Allard Research Commons Motherhood

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Allard Research Commons Motherhood The Peter A. Allard School of Law Allard Research Commons Faculty Publications (Emeriti) Allard Faculty Publications 2013 Motherhood Susan B. Boyd Allard School of Law at the University of British Columbia Follow this and additional works at: https://commons.allard.ubc.ca/emeritus_pubs Part of the Family Law Commons, Law and Gender Commons, and the Sexuality and the Law Commons Citation Details Susan Boyd, "Motherhood" in Margaret Davies & Vanessa Munro, eds, A Research Companion to Feminist Legal Theory [forthcoming in 2013]. This Working Paper is brought to you for free and open access by the Allard Faculty Publications at Allard Research Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Publications (Emeriti) by an authorized administrator of Allard Research Commons. 1 MOTHERHOOD By Susan Boyd [email protected] A Research Companion to Feminist Legal Theory Edited by Margaret Davies & Vanessa Munro Introduction An extensive feminist literature explores how law interacts with the social institution of motherhood and with the ideological frameworks that contribute to women’s oppression in western, liberal states. This chapter’s main concern is with feminist theories about law’s role in relation to motherhood, which reflects both coercive and ideological aspects. That is, women can be coerced into normative ideals of motherhood and penalized for failure to conform, but women can also ‘consent’ or choose to conform to ideological norms, raising far more complex questions for feminists and for feminist legal strategy. The chapter also explores the degree to which law and feminist legal strategies reinforce and/or challenge dominant ideologies of motherhood, which are rooted in the histories of race, class, gender, and sexuality. Another theme of this chapter is the differential impact of legal regulation, depending on whether a mother is working class or middle class, racialized or non-racialized, lesbian or straight, disabled or able-bodied, and so on. All women can be detrimentally affected by dominant legal norms, but women who depart from normative white, middle-class, heterosexual motherhood are likely to be scrutinized more heavily and treated more coercively than those who are able to conform. The question of law’s differential impact on women whose social location differs also poses important questions about feminist legal strategies, including whether they lapse into essentialist or ‘maternalist’ modes of analysis. This chapter proceeds on the premise that motherhood is socially constructed through the interaction of complex structures and ideologies. The first part explains this process and is then followed by two illustrative case studies on criminal law and family law. The risk of essentialism 2 is taken up in the next part on legal strategy. The last part of the chapter uses examples of ‘transgressive motherhood’ to suggest future directions for feminist legal theory and concludes with questions that continue to challenge feminist legal engagement with motherhood. The Social Construction of Motherhood: Law’s Ideological Role Despite women’s biological potential to conceive, gestate, give birth and lactate, ‘[m]otherhood is not a natural condition’ (Smart 1996: 37). Numerous feminist scholars have shown how the institution of motherhood is socially constructed in different historical periods, yet is presented ideologically as a natural consequence of biological differences between women and men. Indeed, in their review of feminist approaches to motherhood, Katherine O’Donovan and Jill Marshall (2006: 107) found that social construction is the most common approach within second wave feminism’s analysis of motherhood. Adrienne Rich (1976) is often credited as the first feminist to have presented a scholarly analysis of motherhood as an institution and to deconstruct the notion of an inherent maternal instinct. Motherhood, mothering, and family structures are all shaped by social, economic and cultural contexts, which in turn are framed by the interlocking structures of gender, race, class, and sexuality. As Martha Fineman puts it, motherhood is a colonized concept, something physically occupied and experienced by women, but defined, controlled, and given legal content by patriarchal ideology (1995: 38). Early feminist treatments of motherhood often drew on materialist feminist approaches to the family within capitalist patriarchy, including the work of sociologists and political economists about the (hetero)sexual division of labour within both public and private spheres that developed within the context of industrial capitalism (Boyd 1997). For instance, Michèle Barrett and Mary McIntosh (1982) showed that the traditional, nuclear, ‘anti-social’ or privatized family plays a particular role within capitalism as a socio-economic institution and an ideology. Among other things, the family provides ‘free’ reproductive labour by women in relation to the care of children and workers which, in turn, allows productive labour to be pursued on the assumption that the ‘private’ sphere of family is handling care work. Feminist historians have shown that as fathers became increasingly linked with the public world of paid work in the 19th and 20th centuries, and children became an economic cost to families, mothers were constructed as the 3 ‘divinely appointed guardians of the family’ (Backhouse 1981: 239). Ironically, this idealized and deeply gendered role for mothers did not necessarily translate into legal rights in relation to children (Boyd 2003). These structural insights about the material basis for motherhood