Walsh on Miller, 'Reading Popular Newtonianism: Print, the Principia, and the Dissemination of Newtonian Science'

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Walsh on Miller, 'Reading Popular Newtonianism: Print, the Principia, and the Dissemination of Newtonian Science' H-Albion Walsh on Miller, 'Reading Popular Newtonianism: Print, the Principia, and the Dissemination of Newtonian Science' Review published on Wednesday, July 29, 2020 Laura Miller. Reading Popular Newtonianism: Print, the Principia, and the Dissemination of Newtonian Science. Charlottesville: University of Virginia Press, 2018. 248 pp. $45.00 (cloth), ISBN 978-0-8139-4125-7. Reviewed by Kirsten Walsh (University of Exeter)Published on H-Albion (July, 2020) Commissioned by Jeffrey R. Wigelsworth (Red Deer College) Printable Version: http://www.h-net.org/reviews/showpdf.php?id=53076 It is difficult to overstate Sir Isaac Newton’s importance to the development of modern science. His Principia, published in 1686, redirected physics and set its agenda for two hundred years. Along the way, Newton became a near-mythic figure: as Laura Miller puts it in Reading Popular Newtonianism, “Newton’s was a household name that represented the heights of English rational achievement” (p. 128). By the end of the eighteenth century, Newtonianism had become as much a cultural phenomenon as a scientific one. Focusing on the reception of Newton’sPrincipia across non-expert audiences, Miller weaves a captivating tale of popular Newtonianism, the emerging middle classes, and the culture of print in the eighteenth century. Each chapter can be read as a stand-alone piece, but together they form a coherent and compelling narrative that takes us from the expert epicenter of Newtonianism in the late seventeenth century through to its still-reverberating tremors across popular culture at the close of the eighteenth century. The story starts, naturally enough, with Newton. In chapter 1, Miller explores the traces of Newton’s engagement with print as a reader. Through marginalia, dog-eared pages, and references from Newton’s own writings, she paints an image of Newton as someone keenly aware (perhaps paranoidly so) of how public perception can be influenced by print. In chapter 2, we turn from Newton-the-reader to Newton-the-author, specifically, of thePrincipia . Focusing on the content and design of thePrincipia , Miller shows how Newton exploited print conventions to facilitate engagement with the book’s arguments and concepts at many different levels, by audiences with varying degrees of expertise. While few readers could have obtained deep understanding of the mathematical demonstrations, Miller argues that clever use of typography and diagrams worked to foreground and simplify the central ideas, meaning that many were nonetheless able to follow the main claims and basic arguments. And so, for Miller, thePrincipia is a book that simultaneously invites readers in and keeps them at a distance—both from the tricky mathematics and from Newton himself—and in so doing, secures Newton’s position at the top of the intellectual hierarchy. The Principia, then, was not the inaccessible, alienating, and poorly understood (except for a few elite mathematicians) work that it is often painted as. As Miller stresses, this allows us to make Citation: H-Net Reviews. Walsh on Miller, 'Reading Popular Newtonianism: Print, the Principia, and the Dissemination of Newtonian Science'. H-Albion. 07-29-2020. https://networks.h-net.org/node/16749/reviews/6291664/walsh-miller-reading-popular-newtonianism-print-principia-and Licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0 United States License. 1 H-Albion sense of the Principia’s vast reach into eighteenth-century popular culture. We then move from Newton himself to the transmission of Newtonian ideas through poetry. In chapter 3, Miller focuses on two poems, Edmond Halley’s “Ode to Newton” (1687) and James Thomson’s “A Poem Sacred to the Memory of Sir Isaac Newton” (1730), the latter of which, she argues, reached a much wider audience than previously assumed. Miller argues that poetry was instrumental in the widespread transmission of information about both Newton and his ideas. She shows how Halley and Thomson deliberately and knowingly constructed the image of Newton as hypermasculine and solitary. In so doing, such poetry associated scientific