Newtonianism

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Newtonianism Newtonianism Rob Iliffe Isaac Newton (1642/3-1727) • Born in Woolsthorpe, Lincolnshire, England; attended Grantham Grammar School, 1655-61, and then Trinity College Cambridge. • In the mid-1660s ( the ‘marvelous’ – or plague – years) he discovered the integral and differential calculus, the Binomial Theorem, • and the heterogeneity of white light – white light is composed of a mixture of more basic primary rays. • Shortly afterwards he showed that laws of force on Earth and in the heavens were governed by the same inverse-square (1/r2) law. • But – (a) his demonstration did not satisfy him and • (b) this was very far away from the later theory of universal gravitation. • He built first working reflecting telescope (1668), which gave rise to his research into alchemy and chemistry. Newton’s Theory of Light and Colour • In 1664-5 Newton read Robert Boyle’s book on colours and Robert Hooke’s Micrographia, and started his own research program on light, colour and vision. • Discovered in c. 1666 (during plague) that different coloured rays emerging from a prism had specific, unchanging refractive indexes. • He then spent years producing many experiments proving that white light was composed of a mixture of such (primary) rays. • This was his theory of the heterogeneity of white light. • Visible objects seemed to be one or other colour depending on their propensity to reflect rather than absorb specific colours. The Crucial Experiment • Newton sent off a version of his private writings to Henry Oldenburg in February 1672 for publication in the Philosophical transactions, • he described how he had passed white light through a prism and was amazed to find that the image produced as a result was elongated, • and not round, as one would have expected given other theories. • To test whether light was produced/modified as a result of white light passing through a prism, or constitutive of the light before it reached the prism, • Newton described a ‘crucial experiment’ with two prisms, which was supposed to provide a demonstration of the truth of his theory. • However, to his frustration, it turned out to be hard to reproduce. Newton’s only drawing of the crucial experiment: 1. Light enters through a slit in a covered window on the right, and passes through a lens before encountering the first prism in the middle of the drawing. 2. After refraction it makes an elongated image on a board with 5 small circles; a hole that allows a primary ray to encounter a second prism to the left. 3. On passing through the second prism, the colour and the angle of refraction ‘nec variat lux fracta colorem’: ‘light does not change remain the same. [i.e. is not modified] when broken into colour’ Newton’s mathematical science - June 1672 • Made novel methodological and disciplinary claims, arguing that his theory of colours was a mathematically certain ‘science’. • Significantly, he defined a ray of light phenomenologically or ‘abstractedly’ (i.e. without reference to the physical structure of light) and in terms of its measured index of refraction • The heterogeneity of white light was a theory but it was established by the crucial experiment and was not an ‘hypothesis’. • Hypotheses and unwarranted references to the internal physical structure of bodies were imaginary and inevitably caused disputes, • while mathematically certain statements were part of a well ordered scientific community. The comet of 1680-1 • The so-called ‘Great Comet’ appeared at end of 1680 and another appeared at start of 1681. • many theories, generally magnetical, were offered about their history, nature, and orbit. • And there were discussions about where they were the same comet. • In 1682, the English Astronomer Royal John Flamsteed argued that they had to be the same comet, which had turned in front of the Sun due to magnetic repulsion, • but Newton disagreed, adhering to older notion that comets generally travelled in straight(ish) lines. • Newton’s model of the path of the comet, entering picture from lower right. • Comet travels BKC at which point some unknown force pulls it to D and then F. • The force cannot be magnetic, according to Newton. • It was therefore driven by an unknown species of force Newton and the Great Comet • Newton argued that: • (a) according to the observations, a single comet would have had to slow down if it changed direction in front of the Sun; • (b) Hot magnets did not work, so the Sun could not be a magnet; • (c) There was no known mechanism, magnetic, vortical or otherwise, that explained how it could turn in its observed path either in front of, or behind the Sun; • A path behind the Sun was the best fit for the data, but there was no known mechanism to account for it, and so it made no sense. The route to Universal Gravitation • Discussions about inverse-square force law, the elliptical orbits of planets and the physical cause of their motion had taken place in London in early 1680s. • Edmond Halley visited Newton summer 1684 and asked him whether he could prove that the inverse-square