Athens and Byzantium: Platonic Political Philosophy in Religious Empire Jeremiah Heath Russell Louisiana State University and Agricultural and Mechanical College
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Louisiana State University LSU Digital Commons LSU Doctoral Dissertations Graduate School 2010 Athens and Byzantium: Platonic political philosophy in religious empire Jeremiah Heath Russell Louisiana State University and Agricultural and Mechanical College Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_dissertations Part of the Political Science Commons Recommended Citation Russell, Jeremiah Heath, "Athens and Byzantium: Platonic political philosophy in religious empire" (2010). LSU Doctoral Dissertations. 2978. https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_dissertations/2978 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at LSU Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in LSU Doctoral Dissertations by an authorized graduate school editor of LSU Digital Commons. For more information, please [email protected]. ATHENS AND BYZANTIUM: PLATONIC POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY IN RELIGIOUS EMPIRE A Dissertation Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of the Louisiana State University Agricultural and Mechanical College in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in The Department of Political Science by Jeremiah Heath Russell B.A., The Southern Baptist Theological Seminary, 2001 M. Div., The Southern Baptist Theological Seminary, 2003 M.A., Baylor University, 2006 August, 2010 ACKNOWLEDGMENTS This dissertation was not possible without the numerous sources of support that I received throughout my graduate studies. First, I must thank my major professor, James R. Stoner, Jr., whose encouragement was there from my earliest days at LSU until the completion of this program. He is a model intellectual with an uncanny ability to identify the heart of the matter and to offer penetrating questions. My commitment to the importance of the political, reflected in this dissertation, I owe to him. Moreover, his interest in the early stages of this project, the continued feedback, and the constant prodding to finish helped ensure its completion. I also want to thank him for his procurement of the Earhart fellowship, which made it possible for me to focus solely on my studies for four years. Gratitude is also in order to the Earhart Foundation, whose long support of political science scholarship has made a lasting impact on our discipline. I must also thank the other members of my dissertation committee. Two of the members, along with Stoner, compromised the political theory faculty at LSU during my coursework. These three men make up one of the preeminent theory faculties in the country, and I am honored to have finished the program under their tutelage. Cecil L. Eubanks, my teaching mentor, is an exemplary educator. His care for the subject matter, and more importantly the students, is something that I hope to emulate in my own career. He always has an open door, willing to listen, and his office served as a shelter for me during some stormy times. G. Ellis Sandoz also provided encouragement throughout my studies. He was instrumental in my coming to LSU and provided me an early platform to express my ideas. Much like Eubanks, Sandoz‟s academic career is exemplary, and his seemingly tireless efforts in publishing and editing scholarly works in political theory are inspiring. Besides the theorists, I want to thank William ii A. Clark, who first exposed me to the world of comparative politics; Ian Crystal for bringing his expertise on Neoplatonism to bear on my dissertation; and Dean W. David Constant for his willingness to serve. Last, but certainly not least, I must thank my family for supporting me throughout my education, particularly my doctoral program. My wife, Ashleigh, is a special and unique person, whose willingness to give is seemingly endless. As I write this on the day we celebrate our tenth year of marriage, I can honestly say that her dedication and encouragement to me over these years is perhaps the most important reason for my success. My daughter, Elizabeth, provided me determination as well as perspective. To all these and others not mentioned, I am forever grateful. iii TABLE OF CONTENTS ACKNOWLEDGMENTS . ii LIST OF TABLES . v ABSTRACT . vi CHAPTER 1 INTRODUCTION: THE TENSION BETWEEN ATHENS AND BYZANTIUM . 1 CHAPTER 2 POLITICAL SCIENCE IN THE NEOPLATONIC CURRICULUM . 30 CHAPTER 3 THE STATESMAN AND THE BEST REGIME . 67 CHAPTER 4 CONSTITUTING THE BEST REGIME: MYTH . 103 CHAPTER 5 CONSTITUTING THE BEST REGIME: RHETORIC . 133 CHAPTER 6 THE STATESMAN‟S RETREAT IN A CORRUPT REGIME . 157 CHAPTER 7 CONCLUSION: THE TENSION REVISITED . 193 BIBLIOGRAPHY. 207 VITA . 221 iv LIST OF TABLES 2.1 The Hierarchy of Virtue . 43 2.2 The Neoplatonic Curriculum . 