have been adopted by many authors (e.g. Fineman 1995), often combined with attention to the role of ideology. The tool of ideology has been deployed to show how law both constructs and normalizes a set of ideas about motherhood, often distracting attention to its material roots, and facilitated an increasingly complex understanding of law’s roles in the social construction of motherhood. Ideology also assists in understanding the dynamics through which women are regulated by law across and through their differences and, specifically, how mothers are constructed as ‘good’ or ‘bad’, depending on their adherence to the expectations of the ‘normative mother’ (Boyd 1996; Fineman 1995; Kline 1989). Marlee Kline evocatively summarized the significance of ideology in the regulation of motherhood and highlighted its relationship to traditional family structures during a period of proliferation of literature on the ideology of motherhood (e.g. Fineman and Karpin 1995): By the dominant ideology of motherhood, I mean the constellation of ideas and images in western capitalist societies that constitute the dominant ideals of motherhood against which women’s lives are judged. The expectations established by these ideals limit and shape the choices women make in their lives, and construct the dominant criteria of ‘good’ and ‘bad’ mothering. They exist within a framework of dominant ideologies of motherhood, which, in turn, intersect with dominant ideologies of family. (Kline 1993: 310) The key normative expectations associated with the ideology of motherhood are that (1) a woman must be a mother before she will be considered a proper adult woman, thus tying motherhood with femininity; (2) a ‘good’ mother will be selflessly available to her children, taking primary care of them; (3) a ‘good’ mother will do so in the context of a heterosexual, nuclear family model premised on privatized female dependence and domesticity. These expectations may shift over time and even countenance working mothers (Boyd 2003; Murphy 4 1998), but those who deviate may still be constructed as unfit, which in turn can compromise their legal ties with their children. At best, mothers may ‘win’ a legal claim, but in a manner that reproduces oppressive dominant norms about women and mothers. For instance, arguments from both prosecution and defence in relation to mothers who are charged with murdering their infants often reinforce dominant norms of motherhood (Cunliffe 2011). Whereas the prosecution typically attempts to portray the woman as a bad mother because she departs from those norms, the defence offers evidence of the woman’s conformity with maternal ideals. The requirement that mothers behave selflessly in relation to children in their primary care has important consequences, not least by limiting their ability to take up paid work. As well, mothers’ rights are often constructed in opposition to the rights of their children, which may undermine ‘the fundamental bond that exists between most mothers and their children’ (Murphy 1998: 691). This oppositional treatment of mothers and children is manifested particularly in relation to child protection law, where women can be defined as failing to adequately protect their children even if the risk to the child is generated by other factors, such as poverty (Kline 1993). Even more acute are situations where a pregnant woman is positioned as a risk to the health of her fetus (Diduck 1993). This example illustrates that law is not the only institution that reproduces the ideology of motherhood through its discursive power: ‘discourses such as feminism, modern rationality, science, social work and psychology’ interact with law ‘in a kind of shifting hierarchy’ and also ‘are imbued with such factors as race, class and sexuality’ (Diduck 1993: 462). In combination with other professional discourses, such as science or medicine or psychiatry, law can be particularly powerful in scrutinizing maternal conduct,
Recommended publications
  • All Mixed up About Mixed Questions
    The Journal of Appellate Practice and Process Volume 7 Issue 1 Article 7 2005 All Mixed Up about Mixed Questions Randall H. Warner Follow this and additional works at: https://lawrepository.ualr.edu/appellatepracticeprocess Part of the Jurisprudence Commons, and the Rule of Law Commons Recommended Citation Randall H. Warner, All Mixed Up about Mixed Questions, 7 J. APP. PRAC. & PROCESS 101 (2005). Available at: https://lawrepository.ualr.edu/appellatepracticeprocess/vol7/iss1/7 This document is brought to you for free and open access by Bowen Law Repository: Scholarship & Archives. It has been accepted for inclusion in The Journal of Appellate Practice and Process by an authorized administrator of Bowen Law Repository: Scholarship & Archives. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE JOURNAL OF APPELLATE PRACTICE AND PROCESS ARTICLES ALL MIXED UP ABOUT MIXED QUESTIONS* Randall H. Warner** I. INTRODUCTION "Elusive abominations."' Among the countless opinions that wrestle with so-called "mixed questions of law and fact," one from the Court of Claims best summed up the problem with these two words. The Ninth Circuit was more direct, if less poetic, when it said that mixed question jurisprudence "lacks clarity and coherence."2 And as if to punctuate the point, Black's Law Dictionary offers a definition that is perfectly clear and perfectly circular: "A question depending for solution on questions of both law and fact, but is really a question3 of either law or fact to be decided by either judge or jury." * © 2005 Randall H. Warner. All rights reserved. ** The author is an appellate lawyer with the Phoenix firm of Jones, Skelton & Hochuli, PLC.
