Liability Law for Present and Future Robotics Technology Trevor N

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Liability Law for Present and Future Robotics Technology Trevor N Liability Law for Present and Future Robotics Technology Trevor N. White and Seth D. Baum Global Catastrophic Risk Institute http://gcrinstitute.org * http://sethbaum.com Published in Robot Ethics 2.0, edited by Patrick Lin, George Bekey, Keith Abney, and Ryan Jenkins, Oxford University Press, 2017, pages 66-79. This version 10 October 2017 Abstract Advances in robotics technology are causing major changes in manufacturing, transportation, medicine, and a number of other sectors. While many of these changes are beneficial, there will inevitably be some harms. Who or what is liable when a robot causes harm? This paper addresses how liability law can and should account for robots, including robots that exist today and robots that potentially could be built at some point in the near or distant future. Already, robots have been implicated in a variety of harms. However, current and near-future robots pose no significant challenge for liability law: they can be readily handled with existing liability law or minor variations thereof. We show this through examples from medical technology, drones, and consumer robotics. A greater challenge will arise if it becomes possible to build robots that merit legal personhood and thus can be held liable. Liability law for robot persons could draw on certain precedents, such as animal liability. However, legal innovations will be needed, in particular for determining which robots merit legal personhood. Finally, a major challenge comes from the possibility of future robots that could cause major global catastrophe. As with other global catastrophic risks, liability law could not apply, because there would be no post- catastrophe legal system to impose liability. Instead, law must be based on pre-catastrophe precautionary measures. Introduction In June 2005, a surgical robot at a hospital in Philadelphia malfunctioned during a prostate surgery, possibly injuring the patient.1 In June 2015, a worker at a Volkswagen plant in Germany was crushed to death by a robot that was part of the assembly process.2 In November 2015, a self-driving car in California made a complete stop at an intersection and then was hit by a car with a human driver, apparently because the self-driving car followed traffic law but not traffic norms.3 These are just some of the ways that robots are already implicated in harms. As robots become more sophisticated and more widely adopted, the potential for harm will get even larger. Robots even show potential for causing harm at massive catastrophic scales. How should robot harms be governed? In general, liability law governs harms in which someone or something else is responsible. Liability law is used to punish those who have caused harms, particularly those that could have and should have been avoided. The threat of punishment further serves to discourage those who could cause harm. Liability law is thus an important legal tool for serving justice and advancing the general welfare of society and its members. The value of liability law holds for robotics just as it does for any other harm-causing technology. But robots are not just any other technology. Robots are (or at least can be) intelligent, autonomous actors moving about in the physical world. They can cause harms through actions that they choose to make, actions that no human told them to make and, indeed, that may surprise 1 their human creators. Perhaps robots should be liable for their harms. This is a historic moment: humans creating technology that could potentially be liable for its own actions. Furthermore, robots can have the strength of industrial machinery and the intelligence of advanced computer systems. Robots can also be mass produced and connected to each other and to other technological systems. This creates the potential for robots to cause unusually great harm. This paper addresses how liability law can and should account for robots, including robots that exist today and robots that potentially could be built at some point in the near or distant future. Three types of cases are distinguished, each with very different implications. First are cases in which some human party is liable, such as the manufacturer or the human using the robot. These cases pose no novel challenges for liability law: they are handled the same way as with other technologies in comparable circumstances. Second are cases in which the robot itself is liable. These cases require dramatic revision to liability law, including standards to assess when robots can be held liable and principles for dividing liability between the robot and the humans who designed, built, and used it. Third are cases in which the robot poses a major catastrophic risk. These cases merit separate attention because a sufficiently large catastrophe would destroy the legal system and thus the potential to hold anyone or anything liable. The three types of cases differ across two dimensions as shown in Figure 1. One dimension is the robot’s degree of legal personhood, meaning the extent to which a robot shows attributes that qualify it for independent standing in a court of law. As we discuss, a robot can be held liable in the eyes of the law to the extent that it merits legal personhood. The other dimension shows the size of the harm the robot causes. Harms of extreme severity cannot be handled by liability law. However, there is no strict distinction between the three cases. Instead, there is a continuum, as shown by the regions in which a robot can have partial liability or more-than-human liability and in which liability law works to a limited extent. Figure 1. Classification scheme for the applicability of liability law to various sizes of harms caused by various types of robots. I - A Human Party Is Liable In a detailed study of robot law, Weaver (2014, 21–27) identifies four types of parties that could be liable for harm caused by a robot: (1) people who were using the robot or overseeing its use; (2) other people who were not using the robot but otherwise came into contact with it, which can include people harmed by the robot; (3) some party involved in the robot’s production and distribution, such as the company that manufactured the robot; or (4) the robot itself. 