law of motion gave rise to an elliptical orbit. • Over next 2 years Newton wrestled with problem and gradually developed 3 laws of motion and concepts of ‘force’, ‘mass’, and Universal Gravitation (‘attraction’). Naturalis Philosophiae Principia Mathematica (1687) • Newton showed that measurable motions of the terrestrial and celestial spheres were subject to the same fundamental and mathematical general law. • He articulated the Law of Universal Gravitation in the equation F = G.mm’/r2 • The attractive force linking any two bodies in the world can be measured in terms of a constant (G) multiplied by the product of their masses divided by the distance between them. • Newton’s revolutionary book linked numerous types of measurable celestial and terrestrial phenomena, • and key data in favour of Universal Gravitation came from astronomers and others from around the globe. The success of the Principia • Newton used the theory of universal gravitation to account for tides, cometary motion and the oblate spheroidal shape of the earth, • Making predictions about future, minute motions in the solar system • Crucial elements of Principia are quantification and measurement; • Like his earlier work on light and colours, the Principia was an example of a mathematically-based science, and a demonstration that natural philosophy (as Galileo had said) was fundamentally mathematical. • Newton understood this in theological terms; God was a consummate geometer, who had embedded mathematical order into the structure of the infinite universe. • It required a mathematician like Newton to read the Book of Nature. The Methodology of the Principia • Newton’s methodology (i.e. the way in which he set out his demonstrative argument) was very sophisticated: • 1. Due to an infinite number of Newtonian forces always in operation, less general laws (Galilean/ Keplerian) could never be exact. • 2. Discrepancy between theory (e.g. idealized, perfect Keplerian orbits) and robust data would always point to potential causal factors – it was evidence of the operation of such forces and thus a prompt for further research. • 3. It could make detailed predictions (e.g. return of Halley’s Comet in 1758) • 4. was Universal Gravitation falsifiable? • 5. or comprehensible? Privately Newton thought the direct cause was God. Criticism of Principia • Critics such as Christiaan Huygens and Gottfried Leibniz were committed to physical/ mechanical explanations of natural phenomena as a key part of what natural philosophy was; • and Leibniz in particular argued that the notion of ‘attraction’ was an incomprehensible ‘occult quality’ (and thus a medieval voodoo force). • Others saw Principia as merely an exquisite piece of geometry, a position that was complicated by Newton’s explicitly mathematicist approach in the first two Books of the Principia. • Or, like Louis-Bertrand Castel, they saw Principia as a monster that was neither mathematics nor physics. Newtonianism: The Divided Legacy • Tin the Principia, the 3 laws of Motion and the definitions of ‘force’ and ‘mass’, implied homogeneity of all matter. • Newton was an atomist and a vacuist; evidence from both celestial and terrestrial phenomena suggested that there was no matter in empty space that retarded planetary or cometary motions; • He attacked various physical explanations and their related systems as mere ‘hypotheses’ (especially the Cartesian system) • And his brief claim ‘Hypotheses non Fingo’ in his attack on vortices and hypotheses in the ‘General Scholium’ of 1713 became the great anti-fictivist credo of Enlightenment. Newton’s Opticks (1704, 1706, 1717/18) • First major publication of Newton’s theories of reflection, refraction – originally in English, with Latin edition in 1706 and second English edition in 1717. • ‘Queries’ added to successive editions were extensions of questions and concepts from earlier alchemical and scientific programmes. • became most influential statements in Eighteenth century about existence of an aether, or two aethers, to explain light, heat, electricity and even gravity. Physics at the Royal Society under Newton’s presidency (1703-27); Hauksbee’s electric machine French Newtonians everywhere • French philosophers were generally supportive of the Cartesian- Leibnizian view, and hostile to Newton’s doctrines. • This especially true of shape of the Earth – so 2 scientific expeditions were devised to test the issue: • In Peru (Ecuador) (1735-44): • Charles Marie de La Condamine, Pierre Bouguer, Louis Godin • In Lapland (1736-7): • Pierre Maupertuis, Aléxis-Claude Clairaut, Pierre Le Monnier (and Anders Celsius) Pierre Louis Moreau de Maupertuis (1698-1759) first Head of Prussian Academy of Sciences under Frederick the Great: Inventor of Principle of Least Action Francesco Algarotti, Newtonianism Per le Dame (1737, 1739) Voltaire (with help of Madame du Châtelet), Eléments de la Philosophie de Neuton, (1738) Newton and Enlightenment Sense Experience and the Real world • Like many of his predecessors, Newton denied in the Principia that ordinary sense experience gave a true account of the real world.
