Oppy Logic and Theism Is a Very Fine Book, Crammed With
    REVIEW ARTICLE LOGIC AND THEISM: ARGUMENTS FOR AND AGAINST BELIEFS IN GOD, BY JORDAN HOWARD SOBEL (CAMBRIDGE: CUP), XIX+652 PP. HARDBACK. Graham Oppy Logic and Theism is a very fine book, crammed with detailed analyses of arguments for and against belief in God. It is not a book that can be read quickly; but it is a book that repays effort invested in it by readers. Despite the fact that it is a very large book, and despite the wide range of the arguments that are considered, the book is not intended to be a comprehensive assessment of arguments for and against belief in God. This is one way in which it contrasts with, say, John Mackie’s The Miracle of Theism or Michael Martin’s Atheism: A Philosophical Justification. There is no serious discussion in Sobel’s book of, for example, arguments from religious experience, arguments from consciousness, arguments from morality, arguments from the natural history of religion, and sundry other minor arguments for the existence of God. Moreover, the book contains no serious discussion of, for example, the meaningfulness of religious talk, anti-realist construals of religious talk, the critiques of religion offered by Feuerbach, Marx, Engels, Freud, and Nietzsche, and so forth. The book makes considerable use of technical logical and mathematical machinery. Arguments are frequently given symbolisations in first-order predicate calculus or extensions thereof; and, where these symbolisations correspond to valid arguments in the relevant logical systems, detailed derivations are supplied. Several chapters make use of the mathematics of probability, in ways that require more than just nodding acquaintance with standard formulations of Bayes’ Theorem.
    [Show full text]
  • ABSTRACT Explanation in Metaphysics Daniel M. Johnson, Ph
    ABSTRACT Explanation in Metaphysics Daniel M. Johnson, Ph.D. Mentor: Alexander R. Pruss, Ph.D. One of the primary tasks of the philosopher is to explain what it is for something to be the case—what it is for one event (substance, fact) to cause another, what it is for an action to be obligatory, what it is for an object to bear a property, what it is for a proposition to be true necessarily, what it is for a person to know something. This activity of explaining what something is or what it is for something to be the case, of identifying what I call ontological explanations, is of special importance to metaphysics, since the task of metaphysics generally is to get to the bottom of reality. The concept of ontological explanation is usually buried a layer deep in most discussions, however, and theses about it are either presupposed or clothed as claims about other things. In some cases, this leads to confusion and frustration, and in many other cases the discussion could benefit from a long look at ontological explanation even if that look isn’t strictly necessary to remedy confusion. My goal is to give ontological explanation that long look, and then use the clarity gained to reinterpret, reorganize, and even make progress on some long-standing disputes in metaphysics. In the first two chapters I examine ontological explanation itself and connect it to a host of important metaphysical issues, including ontological commitment and truthmaker theory. In the third and fourth chapters, I apply the work done in the first two chapters to a pair of important metaphysical arguments that crucially employ infinite regresses of ontological explanations—Bradley’s Regress and McTaggart’s Paradox.
    [Show full text]