2 For the first three types of parties, liability applies the same as for other technologies. A surgical robot, for example, can be misused by the surgeon (type 1), bumped into by a hospital visitor who wandered into a restricted area (type 2), or poorly built by the manufacturer (type 3). The same situations can also arise for other, non-robotic medical technologies. In each case, the application of liability law is straightforward. Or rather, to the extent that the application of liability law is not straightforward, the challenges faced are familiar. The fourth type—when the robot is liable—is the only one that poses novel challenges for liability law. To see this, consider one of the thornier cases of robot liability, that of lethal autonomous weapon systems (LAWSs). These are weapons that decide for themselves whom to kill. Sparrow (2007) argues that there could be no one liable for certain LAWS harms—for example, if a LAWS decides to kill civilians or soldiers who have surrendered. A sufficiently autonomous LAWS could make its own decisions, regardless of how humans designed and deployed it. In this case, Sparrow argues, it would be unfair to hold the designer or deployer liable (or the manufacturer or other human parties). It might further be inappropriate to hold the robot itself liable, if it is not sufficiently advanced in legally relevant ways (more on this in Section II). In this case, who or what to hold liable is ambiguous. This ambiguous liability is indeed a challenge, but it is a familiar one. In the military context, precedents include child soldiers (Sparrow 2007, 73–74) and landmines (Hammond 2015, note 62). Child soldiers can make their own decisions, disobey orders, and cause harm in the process. Landmines can linger long after a conflict, making it difficult or impossible to identify who is responsible for their placement. In both cases, it can be difficult or perhaps impossible to determine who is liable. So too for LAWSs. This ambiguous liability can be a reason to avoid or even ban the use of child soldiers, landmines, and LAWSs in armed conflict. Regardless, even for this relatively thorny case of robot liability, robotics technology raises no new challenges for liability law. In the United States, agencies such as the Department of Defense produce regulations on the use of LAWSs which are not dramatically different than for other weapons. Internationally, bodies like the UN’s International Court of Justice could hold a state liable for authorizing drone strikes that caused excessive civilian casualties. Meanwhile, commercial drones can be regulated as other aircraft are now: by a combination of the FAA and corporate oversight by their creators (McFarland 2015). The handling of such relatively simple robots under liability law will thus be familiar if not straightforward. The above LAWSs examples also resemble how liability law handles non-human animals, which has prompted proposals for robots to be given legal status similar to non-human animals (e.g., Kelley et al. 2010). Suppose someone gets a pet dog and then the dog bites someone, despite the owner trying to stop it. If this person had absolutely no idea the dog would bite someone, then she would not be liable for that bite. However, having seen the dog bite someone, she now knows the dog is a biter, and is now expected to exercise caution with it in the future.
Recommended publications
  • Safety of Artificial Superintelligence
    Environment. Technology. Resources. Rezekne, Latvia Proceedings of the 12th International Scientific and Practical Conference. Volume II, 180-183 Safety of Artificial Superintelligence Aleksejs Zorins Peter Grabusts Faculty of Engineering Faculty of Engineering Rezekne Academy of Technologies Rezekne Academy of Technologies Rezekne, Latvia Rezekne, Latvia [email protected] [email protected] Abstract—The paper analyses an important problem of to make a man happy it will do it with the fastest and cyber security from human safety perspective which is usu- cheapest (in terms of computational resources) without ally described as data and/or computer safety itself with- using a common sense (for example killing of all people out mentioning the human. There are numerous scientific will lead to the situation that no one is unhappy or the predictions of creation of artificial superintelligence, which decision to treat human with drugs will also make him could arise in the near future. That is why the strong neces- sity for protection of such a system from causing any farm happy etc.). Another issue is that we want computer to arises. This paper reviews approaches and methods already that we want, but due to bugs in the code computer will presented for solving this problem in a single article, analy- do what the code says, and in the case of superintelligent ses its results and provides future research directions. system, this may be a disaster. Keywords—Artificial Superintelligence, Cyber Security, The next sections of the paper will show the possible Singularity, Safety of Artificial Intelligence. solutions of making superintelligence safe to humanity.