    [Show full text]
  • Theorizing Legal Needs: Towards a Caring Legal System
    Theorizing Legal Needs: Towards a Caring Legal System Benjamin Miller A thesis submitted to the Faculty of Graduate and Postdoctoral Studies in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the MA degree in Political Science School of Political Studies Faculty of Social Sciences University of Ottawa Ottawa, Canada 2016 2 Table of Contents Table of Contents Abstract...................................................................................................................................... 5 Acknowledgements .................................................................................................................... 6 Introduction ................................................................................................................................ 7 The Ethics of Care: An Introduction ........................................................................................ 8 Plan of the Work ....................................................................................................................11 Method & Conceptual Framework .........................................................................................12 Practical Value ......................................................................................................................15 Prima Facie Issues ................................................................................................................15 Chapter 1: Legal Needs ............................................................................................................18
    [Show full text]
  • Truth and the Law: a Critical View of Community
    TRUTH AND THE LAW: A CRITICAL VIEW OF COMMUNITY Jan G. Deutsch * I Oliver Wendell Holmes, Jr. was masterful both as a judge and as a phrasemaker. The study of law inevitably includes acquaintance with his description of the common law: "The life of the law has not been logic: it has been experience." 1 A typical Holmes phrase, the description is striking, clear, memorable-and incapable of with- standing rigorous scrutiny. Logic may not be all there is to law, but clearly logic is necessary to law. The justification for legal coercion is the proposition that like cases should be decided alike, and without logic we have no assurance that we can construct valid categories in terms of which to define like cases. How, then, can one understand what Holmes has written? Holmes was wounded in a war which was fought to gain freedom for slaves, and which produced the political excesses of Reconstruc- tion and the economic excesses of rapid industrialization. Experience taught Holmes to live with conflict and paradox, to accept the propo- sition that logic provides no easy answers to important questions. Ex- perience sounds more flexible and organic than logic, but as a guide to the correct decision, it fares no better. "'[Brandeis],'" said Holmes, "'always desires to know all that can be known about a case whereas I am afraid that I wish to know as little as I can safely go on.' "2 Holmes was certain that facts alone- the talisman which justified Brandeis's infatuation with the collection of statistics-would provide no basis on which to determine how little a judge "can safely go on." This divergence, on its face, is about tech- niques of judging.
    [Show full text]
  • Mixed Questions of Law and Fact and the Administrative Procedure Act
    Fordham Law Review Volume 19 Issue 1 Article 3 1950 Mixed Questions of Law and Fact and the Administrative Procedure Act Bernard Schwartz Follow this and additional works at: https://ir.lawnet.fordham.edu/flr Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Bernard Schwartz, Mixed Questions of Law and Fact and the Administrative Procedure Act, 19 Fordham L. Rev. 73 (1950). Available at: https://ir.lawnet.fordham.edu/flr/vol19/iss1/3 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by FLASH: The Fordham Law Archive of Scholarship and History. It has been accepted for inclusion in Fordham Law Review by an authorized editor of FLASH: The Fordham Law Archive of Scholarship and History. For more information, please contact [email protected]. MIXED QUESTIONS OF LAW AND FACT AND THE ADMINISTRATIVE PROCEDURE ACT BERNARD SCHWARTZt J UDICIAL review of administrative action is based upon the distinction between "law" and "fact". Questions of law are to be decided ju- dicially, for the judge, both by training and tradition, is best equipped to deal with them. "Our desire to have courts determine questions of law is related to a belief in their possession of expertness with regard to such questions."' These considerations do not apply with equal force to the judicial review of the factual issues arising out of administrative deter- minations. There, the advantages of expertise are with the administrator. The fact "findings of an expert commission have a validity to which no judicial examination can pretend; the decision, for instance, of the New York Public Service Commission that a gas company ought to provide gas service for a given district is almost inevitably more right than a decision pronounced by the Courts in a similar case." 2 A theory of review based upon the "law-fact" distinction assumes that there is a more or less clear-cut division between "law' and "fact", with the former for the judge and the latter for the administrator.