excellence with superior masculinity, in contrast with the gentlemanliness and sociability often promoted within the Royal Society. Newton’s social isolation and general reluctance to publish were framed as features that placed him above other men. In chapter 4, we move from poetry to popular science texts. Here, Miller focuses on the many editions of Francesco Algarotti’s Newtonianism for Ladies (originally published in Italian in 1737). Despite its title, Newtonianism for Ladies was by no means exclusively read by women, nor was it intended to be. Miller shows that Algarotti had a wider and more diffuse influence on the uptake of Newtonian ideas among the British middle classes than has previously been recognized. The book should be understood as part of a general trend toward catering to an emerging middle class with an avid desire for cultural sophistication. Indeed, Algarotti fed this appetite by producing popular books about painting and opera as well as science. Miller also describes piracy, the sexualization (in print) of both Newton and his ideas, and the strategies employed to package and market Newtonianism to various audiences. The fifth and final chapter is a highlight. Here, Miller considers popular Newtonianism from the context of a community of readers—specifically, members of the small, developing New York Society Library at the end of the eighteenth century. Miller uses the first charging ledger of the library (1789–92)—a fascinating resource in itself!—as an inroads to the borrowing patterns across a diverse readership who sampled a wide variety of works containing Newtonian natural philosophy, from popularizations and encyclopedias to novels. The resulting patterns challenge the idea that Newtonian popularizations were read by people with a specific interest in science and a limited scientific education, who would encounter “dumbed down” versions of scientific works. Instead, borrowing practices reveal more diverse uses: some families would take out popularizations of all kinds, while others mingled their popular science with works containing more substantial scientific content. Miller describes Newtonian popularizations as “gateway” books, opening readers to many different topics and kinds of reading, related in many different ways. Reading Popular Newtonianism is thematically rich and, as a historian of philosophy, I sometimes found it difficult to pin down precisely what substantive points were being made. Nevertheless, I think this book offers some important lessons for the history and philosophy of science in the present day. I shall briefly highlight three of them. First, a lesson about the nature of popularization. Miller emphasizes the dynamic nature of Newtonianism through the long eighteenth century. Scholars have long recognized this feature vis-à- vis practitioners (natural philosophers, mathematicians, etc.). When thinking about non-experts, however, there has been a tacit assumption of homogeneity concerning the Newtonianism that Citation: H-Net Reviews. Walsh on Miller, 'Reading Popular Newtonianism: Print, the Principia, and the Dissemination of Newtonian Science'. H-Albion. 07-29-2020. https://networks.h-net.org/node/16749/reviews/6291664/walsh-miller-reading-popular-newtonianism-print-principia-and Licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-Noncommercial-No Derivative Works 3.0 United States License. 2 H-Albion filtered down in highly simplified form to amateur audiences. Instead, Miller presents popular Newtonianism as a phenomenon in flux: changing, developing, and evolving across time, place, and context. Second, a point about the exclusivity of Western science. Newtonianism was presented as something for, rather than by women. In chapter 3, Miller demonstrates the purposeful construction of the “masculinity” of science. This image is insidious and entrenched, and likely has a long reach underwriting the present inequalities we see for women, BAME, and people from low socioeconomic backgrounds in many scientific disciplines. These attitudes were not invented with Newton—the history of Western science is largely a history of exclusion—but, just as Newtonianism played a crucial role in bringing science to the emerging middle classes, it also played a role in reinforcing the exclusion of women from science and medicine. The masculinization, gentrification, and whitewashing of science