    [Show full text]
  • Classification Schemas for Artificial Intelligence Failures
    Journal XX (XXXX) XXXXXX https://doi.org/XXXX/XXXX Classification Schemas for Artificial Intelligence Failures Peter J. Scott1 and Roman V. Yampolskiy2 1 Next Wave Institute, USA 2 University of Louisville, Kentucky, USA [email protected], [email protected] Abstract In this paper we examine historical failures of artificial intelligence (AI) and propose a classification scheme for categorizing future failures. By doing so we hope that (a) the responses to future failures can be improved through applying a systematic classification that can be used to simplify the choice of response and (b) future failures can be reduced through augmenting development lifecycles with targeted risk assessments. Keywords: artificial intelligence, failure, AI safety, classification 1. Introduction Artificial intelligence (AI) is estimated to have a $4-6 trillion market value [1] and employ 22,000 PhD researchers [2]. It is estimated to create 133 million new roles by 2022 but to displace 75 million jobs in the same period [6]. Projections for the eventual impact of AI on humanity range from utopia (Kurzweil, 2005) (p.487) to extinction (Bostrom, 2005). In many respects AI development outpaces the efforts of prognosticators to predict its progress and is inherently unpredictable (Yampolskiy, 2019). Yet all AI development is (so far) undertaken by humans, and the field of software development is noteworthy for unreliability of delivering on promises: over two-thirds of companies are more likely than not to fail in their IT projects [4]. As much effort as has been put into the discipline of software safety, it still has far to go. Against this background of rampant failures we must evaluate the future of a technology that could evolve to human-like capabilities, usually known as artificial general intelligence (AGI).
    [Show full text]
  • Leakproofing the Singularity Artificial Intelligence Confinement Problem
    Roman V.Yampolskiy Leakproofing the Singularity Artificial Intelligence Confinement Problem Abstract: This paper attempts to formalize and to address the ‘leakproofing’ of the Singularity problem presented by David Chalmers. The paper begins with the definition of the Artificial Intelli- gence Confinement Problem. After analysis of existing solutions and their shortcomings, a protocol is proposed aimed at making a more secure confinement environment which might delay potential negative effect from the technological singularity while allowing humanity to benefit from the superintelligence. Keywords: AI-Box, AI Confinement Problem, Hazardous Intelligent Software, Leakproof Singularity, Oracle AI. ‘I am the slave of the lamp’ Genie from Aladdin 1. Introduction With the likely development of superintelligent programs in the near future, many scientists have raised the issue of safety as it relates to such technology (Yudkowsky, 2008; Bostrom, 2006; Hibbard, 2005; Chalmers, 2010; Hall, 2000). A common theme in Artificial Intelli- gence (AI)1 safety research is the possibility of keeping a super- intelligent agent in a sealed hardware so as to prevent it from doing any harm to humankind. Such ideas originate with scientific Correspondence: Roman V. Yampolskiy, Department of Computer Engineering and Computer Sci- ence University of Louisville. Email: [email protected] [1] In this paper the term AI is used to represent superintelligence. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 19, No. 1–2, 2012, pp. 194–214 Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2011 For personal use only -- not for reproduction LEAKPROOFING THE SINGULARITY 195 visionaries such as Eric Drexler, who has suggested confining transhuman machines so that their outputs could be studied and used safely (Drexler, 1986).
    [Show full text]
  • Intelligence Explosion FAQ
    MIRI MACHINE INTELLIGENCE RESEARCH INSTITUTE Intelligence Explosion FAQ Luke Muehlhauser Machine Intelligence Research Institute Abstract The Machine Intelligence Research Institute is one of the leading research institutes on intelligence explosion. Below are short answers to common questions we receive. Muehlhauser, Luke. 2013. “Intelligence Explosion FAQ.” First published 2011 as “Singularity FAQ.” Machine Intelligence Research Institute, Berkeley, CA Contents 1 Basics 1 1.1 What is an intelligence explosion? . 1 2 How Likely Is an Intelligence Explosion? 2 2.1 How is “intelligence” defined? . 2 2.2 What is greater-than-human intelligence? . 2 2.3 What is whole-brain emulation? . 3 2.4 What is biological cognitive enhancement? . 3 2.5 What are brain-computer interfaces? . 4 2.6 How could general intelligence be programmed into a machine? . 4 2.7 What is superintelligence? . 4 2.8 When will the intelligence explosion happen? . 5 2.9 Might an intelligence explosion never occur? . 6 3 Consequences of an Intelligence Explosion 7 3.1 Why would great intelligence produce great power? . 7 3.2 How could an intelligence explosion be useful? . 7 3.3 How might an intelligence explosion be dangerous? . 8 4 Friendly AI 9 4.1 What is Friendly AI? . 9 4.2 What can we expect the motivations of a superintelligent machine to be? 10 4.3 Can’t we just keep the superintelligence in a box, with no access to the Internet? . 11 4.4 Can’t we just program the superintelligence not to harm us? . 11 4.5 Can we program the superintelligence to maximize human pleasure or desire satisfaction? .