    [Show full text]
  • 19 No Right Answer?
    JOBNAME: Jackson PAGE: 1 SESS: 37 OUTPUT: Thu Sep 4 12:06:29 2008 19 No Right Answer? JAMES Q WHITMAN I. INTRODUCTION HE TITLE OF this essay is, of course, lifted from one of the most famous articles in the literature of Anglo-American legal philoso- Tphy.1 As we all know, Ronald Dworkin argued, in his 1977 article ‘No Right Answer?’, that there must indeed always be a right answer to any given question of law, despite the many seemingly intractable disagree- ments we discover among lawyers and judges. Dworkin’s claims have drawn numerous responses, and the ‘no right answer?’ debate has assumed a central place in the literature of legal philosophy.2 Why do I begin an essay celebrating Mirjan Damaška’s work in comparative law by invoking a debate among the legal philosophers? Because one of Damaška’s many striking contributions is his own analysis of the ‘no right answer’ problem. Indeed, Damaška has devoted much of his scholarly career to the question of whether legal systems must inevita- bly be committed to seeking the right answer, starting with his first major article in the pages of an American law review. ‘The Continental,’ Damaška argued in 1968, will seek the right solution; his [American] counterpart will display a liberal agnosticism about “right” answers, coupled with a procedural outlook. Instead of seeking the right answer, the American lawyer ‘will be primarily concerned about good arguments for a case.’3 In intriguing contrast to Dworkin, Damaška thus argued in 1968 that American law was excep- tional among leading western systems in its reluctance to ‘seek’ right answers.
    [Show full text]
  • Questions of Fact in the Practice of Law: a Response to Allen & Pardo's Facts in Law, Facts of Law Paul F
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by University of Montana School of Law The Alexander Blewett III School of Law The Scholarly Forum @ Montana Law Faculty Journal Articles & Other Writings Faculty Publications 2004 Questions of Fact in the Practice of Law: A Response to Allen & Pardo's Facts in Law, Facts of Law Paul F. Kirgis Alexander Blewett I I School of Law at the University of Montana, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.law.umt.edu/faculty_barjournals Part of the Evidence Commons Recommended Citation Paul F. Kirgis, Questions of Fact in the Practice of Law: A Response to Allen & Pardo's Facts in Law, Facts of Law , 8 Int'l J. Evid. & Proof 47 (2004), Available at: http://scholarship.law.umt.edu/faculty_barjournals/112 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Faculty Publications at The choS larly Forum @ Montana Law. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faculty Journal Articles & Other Writings by an authorized administrator of The choS larly Forum @ Montana Law. QUESTIONS OF FACT IN THE PRACTICE OF LAW: A RESPONSE TO ALLEN & PARDO’S FACTS IN LAW AND FACTS OF LAW Paul F. Kirgis* In their article Facts in Law and Facts of Law,1 Professor Ronald Allen and Michael Pardo criticize efforts to distinguish questions of ‘law’ from questions of ‘fact’ based on the nature of the issue under consideration. In convincing fashion, they demonstrate that there is no ontological, epistemological, or analytical distinction between
    [Show full text]
  • General Jurisprudence
    University of Miami International and Comparative Law Review Volume 15 Issue 1 Volume 15 Issue 1 Article 2 4-1-2007 General Jurisprudence William Twining Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.law.miami.edu/umiclr Part of the Comparative and Foreign Law Commons, and the International Law Commons Recommended Citation William Twining, General Jurisprudence, 15 U. Miami Int’l & Comp. L. Rev. 1 (2007) Available at: https://repository.law.miami.edu/umiclr/vol15/iss1/2 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at University of Miami School of Law Institutional Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in University of Miami International and Comparative Law Review by an authorized editor of University of Miami School of Law Institutional Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. GENERAL JURISPRUDENCE I WILLIAM TWINING* I. Introduction .............................................................. 3 IIA. The Significance of "Globalization" ...................... 11 IIB. "General Jurisprudence"........................................ 16 Ic. Jurisprudence, Legal Philosophy, and Socio-Legal This paper is a sequel to WILLIAM TWINING, GLOBALISATION AND LEGAL THEORY (2000) [hereinafter GLT] and WILLIAM TWINING, Reviving General Jurisprudence, in THE GREAT JURISTIC BAZAAR 335-363 (2002) [hereinafter GJB]; see also WILLIAM TWINING, Reviving General Jurisprudence, in TRANSNATIONAL LEGAL PROCESSES: GLOBALIZATION AND POWER DISPARITIES 3-22 (Michael Likosky ed., 2002); WILLIAM TWINING, The Province of Jurisprudence Re-examined, in JURISPRUDENCE FOR AN INTERCONNECTED GLOBE 13-42 (Catherine Dauvergne ed., 2003); William Twining, A Post- Westphalian Conception of Law, 37 LAW & SOC'Y REV. 199 (2003) [hereinafter PWCL]; William Twining, Have Concepts, Will Travel: Analytical Jurisprudence in a Global Context, 1 INT'L J.