has been costly. It has narrowed the topics, attitudes, and perspectives introduced by practitioners and limited the ways in which communities can engage with and benefit from science, medicine, and technology. Miller offers an important analysis of the ways that language and print practices operate to reinforce such attitudes. Third, a point about how ideas are packaged and disseminated. Miller shows us that non-expert readers did not encounter Newton’s ideas in all their complexity and completeness. Even those who read the Principia only grasped certain ideas, engaging with it in ways circumscribed by the text itself. According to Miller, this was by Newton’s design: which ideas a reader was able to take from the Principia reflected Newton’s presentation and editorial decisions. Similarly, the Newtonian ideas encountered elsewhere reflected decisions made by those authors about what was important, crucial, or central to understanding Newton. As Newton became increasingly identified with his writings, an image of Newton the
Recommended publications
  • Newton.Indd | Sander Pinkse Boekproductie | 16-11-12 / 14:45 | Pag
    omslag Newton.indd | Sander Pinkse Boekproductie | 16-11-12 / 14:45 | Pag. 1 e Dutch Republic proved ‘A new light on several to be extremely receptive to major gures involved in the groundbreaking ideas of Newton Isaac Newton (–). the reception of Newton’s Dutch scholars such as Willem work.’ and the Netherlands Jacob ’s Gravesande and Petrus Prof. Bert Theunissen, Newton the Netherlands and van Musschenbroek played a Utrecht University crucial role in the adaption and How Isaac Newton was Fashioned dissemination of Newton’s work, ‘is book provides an in the Dutch Republic not only in the Netherlands important contribution to but also in the rest of Europe. EDITED BY ERIC JORINK In the course of the eighteenth the study of the European AND AD MAAS century, Newton’s ideas (in Enlightenment with new dierent guises and interpre- insights in the circulation tations) became a veritable hype in Dutch society. In Newton of knowledge.’ and the Netherlands Newton’s Prof. Frans van Lunteren, sudden success is analyzed in Leiden University great depth and put into a new perspective. Ad Maas is curator at the Museum Boerhaave, Leiden, the Netherlands. Eric Jorink is researcher at the Huygens Institute for Netherlands History (Royal Dutch Academy of Arts and Sciences). / www.lup.nl LUP Newton and the Netherlands.indd | Sander Pinkse Boekproductie | 16-11-12 / 16:47 | Pag. 1 Newton and the Netherlands Newton and the Netherlands.indd | Sander Pinkse Boekproductie | 16-11-12 / 16:47 | Pag. 2 Newton and the Netherlands.indd | Sander Pinkse Boekproductie | 16-11-12 / 16:47 | Pag.
    [Show full text]
  • Newton's Mathematical Physics
    Isaac Newton A new era in science Waseda University, SILS, Introduction to History and Philosophy of Science LE201, History and Philosophy of Science Newton . Newton’s Legacy Newton brought to a close the astronomical revolution begun by Copernicus. He combined the dynamic research of Galileo with the astronomical work of Kepler. He produced an entirely new cosmology and a new way of thinking about the world, based on the interaction between matter and mathematically determinate forces. He joined the mathematical and experimental methods: the hypothetico-deductive method. His work became the model for rational mechanics as it was later practiced by mathematicians, particularly during the Enlightenment. LE201, History and Philosophy of Science Newton . William Blake’s Newton (1795) LE201, History and Philosophy of Science Newton LE201, History and Philosophy of Science Newton . Newton’s De Motu coporum in gyrum Edmond Halley (of the comet) visited Cambridge in 1684 and 1 talked with Newton about inverse-square forces (F 9 d2 ). Newton stated that he has already shown that inverse-square force implied an ellipse, but could not find the documents. Later he rewrote this into a short document called De Motu coporum in gyrum, and sent it to Halley. Halley was excited and asked for a full treatment of the subject. Two years later Newton sent Book I of The Mathematical Principals of Natural Philosophy (Principia). Key Point The goal of this project was to derive the orbits of bodies from a simpler set of assumptions about motion. That is, it sought to explain Kepler’s Laws with a simpler set of laws.