    [Show full text]
  • Hello, World: Artificial Intelligence and Its Use in the Public Sector
    Hello, World: Artificial intelligence and its use in the public sector Jamie Berryhill Kévin Kok Heang Rob Clogher Keegan McBride November 2019 | http://oe.cd/helloworld OECD Working Papers on Public Governance No. 36 Cover images are the European Parliament and the dome of Germany’s Reichstag building processed through Deep Learning algorithms to match the style of Van Gogh paintings. tw Hello, World: Artificial Intelligence and its Use in the Public Sector Authors: Jamie Berryhill, Kévin Kok Heang, Rob Clogher, Keegan McBride PUBE 2 This document and any map included herein are without prejudice to the status of or sovereignty over any territory, to the delimitation of international frontiers and boundaries and to the name of any territory, city or area. 1. Note by Tukey: The information in this document with reference to ‘Cyprus’ relates to the southern part of the island. There is no single authority representing both Turkish and Greek Cypriot people on the island. Turkey recognises the Turkish Republic of Northern Cyprus (TRNC). Until a lasting and equitable solution is found within the context of the United Nations, Turkey shall preserve its position concerning the ‘Cyprus issue’. 2. Note by all the European Union Member States of the OECD and the European Commission: The Republic of Cyprus is recognised by all members of the United Nations with the exception of Turkey. The information in this document relates to the area under the effective control of the Government of the Republic of Cyprus. HELLO, WORLD: ARTIFICIAL INTELLIGENCE AND ITS USE IN THE PUBLIC SECTOR © OECD 2019 3 Foreword Artificial Intelligence (AI) is an area of research and technology application that can have a significant impact on public policies and services in many ways.
    [Show full text]
  • A Survey of Research Questions for Robust and Beneficial AI
    A survey of research questions for robust and beneficial AI 1 Introduction Artificial intelligence (AI) research has explored a variety of problems and approaches since its inception, but for the last 20 years or so has been focused on the problems surrounding the construction of intelligent agents|systems that perceive and act in some environment. In this context, the criterion for intelligence is related to statistical and economic notions of rationality|colloquially, the ability to make good decisions, plans, or inferences. The adoption of probabilistic representations and statistical learning methods has led to a large degree of integration and cross-fertilization between AI, machine learning, statistics, control theory, neuroscience, and other fields. The establishment of shared theoretical frameworks, combined with the availability of data and processing power, has yielded remarkable successes in various component tasks such as speech recognition, image classification, autonomous vehicles, machine translation, legged locomotion, and question-answering systems. As capabilities in these areas and others cross the threshold from laboratory research to economically valuable technologies, a virtuous cycle takes hold whereby even small improvements in performance are worth large sums of money, prompting greater investments in research. There is now a broad consensus that AI research is progressing steadily, and that its impact on society is likely to increase. The potential benefits are huge, since everything that civilization has to offer is a product of human intelligence; we cannot predict what we might achieve when this intelligence is magnified by the tools AI may provide, but the eradication of disease and poverty are not unfathomable. Because of the great potential of AI, it is valuable to investigate how to reap its benefits while avoiding potential pitfalls.
    [Show full text]
  • Artificial Intelligence Safety and Cybersecurity: a Timeline of AI Failures
    Artificial Intelligence Safety and Cybersecurity: a Timeline of AI Failures Roman V. Yampolskiy M. S. Spellchecker Computer Engineering and Computer Science Microsoft Corporation University of Louisville One Microsoft Way, Redmond, WA [email protected] [email protected] Abstract In this work, we present and analyze reported failures of artificially intelligent systems and extrapolate our analysis to future AIs. We suggest that both the frequency and the seriousness of future AI failures will steadily increase. AI Safety can be improved based on ideas developed by cybersecurity experts. For narrow AIs safety failures are at the same, moderate, level of criticality as in cybersecurity, however for general AI, failures have a fundamentally different impact. A single failure of a superintelligent system may cause a catastrophic event without a chance for recovery. The goal of cybersecurity is to reduce the number of successful attacks on the system; the goal of AI Safety is to make sure zero attacks succeed in bypassing the safety mechanisms. Unfortunately, such a level of performance is unachievable. Every security system will eventually fail; there is no such thing as a 100% secure system. Keywords: AI Safety, Cybersecurity, Failures, Superintelligence. 1. Introduction A day does not go by without a news article reporting some amazing breakthrough in artificial intelligence1. In fact progress in AI has been so steady that some futurologists, such as Ray Kurzweil, project current trends into the future and anticipate what the headlines of tomorrow will bring us. Consider some developments from the world of technology: 2004 DARPA sponsors a driverless car grand challenge. Technology developed by the participants eventually allows Google to develop a driverless automobile and modify existing transportation laws.