Recommended publications
  • Newton.Indd | Sander Pinkse Boekproductie | 16-11-12 / 14:45 | Pag
    omslag Newton.indd | Sander Pinkse Boekproductie | 16-11-12 / 14:45 | Pag. 1 e Dutch Republic proved ‘A new light on several to be extremely receptive to major gures involved in the groundbreaking ideas of Newton Isaac Newton (–). the reception of Newton’s Dutch scholars such as Willem work.’ and the Netherlands Jacob ’s Gravesande and Petrus Prof. Bert Theunissen, Newton the Netherlands and van Musschenbroek played a Utrecht University crucial role in the adaption and How Isaac Newton was Fashioned dissemination of Newton’s work, ‘is book provides an in the Dutch Republic not only in the Netherlands important contribution to but also in the rest of Europe. EDITED BY ERIC JORINK In the course of the eighteenth the study of the European AND AD MAAS century, Newton’s ideas (in Enlightenment with new dierent guises and interpre- insights in the circulation tations) became a veritable hype in Dutch society. In Newton of knowledge.’ and the Netherlands Newton’s Prof. Frans van Lunteren, sudden success is analyzed in Leiden University great depth and put into a new perspective. Ad Maas is curator at the Museum Boerhaave, Leiden, the Netherlands. Eric Jorink is researcher at the Huygens Institute for Netherlands History (Royal Dutch Academy of Arts and Sciences). / www.lup.nl LUP Newton and the Netherlands.indd | Sander Pinkse Boekproductie | 16-11-12 / 16:47 | Pag. 1 Newton and the Netherlands Newton and the Netherlands.indd | Sander Pinkse Boekproductie | 16-11-12 / 16:47 | Pag. 2 Newton and the Netherlands.indd | Sander Pinkse Boekproductie | 16-11-12 / 16:47 | Pag.
    [Show full text]
  • Newton's Mathematical Physics
    Isaac Newton A new era in science Waseda University, SILS, Introduction to History and Philosophy of Science LE201, History and Philosophy of Science Newton . Newton’s Legacy Newton brought to a close the astronomical revolution begun by Copernicus. He combined the dynamic research of Galileo with the astronomical work of Kepler. He produced an entirely new cosmology and a new way of thinking about the world, based on the interaction between matter and mathematically determinate forces. He joined the mathematical and experimental methods: the hypothetico-deductive method. His work became the model for rational mechanics as it was later practiced by mathematicians, particularly during the Enlightenment. LE201, History and Philosophy of Science Newton . William Blake’s Newton (1795) LE201, History and Philosophy of Science Newton LE201, History and Philosophy of Science Newton . Newton’s De Motu coporum in gyrum Edmond Halley (of the comet) visited Cambridge in 1684 and 1 talked with Newton about inverse-square forces (F 9 d2 ). Newton stated that he has already shown that inverse-square force implied an ellipse, but could not find the documents. Later he rewrote this into a short document called De Motu coporum in gyrum, and sent it to Halley. Halley was excited and asked for a full treatment of the subject. Two years later Newton sent Book I of The Mathematical Principals of Natural Philosophy (Principia). Key Point The goal of this project was to derive the orbits of bodies from a simpler set of assumptions about motion. That is, it sought to explain Kepler’s Laws with a simpler set of laws.