    [Show full text]
  • New Seditious Libel Judith Schenck Koffler
    Cornell Law Review Volume 69 Article 5 Issue 4 April 1984 New Seditious Libel Judith Schenck Koffler Bennett L. Gershman Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.law.cornell.edu/clr Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Judith Schenck Koffler and Bennett L. Gershman, New Seditious Libel, 69 Cornell L. Rev. 816 (1984) Available at: http://scholarship.law.cornell.edu/clr/vol69/iss4/5 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at Scholarship@Cornell Law: A Digital Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Cornell Law Review by an authorized administrator of Scholarship@Cornell Law: A Digital Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE NEW SEDITIOUS LIBEL Judith Schenck Koffert & Bennett L Gershman t Let all men take heede how they complayne in wordes against any magistrate, for they are gods. -- Star Chamber saying You've just got to trust us. -Richard Helms, former CIA Director INTRODUCTION Seditious libel is the crime of criticizing the government. It trans- forms dissent, which the first amendment has traditionally been thought to protect, into heresy. Fundamentally antidemocratic, the distinguish- ing feature of seditious libel is, as its nomenclature suggests, injury to the reputation of government or its functionaries. Those who impugn au- thority's good image are diabolized and their criticisms punished as blasphemy. In this way, the doctrine lends a juristic mask to political repression. Seditious libel is alive and well despite attempts of judges and scholars to knock it on the head once and for all.' It is difficult to recog- nize, however, for it wears the mantle of official secrecy and waves the banner of national security.
    [Show full text]
  • What Is a Question of Law? Arthur W
    College of William & Mary Law School William & Mary Law School Scholarship Repository Faculty Publications Faculty and Deans 1949 What is a Question of Law? Arthur W. Phelps William & Mary Law School Repository Citation Phelps, Arthur W., "What is a Question of Law?" (1949). Faculty Publications. 810. https://scholarship.law.wm.edu/facpubs/810 Copyright c 1949 by the authors. This article is brought to you by the William & Mary Law School Scholarship Repository. https://scholarship.law.wm.edu/facpubs WHAT IS A "QUESTION OF LAW"? ARTHUR W. PHELPS Professor of Jurisprudence, College of William and Mary The courts have for many years been developing and using a broad concept which at times has threatened to bring chaos rather than light to the solution of the legal problems it has affected. This concept enunciates the division between questions of law and questions of fact. It is broader than the question of the function of court and jury, for it has achieved significance in the determina­ tion of question of the scope of review which will be accorded by appellate courts in jury-waived cases, ad­ ministrative review, and substantively with respect to mistake, fraud, warranty and the like. It is immediately clear that a legal system . which postulates norms (roughly, rules and principles of law) must make some differentiation between a norm and the question of the existence of the facts which call for its application. If this view is accepted, rather than some anarchical conception of law derived from Justice Holmes' casual observation that law is what the courts do in fact, it is of importance to formulate some sort of category to indicate that the establishment of a claim involves the proof that certain facts exist, and to the contingency of their existence the state attaches the legal consequences now asserted by the claimant.1 Newer schools of thought in jurisprudence when deal­ ing with the nature of law seem to place little emphasis upon the relative cohesion, symmetry, and predictability that a body of legal doctrine can acquire.