    [Show full text]
  • The Ethics of Superintelligent Machines
    Ethical Issues in Advanced Artificial Intelligence Nick Bostrom Oxford University Philosophy Faculty 10 Merton Street Oxford OX1 4JJ United Kingdom Email: [email protected] ABSTRACT The ethical issues related to the possible future creation of machines with general intellectual capabilities far outstripping those of humans are quite distinct from any ethical problems arising in current automation and information systems. Such superintelligence would not be just another technological development; it would be the most important invention ever made, and would lead to explosive progress in all scientific and technological fields, as the superintelligence would conduct research with superhuman efficiency. To the extent that ethics is a cognitive pursuit, a superintelligence could also easily surpass humans in the quality of its moral thinking. However, it would be up to the designers of the superintelligence to specify its original motivations. Since the superintelligence may become unstoppably powerful because of its intellectual superiority and the technologies it could develop, it is crucial that it be provided with human-friendly motivations. This paper surveys some of the unique ethical issues in creating superintelligence, and discusses what motivations we ought to give a superintelligence, and introduces some cost-benefit considerations relating to whether the development of superintelligent machines ought to be accelerated or retarded. KEYWORDS: Artificial intelligence, ethics, uploading, superintelligence, global security, cost-benefit analysis 1. INTRODUCTION A superintelligence is any intellect that is vastly outperforms the best human brains in practically every field, including scientific creativity, general wisdom, and social skills.1 This definition leaves open how the superintelligence is implemented – it could be in a digital computer, an ensemble of networked computers, cultured cortical tissue, or something else.
    [Show full text]
  • Guidelines for Artificial Intelligence Containment
    Guidelines for Artificial Intelligence Containment James Babcock Janos Kramar Roman V. Yampolskiy Cornell University University of Montreal University of Louisville [email protected] [email protected] [email protected] Abstract With almost daily improvements in capabilities of artificial intelligence it is more important than ever to develop safety software for use by the AI research community. Building on our previous work on AI Containment Problem we propose a number of guidelines which should help AI safety researchers to develop reliable sandboxing software for intelligent programs of all levels. Such safety container software will make it possible to study and analyze intelligent artificial agent while maintaining certain level of safety against information leakage, social engineering attacks and cyberattacks from within the container. Keywords: AI Boxing, AI Containment, AI Confinement!, AI Guidelines, AI Safety, Airgapping. 1. Introduction The past few years have seen a remarkable amount of attention on the long-term future of AI. Icons of science and technology such as Stephen Hawking1, Elon Musk2, and Bill Gates3 have expressed concern that superintelligent AI may wipe out humanity in the long run. Stuart Russell, coauthor of the most-cited textbook of AI [35], recently began prolifically advocating4 for the field of AI to take this possibility seriously. AI conferences now frequently have panels and workshops on the topic5,6. There has been an outpouring of support7 from many leading AI researchers for an open letter calling for greatly increased research dedicated to ensuring that increasingly capable AI remains “robust and beneficial”, and gradually a field of “AI safety” is coming into being [64, 33, 55].