    [Show full text]
  • Reposs #19: Newtonianism in the Scandinavian Countries, 1690–1790
    RePoSS: Research Publications on Science Studies RePoSS #19: Newtonianism in the Scandinavian Countries, 1690–1790 Helge Kragh August 2012 Centre for Science Studies, University of Aarhus, Denmark Research group: History and philosophy of science Please cite this work as: Helge Kragh (Aug. 2012). Newtonianism in the Scandinavian Countries, 1690–1790. RePoSS: Research Publications on Sci- ence Studies 19. Aarhus: Centre for Science Studies, University of Aarhus. url: http://www.css.au.dk/reposs. Copyright c Helge Kragh, 2012 1 Newtonianism in the Scandinavian Countries, 1690-1790 HELGE KRAGH 1 Introduction In the present context, the Scandinavian countries refer to two national or administrative units, the one being Denmark and the other Sweden. In the period here considered, largely the century from 1690 to 1790, ‘Denmark’ means really Denmark-Norway, for until 1814 Norway was part of the double monarchy ruled by the king and his government in Copenhagen. It should also be kept in mind that parts of what is today Germany, namely Schleswig-Holstein, belonged to the kingdom. However, as far as language and culture were concerned, these parts of southern Denmark were more German than Danish, and they played no important role in the scientific life of the kingdom. Sweden covered a much larger geographical area than it does today. The country had expanded greatly during the seventeenth century, when not only Finland but also parts of the Baltic area and northern Germany came under Swedish rule. About 1720, after the Great Northern War, Sweden lost most of its possessions, but the major part of Finland remained as part of the country until Centre for Science Studies, Department of Physics and Astronomy, Aarhus University, Denmark.
    [Show full text]
  • Newtonianism and the Physics of Du Châtelet's Institutions De Physique
    To appear in: Collected Wisdom of the Early Modern Scholar: Essays in Honor of Mordechai Feingold, eds. Anna Marie Roos and Gideon Manning. Newtonianism and the physics of Du Châtelet’s Institutions de physique Marius Stan This paper is about two things that cross paths. One is the many senses of the category ‘Newtonian,’ and their uses for exegesis. The other is the phys- ics that Emilie du Châtelet grounded philosophically around 1740 in her book, Institutions de physique. I offer it as a tribute to Moti Feingold’s mag- isterial work on how the century after Newton responded to his science. I begin with some context. Many have described Institutions as a work of Leibnizian foundations for Newtonian science. An inspiring image, no doubt, but is it accurate? I argue here that it is not: little physics in her book is really Newtonian. Most of her physics is from figures before Newton; and even when she includes his results, du Châtelet filters them through demonstrably un-Newtonian ideas. So, we must abandon the conventional wisdom about her science.1 1 In the 20th century, the dominant view became that Institutions is concerned with “merg- ing Leibnizianism and Newtonianism”; is a “marriage between Leibnizian metaphysics and Newtonian science”; is an “introduction to Newtonian physics” attesting du Châtelet’s conversion to “Leibnizian metaphysics”; mediates “between Leibniz and Newton”; is a landmark document in the “history of French Newtonianism” and yet “framed according to Leibnizian principles.” Allegedly it is a “fusion of Newton, Descartes, and Leibniz,” and it synthesizes “Newtonian physics” and “Leibnizian metaphysics.” So pervasive is it that it has seeped into the broader consciousness of Anglophone academia.