52 v ABSTRACT It is traditionally understood that there is a gap, which spans well over one thousand years, between Plato‟s own political philosophy and its successor in medieval Islamic philosophy. A most likely bridge between Plato and these later philosophers is Neoplatonism. However, scholars argue that this philosophic school abandoned its predecessor‟s emphasis on political philosophy. This dissertation challenges the traditional interpretation by reconstructing a political philosophy based on a Neoplatonic commentary on Plato‟s Gorgias. The first two chapters place this commentary within its historical context, as well as its place within the larger Neoplatonic pedagogy. The remainder of the dissertation reconstructs the commentator‟s political philosophy. The third chapter discusses his understanding of the best regime and the art of statesmanship, which in many ways is the centerpiece of his political philosophy. Chapters four and five discuss myth and rhetoric, the tools needed by the statesman to bring about the best regime. The following chapter revisits the theme of statesmanship, particularly the notion of the philosopher as statesman. vi CHAPTER 1 INTRODUCTION: THE TENSION BETWEEN ATHENS AND BYZANTIUM “[Athenian:] Is it god or some human being . who is given the credit for laying down your laws? . [Klenias: A god] . But since you and this man here were reared in such conventions and habits, I expect it would not be unpleasant for you to pass the present time discussing the political regime and laws, talking and listening as we go on our way.” —Plato, Laws 624a-625a One of the more significant contributions of political philosopher Leo Strauss (1899- 1973) is the recovery of the tension between the two roots of Western civilization, religion and philosophy, or as he put it, “Jerusalem and Athens.”1 By religion, Strauss had in mind monotheistic religion, particularly Judaism and Islam, and by philosophy, he meant Greek philosophy as a “way of life,” exemplified by Socrates.2 Initially, he recalled the things they share, such as a commitment to monotheism, the love of man, and a “broad agreement” regarding morality, as well as its insufficiency for achieving the highest human happiness. As a matter of fact, Strauss acknowledges that they appear so similar that it is easy to forget their fundamental conflict, a mistake made by many modern thinkers. This conflict is expressed in 1 Leo Strauss, “Jerusalem and Athens,” in Studies in Platonic Political Philosophy (Chicago, Ill.: University of Chicago Press, 1983); “The Mutual Influence of Theology and Philosophy,” The Independent Journal of Philosophy 3 (1979): 111-18; “Progress or Return?” in Jewish Philosophy and the Crisis of Modernity: Essays and Lectures in Modern Jewish Thought, edited by Kenneth Hart Green (Albany, N.Y.: SUNY Press, 1997). 2 Historically, the tension between philosophy and religion first emerged with the pre-Socratic philosophers. These “natural” philosophers rejected mythological accounts of the cosmos and sought rational explanations for the origins and substance of the cosmos. Thales, for example, argued that water was the substance of which all things were composed. The gods, as presented by the poets, were also the subject of criticism. Xenophanes argued that the poets imagined gods in terms of human beings: “But mortals consider that the gods are born, and that they have clothes and speech and bodies like their own.” Moreover, he writes, “The Ethopians say that their gods are snub-nosed and black, the Thracians that theirs have light blue eyes and red hair.” He continues, “But if cattle and horses or lions had hands, or were able to draw their hands and do the works that men can do, horses would draw the forms of the gods like horses, and cattle like cattle, and they would make their bodies such as they each had themselves” (Fragments 14, 16, 15). For surviving fragments of the pre-Socratics see G.S. Kirk, J.E. Raven and M. Schofield, The Presocratic Philosophers (New York, N.Y.: Cambridge University Press, 1983). 1 terms of what completes morality, either piety (or the need for redemption) in the case of religion or contemplation in the case of philosophy. This initial disagreement points to a second, methodological conflict. Strauss argues that religion believes the good is equated to the ancestral, whereas philosophy seeks to transcend such convention by searching for what is right by nature. The pious person then is obedient to one ancient, divine law and rejects the alternatives, whereas the philosopher transcends the dimension of divine law altogether, in part because of the very recognition of a variety of divine codes that are contradictory between themselves. Thus, in contrast to the religious person, a philosopher can never admit to the “absolute sacredness of a particular or contingent event,” in this case a particular revelation. The philosopher searches for that which is universal, based on “sense perception and reasoning.” Yet Strauss‟ distinction appears problematic when applied to arguably the most influential of the monotheistic religions, Christianity. First of all, Christianity and philosophy were typically viewed as compatible by the Church Fathers. Almost from the religion‟s inception, Christian theologians used philosophy as a tool to express and expound the teaching of Christ and his apostles. The precision found in the formulation of doctrine, as it developed in antiquity and the medieval period, was impossible without the language and concepts of philosophy.