    [Show full text]
  • Hybrid Cognitive-Affective Strategies for AI Safety
    Ph.D. Thesis Hybrid Cognitive-Affective Strategies for AI Safety Nadisha-Marie Aliman Print Gallery (Dutch: Prentententoonstelling) by M.C. Escher, 1956. All M.C. Escher works © 2020 The M.C. Escher Company { the Netherlands. All rights reserved. Used by permission. www:mcescher:com Hybrid Cognitive-Affective Strategies for AI Safety Hybride cognitief-affectieve strategie¨envoor AI-veiligheid (met een samenvatting in het Nederlands) PROEFSCHRIFT ter verkrijging van de graad van doctor aan de Universiteit Utrecht op gezag van de rector magnificus, prof. dr. H.R.B.M. Kummeling, ingevolge het besluit van het college voor promoties in het openbaar te verdedigen op 2 december 2020 te 12.45 uur door Nadisha-Marie Aliman geboren op 23 mei 1992 te Bochum, Duitsland Promotoren: Prof. dr. P.J. Werkhoven Prof. dr. ir. J. Masthoff Contents 1 Introduction 1 2 Self-Awareness and Proactive AI Safety Measures 9 2.1 Introduction . .9 2.2 Self-Awareness . 10 2.3 Proactive AI Safety Measures . 13 2.4 Human Enhancement . 15 2.5 Conclusion and Future Prospects . 17 2.6 Contextualization . 18 3 Transformative AI Governance and Preemptive Simulations for Ethical Goal Functions 20 3.1 Introduction . 20 3.2 Utility-Based AI Governance Strategy . 21 3.3 Dynamical Ethical Enhancement . 23 3.4 Implications of Impossibility Theorems for AI Governance and Ethical En- hancement . 24 3.5 Experiencing Future Well-Being in the Present . 27 3.6 Conclusion . 29 3.7 Contextualization . 30 ii 4 Augmented Utilitarianism for AI Safety 31 4.1 Introduction . 31 4.2 Deconstructing Perverse Instantiation . 32 4.3 Augmenting Utilitarianism .
    [Show full text]
  • AGI Safety Literature Review Arxiv:1805.01109V2 [Cs.AI] 21 May 2018
    AGI Safety Literature Review∗y Tom Everitt, Gary Lea, Marcus Hutter ftom.everitt, gary.lea, [email protected] May 22, 2018 Australian National University The development of Artificial General Intelligence (AGI) promises to be a major event. Along with its many potential benefits, it also raises serious safety concerns (Bostrom, 2014). The intention of this paper is to provide an easily accessible and up-to-date collection of references for the emerging field of AGI safety. A significant number of safety problems for AGI have been identified. We list these, and survey recent research on solving them. We also cover works on how best to think of AGI from the limited knowledge we have today, predictions for when AGI will first be created, and what will happen after its creation. Finally, we review the current public policy on AGI. Contents 1 Introduction2 2 Understanding AGI2 3 Predicting AGI Development5 4 Problems with AGI7 5 Design Ideas for Safe AGI 10 arXiv:1805.01109v2 [cs.AI] 21 May 2018 6 Public Policy on AGI 17 7 Conclusions 20 ∗Cite as Tom Everitt, Gary Lea, and Marcus Hutter (2018). \AGI Safety Literature Review". In: Inter- national Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence (IJCAI). arXiv: 1805.01109. yWe thank Matthew Graves, Kaj Sotala, Ramana Kumar and Daniel Eth for comments and suggestions. 1 1 Introduction An Artificial General Intelligence (AGI) is an AI system that equals or exceeds human intelligence in a wide variety of cognitive tasks. This is in contrast to today's AI systems that solve only narrow sets of tasks.
    [Show full text]
  • The Singularity a Philosophical Analysis
    David J. Chalmers The Singularity A Philosophical Analysis 1. Introduction What happens when machines become more intelligent than humans? One view is that this event will be followed by an explosion to ever- greater levels of intelligence, as each generation of machines creates more intelligent machines in turn. This intelligence explosion is now often known as the ‘singularity’.1 The basic argument here was set out by the statistician I.J. Good in his 1965 article ‘Speculations Concerning the First Ultraintelligent Machine’: Let an ultraintelligent machine be defined as a machine that can far sur- pass all the intellectual activities of any man however clever. Since the design of machines is one of these intellectual activities, an ultra- intelligent machine could design even better machines; there would then unquestionably be an ‘intelligence explosion’, and the intelligence of man would be left far behind. Thus the first ultraintelligent machine is the last invention that man need ever make. The key idea is that a machine that is more intelligent than humans will be better than humans at designing machines. So it will be capable of designing a machine more intelligent than the most intelligent machine that humans can design. So if it is itself designed by humans, Correspondence: Email: [email protected] [1] I first became interested in this cluster of ideas as a student, before first hearing explicitly of the ‘singularity’ in 1997. I was spurred to think further about these issues by an invita- tion to speak at the 2009 Singularity Summit in New York City. I thank many people at that event for discussion, as well as many at later talks and discussions at West Point, CUNY, NYU, Delhi, ANU, Tucson, Oxford, and UNSW.
    [Show full text]