    [Show full text]
  • Science and Belief from the Copernicans to the Creationists and the Way Ahead
    Science and belief from the Copernicans to the Creationists and the way ahead Course Number: HIST/INDS 550 Institution: Regent College Instructors: Dr. David Livingstone and Dr. Mark Noll Course Description This course examines critical historical episodes in the interaction between Christianity and science from the sixteenth century to the present. A major goal is to show how deeply embedded in specific cultural situations are all “encounters” between Christianity and science. A second goal is to subvert the notion that talking about “creation” and “evolution” was or ever can be a simple matter. A third goal is to suggest Christian strategies for a more fruitful interchange between science and faith. From this course, students should take away both enriched historical understanding and better theological balance for approaching critical questions relating science and Christianity. Class Outline Mon, July 17: I. Introduction II. Telling the Story of Science and Christianity Tues, July 18: III. The Copernican "Revolution" IV. The Reformation and Science Wed, July 19: V. The Puritans and Science VI. Newton and the Mechanistic World Picture Thurs, July 20: VII. Enlightenment and the Human Sciences VIII. Enlightenment, Science, and Christianity in North America Fri, July 21: IX. Pre-Darwinian, Early-Victorian Science X. The 1830s as a crucial decade for science, theology, and society Mon, July 24: XI. Darwin the man XII. Evolutionary Theories in the Late 19th Century Tues, July 25: XIII. Christian Scientists Encounter Evolution XIV. Theological Evaluations of Darwin and Darwinism Wed, July 26: XV. Creationism in the Context of American Religious History XVI. Interpreting the New Creationism Thurs, July 27: XVII.
    [Show full text]
  • Of Gods and Kings: Natural Philosophy and Politics in the Leibniz-Clarke Disputes Steven Shapin Isis, Vol. 72, No. 2. (Jun., 1981), Pp
    Of Gods and Kings: Natural Philosophy and Politics in the Leibniz-Clarke Disputes Steven Shapin Isis, Vol. 72, No. 2. (Jun., 1981), pp. 187-215. Stable URL: http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0021-1753%28198106%2972%3A2%3C187%3AOGAKNP%3E2.0.CO%3B2-C Isis is currently published by The University of Chicago Press. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/about/terms.html. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/journals/ucpress.html. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. The JSTOR Archive is a trusted digital repository providing for long-term preservation and access to leading academic journals and scholarly literature from around the world. The Archive is supported by libraries, scholarly societies, publishers, and foundations. It is an initiative of JSTOR, a not-for-profit organization with a mission to help the scholarly community take advantage of advances in technology. For more information regarding JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. http://www.jstor.org Mon Aug 20 10:29:37 2007 Of Gods and Kings: Natural Philosophy and Politics in the Leibniz-Clarke Disputes By Steven Shapin* FTER TWO AND A HALF CENTURIES the Newton-Leibniz disputes A continue to inflame the passions.
    [Show full text]
  • The Self-Fashioning of French Newtonianism J
    Metascience DOI 10.1007/s11016-010-9511-3 BOOK REVIEW The self-fashioning of French Newtonianism J. B. Shank: The Newton Wars and the beginning of the French Enlightenment. Chicago and London: The University of Chicago Press, 2008, xv+571pp, $55.00 HB Charles T. Wolfe • David Gilad Ó Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2010 J. B. Shank has written a major cultural history of Newtonianism in the French Enlightenment—or rather a study of how Newtonianism was constructed to serve the purposes of the ‘‘self-fashioning’’ of various key figures in the French Enlightenment. As straight history of ideas, it can be read as providing a French counterpart to works such as John Gascoigne’s masterful (1989) study of science and religion at Cambridge, or as a more detailed, more culturally and rhetorically sophisticated book-length extension of analyses such as Robert Schofield’s ‘‘taxonomy of eighteenth-century