    [Show full text]
  • The Rights of Others: Legal Claims and Immigration Outside the Law
    MOTOMURA IN FINAL 3/30/2010 6:17:43 AM THE RIGHTS OF OTHERS: LEGAL CLAIMS AND IMMIGRATION OUTSIDE THE LAW HIROSHI MOTOMURA† ABSTRACT This Article analyzes the rights of unauthorized migrants and elucidates how these noncitizens are incompletely but importantly integrated into the U.S. legal system. I examine four topics: (1) state and local laws targeting unauthorized migrants, (2) workplace rights and remedies, (3) suppression of evidence from an unlawful search or seizure, and (4) the right to effective counsel in immigration court. These four inquiries show how unauthorized migrants—though unable to assert individual rights as directly as U.S. citizens in the same circumstances—can nevertheless assert rights indirectly and obliquely by making transsubstantive arguments that fall into five general patterns. The first is an institutional competence argument that Copyright © 2010 by Hiroshi Motomura. † Susan Westerberg Prager Professor of Law, School of Law, University of California, Los Angeles. My title is inspired (loosely) by the film, Das Leben der Anderen, directed by Florian Henckel von Donnersmarck, translated as The Lives of Others. The title also echoes and acknowledges SELYA BENHABIB, THE RIGHTS OF OTHERS: ALIENS, RESIDENTS, AND CITIZENS (2004). This Article is part of a book project based on the conceptual framework in Hiroshi Motomura, Immigration Outside the Law, 108 COLUM. L. REV. 2037 (2008). Please send comments by e-mail to [email protected]. For very helpful conversations and comments on earlier drafts, I would like to thank Asli Bâli, Fred Bloom, Adam Cox, Keith Cunningham-Parmeter, Ingrid Eagly, Nicholas Espíritu, Deep Gulasekaram, Jerry Kang, Stephen Lee, Steve Legomsky, Hans Linnartz, Joe Landau, Steven Munzer, Cristina Rodríguez, Deborah Weissman, Adam Winkler, Noah Zatz, and participants in faculty colloquia at the University of Florida Levin College of Law, the University of California, Irvine, School of Law, the UCLA School of Law, and in the Duke Law Journal’s Administrative Law Symposium.
    [Show full text]
  • 17-9560 Rehaif V. United States (06/21/2019)
    (Slip Opinion) OCTOBER TERM, 2018 1 Syllabus NOTE: Where it is feasible, a syllabus (headnote) will be released, as is being done in connection with this case, at the time the opinion is issued. The syllabus constitutes no part of the opinion of the Court but has been prepared by the Reporter of Decisions for the convenience of the reader. See United States v. Detroit Timber & Lumber Co., 200 U. S. 321, 337. SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES Syllabus REHAIF v. UNITED STATES CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS FOR THE ELEVENTH CIRCUIT No. 17–9560. Argued April 23, 2019—Decided June 21, 2019 Petitioner Rehaif entered the United States on a nonimmigrant student visa to attend university but was dismissed for poor grades. He sub- sequently shot two firearms at a firing range. The Government pros- ecuted him under 18 U. S. C. §922(g), which makes it unlawful for certain persons, including aliens illegally in the country, to possess firearms, and §924(a)(2), which provides that anyone who “knowingly violates” the first provision can be imprisoned for up to 10 years. The jury at Rehaif’s trial was instructed that the Government was not re- quired to prove that he knew that he was unlawfully in the country. It returned a guilty verdict. The Eleventh Circuit affirmed. Held: In a prosecution under §922(g) and §924(a)(2), the Government must prove both that the defendant knew he possessed a firearm and that he knew he belonged to the relevant category of persons barred from possessing a firearm.
    [Show full text]
  • Brierly's Law of Nations
    BRIERLY’S LAW OF NATIONS This page intentionally left blank BRIERLY’S LAW OF NATIONS An Introduction to the Role of International Law in International Relations SEVENTH EDITION A NDREW C LAPHAM 1 1 Great Clarendon Street, Oxford, OX2 6DP, United Kingdom Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University’s objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide. Oxford is a registered trade mark of Oxford University Press in the UK and in certain other countries © Andrew Clapham 2012 Th e moral rights of the author have been asserted First Edition published in 2012 Impression: 1 All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, without the prior permission in writing of Oxford University Press, or as expressly permitted by law, by licence or under terms agreed with the appropriate reprographics rights organization. Enquiries concerning reproduction outside the scope of the above should be sent to the Rights Department, Oxford University Press, at the address above You must not circulate this work in any other form and you must impose this same condition on any acquirer Crown copyright material is reproduced under Class Licence Number C01P0000148 with the permission of OPSI and the Queen’s Printer for Scotland British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data Data available Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data Data available ISBN 978–0–19–965793–3 978–0–19–965794–0 (pbk) Printed in Great Britain by CPI Group (UK) Ltd, Croydon, CR0 4YY Links to third party websites are provided by Oxford in good faith and for information only.
    [Show full text]