Fighting Nature: an Analysis and Critique of Breed-Specific Flourishing Arguments for Dog Fights
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
society & animals (2015) 1-19 brill.com/soan Fighting Nature: An Analysis and Critique of Breed-Specific Flourishing Arguments for Dog Fights Ian Werkheiser Department of Philosophy, University of Texas, Rio Grande Valley [email protected] Abstract Social science literature on dog fighting illustrates an important element in the dis- course of dog fighters, namely patriarchy. However, it has not addressed another com- mon element, namely flourishing. According to this element of that discourse, some dog breeds are born to fight, and therefore dog fighters are helping them achieve their best lives. This argument is explicitly made by dog fighters, and it is inadvertently supported by those trying to give other dogs breed-specific flourishing, and those who advocate for breed-specific legislation. This poses a problem for advocates of using flourishing to understand animal welfare, particularly if they use kinds (like species and breed) to determine what counts as a flourishing life for a particular nonhuman animal. I argue that we can keep a slightly weakened version of breed-specific flourishing as a start- ing place for understanding individual dogs without endorsing sport fighting or breed- specific legislation for “vicious” breeds of dogs. Keywords dog fighting – flourishing – animal welfare – animal ethics – breed-specific legislation Flourishing, as opposed to a welfarist or more traditional rights-based approach, is a growing part of the discourse on nonhuman animal ethics. This is particularly true as an extension of the capabilities approach, largely begun by Nussbaum (2001, 2004, 2006) and taken up by other authors, both within and outside of the dominant capabilities approach (e.g., Bynum, 2006; Walker, © koninklijke brill nv, leiden, 2�15 | doi 10.1163/15685306-12341375 2 doi 10.1163/15685306-12341375 | Werkheiser 2007; White, 2007; Donaldson & Kymlicka, 2011). At its best, this approach promises a rich framework for understanding rights and justice obligations to nonhuman others, and a more intuitive understanding of what sort of life those others ought to be able to achieve than can be found in the more tradi- tional approaches. It is widely agreed in the literature that all living animals, human and other- wise, share some commonalities in what flourishing looks like for them based on the requirements of sentience and similar shared capacities. It is also widely agreed that some capabilities are shared by particular kinds of animals (such as species), and many versions of this approach acknowledge that individuals have their own particular set of capabilities based on their own capacities and other factors. However, that middle category of using kinds to determine what nonhuman animals need and how we ought to act toward them is more con- troversial than might have originally been supposed. Work in the philosophy and history of science has shown that the con- cept of “species” has changed greatly over time, and it is anything but a fixed delineation of natural kinds (Wilkins, 2011). Given this, some authors in the posthumanist and ecofeminist traditions have questioned the construction of species, with built-in values such as the superiority of those we choose to call humans, in the same critical light as feminists and critical race theorists have questioned those other pillars of our conception of our selves, gender and race (e.g. Wolfe, 2003; Haraway, 2007; Mallory, 2013). If the very concept of “species” is a social construct used to constrain, dominate, and oppress those we deem nonhuman, using it to determine capabilities and lack thereof may be seen as perpetuating this domination in an inevitably damaging way. This paper will not answer the radical version of this posthumanist critique of species in animal ethics directly. Instead, it will use resources from philoso- phy as well as the discourse on dog fighting to look at a more modest version of the issue: whether using the category of “breed” to determine flourishing can be useful, or is irretrievably problematic. This will also contribute to the aca- demic literature on dog fighting, which has underexamined the issues brought up by flourishing. Finally, this paper will provide resources to argue against dog fighting and breed-specific legislation. The paper begins with a brief look at the idea of flourishing in general and flourishing for nonhuman animals in particular. Breed-specific flourishing as it is used by dog fanciers, trainers, advocates of breed-specific legislation, and dog fighters will be discussed. It will then be shown how the use of the con- cept by dog fighters—who argue that some breeds of dogs are born to fight and want to fight, and that therefore people who run these events are helping the animals achieve fully flourishing lives—presents a problem for those who Society & Animals (2015) 1-19 Fighting Nature | doi 10.1163/15685306-12341375 3 would use