Newtonianisms’’ (Schofield 1978). But Shank is also interested in a different approach, a different form of analysis, which in fact challenges ‘‘the classic narrative produced by the Enlightenment philosophes’’ (21). He uses lots of language that harks back to the heyday of theory in the humanities— the book is ‘‘a critical genealogy of beginnings,’’ a ‘‘postmodern,’’ ‘‘post- Enlightenment’’ history of an event—but in fact very little of this really has an impact on the detailed analyses produced over the next four hundred and fifty pages. Brunet’s (1931) book on the introduction of Newton’s theories into France in the early eighteenth century,
    [Show full text]
  • The Newtonian Epoch in the American Colonies (1680-1783) by Fkedeeick E
    314 American Antiquarian Society [Oct., THE NEWTONIAN EPOCH IN THE AMERICAN COLONIES (1680-1783) BY FKEDEEICK E. BRASCH ISTORY in its constant recording of events of H human experience moves on steadily and per- sistently. However certain is the course of history, it is nevertheless a varied series of epochs, events, or com- bination of experiences. It is therefore of vital concern from an intellectual point of view that a retrospective and introspective attitude be maintained in order to see how life as it is today has been achieved. From our present position in the course of events, we are con- cerned today with one of the great periods of the past movement. It is a small section to be sure, but a most interesting and timely one. Between the years of 1680 and 1720 in English history, under the rule of William III and Queen Anne, a most brilliant and illuminating intellectual life is reported. England virtually assumed undisputed leadership only to share it later, first with France and then with Germany. In this period England gave to history her best, both in science and philosophy. The accumulated wisdom of the ages seems to have been concentrated in the lives and works of two undis- putedly brilliant minds, Isaac Newton and John Locke. Theirs are beyond question the outstanding names in that epoch, which followed the discoveries and the liberations of the Renaissance and the Reform- ation, and preceded the great mathematical, physical and philosophical discoveries of today. In one sense Newton and Locke were systematizers of ideas which were prevalent.
    [Show full text]
  • Newton for Ladies: Gentility, Gender and Radical Culture
    ORE Open Research Exeter TITLE Newton for ladies: gentility, gender and radical culture AUTHORS Mazzotti, Massimo JOURNAL British Journal for the History of Science DEPOSITED IN ORE 27 May 2008 This version available at http://hdl.handle.net/10036/28295 COPYRIGHT AND REUSE Open Research Exeter makes this work available in accordance with publisher policies. A NOTE ON VERSIONS The version presented here may differ from the published version. If citing, you are advised to consult the published version for pagination, volume/issue and date of publication BJHS 37(2): 119–146, June 2004. f British Society for the History of Science DOI: 10.1017/S0007087404005400 Newton for ladies: gentility, gender and radical culture MASSIMO MAZZOTTI* Abstract. Francesco Algarotti’s Newtonianism for Ladies (1737), a series of lively dialogues on optics, was a landmark in the popularization of Newtonian philosophy. In this essay I shall explore Algarotti’s sociocultural world, his aims and ambitions, and the meaning he attached to his own work. In particular I shall focus on Algarotti’s self-promotional strategies, his deployment of gendered images and his use of popular philosophy within the broader cultural and experimental campaign for the success of Newtonianism. Finally, I shall suggest a radical reading of the dialogues, reconstructing the process that brought them to their religious con- demnation. What did Newtonianism mean to Algarotti? In opposition to mainstream apolo- getic interpretations, he seems to have framed the new experimental methodology in a sensationalistic epistemology derived mainly from Locke, pointing at a series of subversive religious and political implications. Due to the intervention of religious authorities Algarotti’s radical Newtonianism became gradually less visible in subsequent editions and translations.