    [Show full text]
  • Reposs #19: Newtonianism in the Scandinavian Countries, 1690–1790
    RePoSS: Research Publications on Science Studies RePoSS #19: Newtonianism in the Scandinavian Countries, 1690–1790 Helge Kragh August 2012 Centre for Science Studies, University of Aarhus, Denmark Research group: History and philosophy of science Please cite this work as: Helge Kragh (Aug. 2012). Newtonianism in the Scandinavian Countries, 1690–1790. RePoSS: Research Publications on Sci- ence Studies 19. Aarhus: Centre for Science Studies, University of Aarhus. url: http://www.css.au.dk/reposs. Copyright c Helge Kragh, 2012 1 Newtonianism in the Scandinavian Countries, 1690-1790 HELGE KRAGH 1 Introduction In the present context, the Scandinavian countries refer to two national or administrative units, the one being Denmark and the other Sweden. In the period here considered, largely the century from 1690 to 1790, ‘Denmark’ means really Denmark-Norway, for until 1814 Norway was part of the double monarchy ruled by the king and his government in Copenhagen. It should also be kept in mind that parts of what is today Germany, namely Schleswig-Holstein, belonged to the kingdom. However, as far as language and culture were concerned, these parts of southern Denmark were more German than Danish, and they played no important role in the scientific life of the kingdom. Sweden covered a much larger geographical area than it does today. The country had expanded greatly during the seventeenth century, when not only Finland but also parts of the Baltic area and northern Germany came under Swedish rule. About 1720, after the Great Northern War, Sweden lost most of its possessions, but the major part of Finland remained as part of the country until Centre for Science Studies, Department of Physics and Astronomy, Aarhus University, Denmark.
    [Show full text]
  • Newtonianism and the Physics of Du Châtelet's Institutions De Physique
    To appear in: Collected Wisdom of the Early Modern Scholar: Essays in Honor of Mordechai Feingold, eds. Anna Marie Roos and Gideon Manning. Newtonianism and the physics of Du Châtelet’s Institutions de physique Marius Stan This paper is about two things that cross paths. One is the many senses of the category ‘Newtonian,’ and their uses for exegesis. The other is the phys- ics that Emilie du Châtelet grounded philosophically around 1740 in her book, Institutions de physique. I offer it as a tribute to Moti Feingold’s mag- isterial work on how the century after Newton responded to his science. I begin with some context. Many have described Institutions as a work of Leibnizian foundations for Newtonian science. An inspiring image, no doubt, but is it accurate? I argue here that it is not: little physics in her book is really Newtonian. Most of her physics is from figures before Newton; and even when she includes his results, du Châtelet filters them through demonstrably un-Newtonian ideas. So, we must abandon the conventional wisdom about her science.1 1 In the 20th century, the dominant view became that Institutions is concerned with “merg- ing Leibnizianism and Newtonianism”; is a “marriage between Leibnizian metaphysics and Newtonian science”; is an “introduction to Newtonian physics” attesting du Châtelet’s conversion to “Leibnizian metaphysics”; mediates “between Leibniz and Newton”; is a landmark document in the “history of French Newtonianism” and yet “framed according to Leibnizian principles.” Allegedly it is a “fusion of Newton, Descartes, and Leibniz,” and it synthesizes “Newtonian physics” and “Leibnizian metaphysics.” So pervasive is it that it has seeped into the broader consciousness of Anglophone academia.