breed as a way of understanding a flourishing life for that group and/or assessing their capabilities. The possible modifications or responses the problem of dog-fighting-as- flourishing suggests will also be addressed. Though several possible responses have merit, ultimately it will be argued that the mixed nature of the concept of breed as a social construct, with some predictive power, suggests that it should not be treated as a rigid category with particular shared characteristics of all members that can be used to make normative claims. Rather, it is a useful start- ing place for understanding a particular dog in relationship with humans, and not one that justifies using dogs in sport fighting or enacting legislation against particular breeds. Flourishing and Animals Before looking at breed-specific flourishing, it is important to be clear on the basic term and its application. “Flourishing,” as a concept in philosophy, dates back to Aristotle. He argued that there was a “best life” for humans, and that this best life was not a subjective preference, but objectively true. This best life is based on several factors. One of the most important is eudaimonia, which is commonly translated as “flourishing.” Flourishing occurs when a human lives in such a way as to maximally fulfill the capacities that she was born with— for her true nature to flower. Something is virtuous then if it leads to a flour- ishing life (Sheilds, 2008). It is important to point out here that for Aristotle, flourishing is by no means synonymous with mere happiness or absence from suffering. In fact, suffering, pain, and death may all be important parts of a flourishing life. Aristotle himself did not extend flourishing to nonhuman animals, but other philosophers since have done so. Aristotle’s argument was that a cen- tral element of flourishing is reason, and animals do not have this capacity. As he said, “It is not surprising, then, that we regard neither ox nor horse nor any other kind of animal . [as flourishing], since none of them can share in this sort of activity [reason]” (quoted in Walker, 2007, p. 7). While this claim that animals cannot reason is an increasingly contentious one given research into animal cognition (see, e.g., de Waal & Tyack, 2005; Bekoff & Pierce, 2010), directly refuting it is not necessary for expanding the idea of flourishing to animals. Walker (2007) makes just this move in her article “The Good Life for Non-Human Animals: What Virtue Requires for Humans.” She sidesteps the tendentious claim that nonhuman animals can reason, and she instead argues Society & Animals (2015) 1-19 4 doi 10.1163/15685306-12341375 | Werkheiser that it is unnecessary. Human flourishing is multifaceted, and only part of it is constituted by reason. Nonhuman animals at least share all the other con- stituents, including things like “having a safe and comfortable place to sleep, enough to eat, appropriately satisfied sexual urges, sufficient room for exercise, clean water, sunshine (or darkness), appropriate social relations and hierarchy, physical health, [and] positive psychological states” (Walker, 2007, p. 15). There is also an important caveat: flourishing in this broader sense is species- and kind-specific. Humans have some constituents of flourishing (arguably reason) that other animals may not have, and the same is true for all other animals (for example, a salmon may have the return to her home stream to breed as a constitutive element in her flourishing, but this is not something humans are generally thought to have). Nussbaum, perhaps the most prominent advo- cate of flourishing for nonhuman animals with her capabilities approach, also endorses species- and kind-specific flourishing. As she says, “The species norm (duly evaluated) tells us what the appropriate benchmark is for judging whether a given creature has decent opportunities for flourishing. The same thing goes for nonhuman animals: in each case, what is wanted is a species- specific account of central capabilities” (Nussbaum, 2006, p. 365). Walker (2007) also argues that as animals do in fact have the capacity for flourishing, we ought to aid them in that flourishing when we can. This point is broadly endorsed by those thinking about flourishing for nonhuman animals: Nussbaum has also long maintained that frustrating capabilities for flourish- ing is an injustice, and we further have a positive duty to enable capabilities if possible (e.g., Nussbaum, 2006, p. 365). Most authors working in flourishing ethics for nonhuman animals see a special positive duty and responsibility to promote the flourishing of domes- ticated companion species (Nussbaum, 2004, 2006; Walker, 2007; Donaldson & Kymlicka, 2011). This idea is well supported by scientific studies into domes- ticated species, particularly dogs. Studies of dogs have shown that they have adapted their social behaviors to their niche as a companion species, and as a result domesticated animals were “reorganized so that their natural state became one of coexistence with humans” (Anderson, 1997).