    [Show full text]
  • The Birth of Calculus: Towards a More Leibnizian View
    The Birth of Calculus: Towards a More Leibnizian View Nicholas Kollerstrom [email protected] We re-evaluate the great Leibniz-Newton calculus debate, exactly three hundred years after it culminated, in 1712. We reflect upon the concept of invention, and to what extent there were indeed two independent inventors of this new mathematical method. We are to a considerable extent agreeing with the mathematics historians Tom Whiteside in the 20th century and Augustus de Morgan in the 19th. By way of introduction we recall two apposite quotations: “After two and a half centuries the Newton-Leibniz disputes continue to inflame the passions. Only the very learned (or the very foolish) dare to enter this great killing- ground of the history of ideas” from Stephen Shapin1 and “When de l’Hôpital, in 1696, published at Paris a treatise so systematic, and so much resembling one of modern times, that it might be used even now, he could find nothing English to quote, except a slight treatise of Craig on quadratures, published in 1693” from Augustus de Morgan 2. Introduction The birth of calculus was experienced as a gradual transition from geometrical to algebraic modes of reasoning, sealing the victory of algebra over geometry around the dawn of the 18 th century. ‘Quadrature’ or the integral calculus had developed first: Kepler had computed how much wine was laid down in his wine-cellar by determining the volume of a wine-barrel, in 1615, 1 which marks a kind of beginning for that calculus. The newly-developing realm of infinitesimal problems was pursued simultaneously in France, Italy and England.
    [Show full text]
  • Interpreting Newton
    INTERPRETING NEWTON This collection of specially commissioned essays by leading scholars presents new research on Isaac Newton and his main philosophical inter- locutors and critics. The essays analyze Newton’s relation to his contem- poraries, especially Barrow, Descartes, Leibniz, and Locke, and discuss the ways in which a broad range of figures, including Hume, MacLaurin, Maupertuis, and Kant, reacted to his thought. The wide range of topics discussed includes the laws of nature, the notion of force, the relation of mathematics to nature, Newton’s argument for universal gravitation, his attitude toward philosophical empiricism, his use of “fluxions,” his approach toward measurement problems, and his concept of absolute motion, together with new interpretations of Newton’s matter theory. The volume concludes with an extended essay that analyzes the changes in physics wrought by Newton’s Principia. A substantial introduction and bibliography provide essential reference guides. andrew janiak is Creed C. Black Associate Professor of Philosophy at Duke University. He is the editor of Newton: Philosophical Writings (Cambridge, 2004) and author of Newton as Philosopher (Cambridge, 2008). eric schliesser is BOF Research Professor, Philosophy and Moral Sciences at Ghent University. He has published widely on Newton, Huygens, and their eighteenth-century reception (especially by Hume and Adam Smith) as well as in philosophy of economics. Downloaded from Cambridge Books Online by IP 130.194.20.173 on Fri Nov 02 04:45:13 GMT 2012. http://ebooks.cambridge.org/ebook.jsf?bid=CBO9780511994845 Cambridge Books Online © Cambridge University Press, 2012 INTERPRETING NEWTON Critical Essays Edited by ANDREW JANIAK AND ERIC SCHLIESSER Downloaded from Cambridge Books Online by IP 130.194.20.173 on Fri Nov 02 04:45:13 GMT 2012.
    [Show full text]
  • Projects 321
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Elsevier - Publisher Connector HM2 Projects 321 PROJECTS This department welcomes brief notes and article-length manu- scripts. The former may include announcements of contemplated or ongoing projects, information on doctoral theses in progress or completed (writer, title, institution, supervisor, and available information on completion time), proposals and questions, and requests for assistance. Announcements of indi- vidual research projects, including theses, are very important to avoid awkward and wasteful duplication of effort. Articles will ordinarily describe projected, in process, or completed large-scale projects involving one or several scholars and should follow the same standards as other articles. They will be abstracted and indexed like other articles, and authors will be supplied with free reprints. THE BOOK SUBSCRIPTION LISTS PROJECT -- ITS RELEVANCE FOR HISTORIANS OF MATHEMATICS By Peter J. Wallis University of Newcastle upon Tyne As the Project has grown out of the writer's work on his Biobibliography of British Mathematics [Wallis 1974a], it is particularly appropriate to examine the connections between the two fields. Although these connections have been known for a considerable time [Heal 1931; Taylor 1954, 19661, it will be argued that the full use of the wealth of information in book subscription lists will only become possible as their analysis by computers becomes available. Previous references to lists have, as it were, only been scratching the surface. Only when the soil has been carefully tilled will the plants and flowers be able to shoot up and show their full variety.
    [Show full text]