    [Show full text]
  • Science and Belief from the Copernicans to the Creationists and the Way Ahead
    Science and belief from the Copernicans to the Creationists and the way ahead Course Number: HIST/INDS 550 Institution: Regent College Instructors: Dr. David Livingstone and Dr. Mark Noll Course Description This course examines critical historical episodes in the interaction between Christianity and science from the sixteenth century to the present. A major goal is to show how deeply embedded in specific cultural situations are all “encounters” between Christianity and science. A second goal is to subvert the notion that talking about “creation” and “evolution” was or ever can be a simple matter. A third goal is to suggest Christian strategies for a more fruitful interchange between science and faith. From this course, students should take away both enriched historical understanding and better theological balance for approaching critical questions relating science and Christianity. Class Outline Mon, July 17: I. Introduction II. Telling the Story of Science and Christianity Tues, July 18: III. The Copernican "Revolution" IV. The Reformation and Science Wed, July 19: V. The Puritans and Science VI. Newton and the Mechanistic World Picture Thurs, July 20: VII. Enlightenment and the Human Sciences VIII. Enlightenment, Science, and Christianity in North America Fri, July 21: IX. Pre-Darwinian, Early-Victorian Science X. The 1830s as a crucial decade for science, theology, and society Mon, July 24: XI. Darwin the man XII. Evolutionary Theories in the Late 19th Century Tues, July 25: XIII. Christian Scientists Encounter Evolution XIV. Theological Evaluations of Darwin and Darwinism Wed, July 26: XV. Creationism in the Context of American Religious History XVI. Interpreting the New Creationism Thurs, July 27: XVII.
    [Show full text]
  • Of Gods and Kings: Natural Philosophy and Politics in the Leibniz-Clarke Disputes Steven Shapin Isis, Vol. 72, No. 2. (Jun., 1981), Pp
    Of Gods and Kings: Natural Philosophy and Politics in the Leibniz-Clarke Disputes Steven Shapin Isis, Vol. 72, No. 2. (Jun., 1981), pp. 187-215. Stable URL: http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0021-1753%28198106%2972%3A2%3C187%3AOGAKNP%3E2.0.CO%3B2-C Isis is currently published by The University of Chicago Press. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/about/terms.html. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/journals/ucpress.html. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. The JSTOR Archive is a trusted digital repository providing for long-term preservation and access to leading academic journals and scholarly literature from around the world. The Archive is supported by libraries, scholarly societies, publishers, and foundations. It is an initiative of JSTOR, a not-for-profit organization with a mission to help the scholarly community take advantage of advances in technology. For more information regarding JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. http://www.jstor.org Mon Aug 20 10:29:37 2007 Of Gods and Kings: Natural Philosophy and Politics in the Leibniz-Clarke Disputes By Steven Shapin* FTER TWO AND A HALF CENTURIES the Newton-Leibniz disputes A continue to inflame the passions.
    [Show full text]
  • The Self-Fashioning of French Newtonianism J
    Metascience DOI 10.1007/s11016-010-9511-3 BOOK REVIEW The self-fashioning of French Newtonianism J. B. Shank: The Newton Wars and the beginning of the French Enlightenment. Chicago and London: The University of Chicago Press, 2008, xv+571pp, $55.00 HB Charles T. Wolfe • David Gilad Ó Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2010 J. B. Shank has written a major cultural history of Newtonianism in the French Enlightenment—or rather a study of how Newtonianism was constructed to serve the purposes of the ‘‘self-fashioning’’ of various key figures in the French Enlightenment. As straight history of ideas, it can be read as providing a French counterpart to works such as John Gascoigne’s masterful (1989) study of science and religion at Cambridge, or as a more detailed, more culturally and rhetorically sophisticated book-length extension of analyses such as Robert Schofield’s ‘‘taxonomy of eighteenth-century Newtonianisms’’ (Schofield 1978). But Shank is also interested in a different approach, a different form of analysis, which in fact challenges ‘‘the classic narrative produced by the Enlightenment philosophes’’ (21). He uses lots of language that harks back to the heyday of theory in the humanities— the book is ‘‘a critical genealogy of beginnings,’’ a ‘‘postmodern,’’ ‘‘post- Enlightenment’’ history of an event—but in fact very little of this really has an impact on the detailed analyses produced over the next four hundred and fifty pages. Brunet’s (1931) book on the introduction of Newton’s theories into France in the early eighteenth century,
    [Show full text]
  • The Newtonian Epoch in the American Colonies (1680-1783) by Fkedeeick E
    314 American Antiquarian Society [Oct., THE NEWTONIAN EPOCH IN THE AMERICAN COLONIES (1680-1783) BY FKEDEEICK E. BRASCH ISTORY in its constant recording of events of H human experience moves on steadily and per- sistently. However certain is the course of history, it is nevertheless a varied series of epochs, events, or com- bination of experiences. It is therefore of vital concern from an intellectual point of view that a retrospective and introspective attitude be maintained in order to see how life as it is today has been achieved. From our present position in the course of events, we are con- cerned today with one of the great periods of the past movement. It is a small section to be sure, but a most interesting and timely one. Between the years of 1680 and 1720 in English history, under the rule of William III and Queen Anne, a most brilliant and illuminating intellectual life is reported. England virtually assumed undisputed leadership only to share it later, first with France and then with Germany. In this period England gave to history her best, both in science and philosophy. The accumulated wisdom of the ages seems to have been concentrated in the lives and works of two undis- putedly brilliant minds, Isaac Newton and John Locke. Theirs are beyond question the outstanding names in that epoch, which followed the discoveries and the liberations of the Renaissance and the Reform- ation, and preceded the great mathematical, physical and philosophical discoveries of today. In one sense Newton and Locke were systematizers of ideas which were prevalent.
    [Show full text]
  • Newtonianism
    Newtonianism Rob Iliffe Isaac Newton (1642/3-1727) • Born in Woolsthorpe, Lincolnshire, England; attended Grantham Grammar School, 1655-61, and then Trinity College Cambridge. • In the mid-1660s ( the ‘marvelous’ – or plague – years) he discovered the integral and differential calculus, the Binomial Theorem, • and the heterogeneity of white light – white light is composed of a mixture of more basic primary rays. • Shortly afterwards he showed that laws of force on Earth and in the heavens were governed by the same inverse-square (1/r2) law. • But – (a) his demonstration did not satisfy him and • (b) this was very far away from the later theory of universal gravitation. • He built first working reflecting telescope (1668), which gave rise to his research into alchemy and chemistry. Newton’s Theory of Light and Colour • In 1664-5 Newton read Robert Boyle’s book on colours and Robert Hooke’s Micrographia, and started his own research program on light, colour and vision. • Discovered in c. 1666 (during plague) that different coloured rays emerging from a prism had specific, unchanging refractive indexes. • He then spent years producing many experiments proving that white light was composed of a mixture of such (primary) rays. • This was his theory of the heterogeneity of white light. • Visible objects seemed to be one or other colour depending on their propensity to reflect rather than absorb specific colours. The Crucial Experiment • Newton sent off a version of his private writings to Henry Oldenburg in February 1672 for publication in the Philosophical transactions, • he described how he had passed white light through a prism and was amazed to find that the image produced as a result was elongated, • and not round, as one would have expected given other theories.
    [Show full text]
  • Newton for Ladies: Gentility, Gender and Radical Culture
    ORE Open Research Exeter TITLE Newton for ladies: gentility, gender and radical culture AUTHORS Mazzotti, Massimo JOURNAL British Journal for the History of Science DEPOSITED IN ORE 27 May 2008 This version available at http://hdl.handle.net/10036/28295 COPYRIGHT AND REUSE Open Research Exeter makes this work available in accordance with publisher policies. A NOTE ON VERSIONS The version presented here may differ from the published version. If citing, you are advised to consult the published version for pagination, volume/issue and date of publication BJHS 37(2): 119–146, June 2004. f British Society for the History of Science DOI: 10.1017/S0007087404005400 Newton for ladies: gentility, gender and radical culture MASSIMO MAZZOTTI* Abstract. Francesco Algarotti’s Newtonianism for Ladies (1737), a series of lively dialogues on optics, was a landmark in the popularization of Newtonian philosophy. In this essay I shall explore Algarotti’s sociocultural world, his aims and ambitions, and the meaning he attached to his own work. In particular I shall focus on Algarotti’s self-promotional strategies, his deployment of gendered images and his use of popular philosophy within the broader cultural and experimental campaign for the success of Newtonianism. Finally, I shall suggest a radical reading of the dialogues, reconstructing the process that brought them to their religious con- demnation. What did Newtonianism mean to Algarotti? In opposition to mainstream apolo- getic interpretations, he seems to have framed the new experimental methodology in a sensationalistic epistemology derived mainly from Locke, pointing at a series of subversive religious and political implications. Due to the intervention of religious authorities Algarotti’s radical Newtonianism became gradually less visible in subsequent editions and translations.
    [Show full text]
  • The Birth of Calculus: Towards a More Leibnizian View
    The Birth of Calculus: Towards a More Leibnizian View Nicholas Kollerstrom [email protected] We re-evaluate the great Leibniz-Newton calculus debate, exactly three hundred years after it culminated, in 1712. We reflect upon the concept of invention, and to what extent there were indeed two independent inventors of this new mathematical method. We are to a considerable extent agreeing with the mathematics historians Tom Whiteside in the 20th century and Augustus de Morgan in the 19th. By way of introduction we recall two apposite quotations: “After two and a half centuries the Newton-Leibniz disputes continue to inflame the passions. Only the very learned (or the very foolish) dare to enter this great killing- ground of the history of ideas” from Stephen Shapin1 and “When de l’Hôpital, in 1696, published at Paris a treatise so systematic, and so much resembling one of modern times, that it might be used even now, he could find nothing English to quote, except a slight treatise of Craig on quadratures, published in 1693” from Augustus de Morgan 2. Introduction The birth of calculus was experienced as a gradual transition from geometrical to algebraic modes of reasoning, sealing the victory of algebra over geometry around the dawn of the 18 th century. ‘Quadrature’ or the integral calculus had developed first: Kepler had computed how much wine was laid down in his wine-cellar by determining the volume of a wine-barrel, in 1615, 1 which marks a kind of beginning for that calculus. The newly-developing realm of infinitesimal problems was pursued simultaneously in France, Italy and England.
    [Show full text]
  • Interpreting Newton
    INTERPRETING NEWTON This collection of specially commissioned essays by leading scholars presents new research on Isaac Newton and his main philosophical inter- locutors and critics. The essays analyze Newton’s relation to his contem- poraries, especially Barrow, Descartes, Leibniz, and Locke, and discuss the ways in which a broad range of figures, including Hume, MacLaurin, Maupertuis, and Kant, reacted to his thought. The wide range of topics discussed includes the laws of nature, the notion of force, the relation of mathematics to nature, Newton’s argument for universal gravitation, his attitude toward philosophical empiricism, his use of “fluxions,” his approach toward measurement problems, and his concept of absolute motion, together with new interpretations of Newton’s matter theory. The volume concludes with an extended essay that analyzes the changes in physics wrought by Newton’s Principia. A substantial introduction and bibliography provide essential reference guides. andrew janiak is Creed C. Black Associate Professor of Philosophy at Duke University. He is the editor of Newton: Philosophical Writings (Cambridge, 2004) and author of Newton as Philosopher (Cambridge, 2008). eric schliesser is BOF Research Professor, Philosophy and Moral Sciences at Ghent University. He has published widely on Newton, Huygens, and their eighteenth-century reception (especially by Hume and Adam Smith) as well as in philosophy of economics. Downloaded from Cambridge Books Online by IP 130.194.20.173 on Fri Nov 02 04:45:13 GMT 2012. http://ebooks.cambridge.org/ebook.jsf?bid=CBO9780511994845 Cambridge Books Online © Cambridge University Press, 2012 INTERPRETING NEWTON Critical Essays Edited by ANDREW JANIAK AND ERIC SCHLIESSER Downloaded from Cambridge Books Online by IP 130.194.20.173 on Fri Nov 02 04:45:13 GMT 2012.
    [Show full text]