The Importance of the Meno on the Transition from the Early to the Middle Platonic Dialogues a Thesis Submitted to the Graduate

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Importance of the Meno on the Transition from the Early to the Middle Platonic Dialogues a Thesis Submitted to the Graduate THE IMPORTANCE OF THE MENO ON THE TRANSITION FROM THE EARLY TO THE MIDDLE PLATONIC DIALOGUES A THESIS SUBMITTED TO THE GRADUATE SCHOOL OF SOCIAL SCIENCES OF MIDDLE EAST TECHNICAL UNIVERSITY BY TONGUÇ SEFEROĞLU IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF MASTER OF ARTS IN DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY MAY 2012 Approval of the Graduate School of Social Sciences Prof. Dr.Meliha Altunışık Director I certify that this thesis satisfies all the requirements as a thesis for the degree of Master of Arts Prof. Dr. Ahmet İnam Head of Department This is to certify that we have read this thesis and that in our opinion it is fully adequate, in scope and quality, as a thesis for the degree of Master of Arts. Doç. Dr. Samet Bağçe Supervisor Examining Committee Members Doç. Dr. Barış Parkan (METU, PHIL) Doç. Dr. Erdoğan Yıldırım (METU, SOC) Doç. Dr. Samet Bağçe (METU, PHIL) I hereby declare that all information in this document has been obtained and presented in accordance with academic rules and ethical conduct. I also declare that, as required by these rules and conduct, I have fully cited and referenced all material and results that are not original to this work. Name, Last name : Tonguç Seferoğlu Signature: iii ABSTRACT THE IMPORTANCE OF THE MENO ON THE TRANSITION FROM THE EARLY TO THE MIDDLE PLATONIC DIALOGUES Seferoğlu, Tonguç M.A. in Philosophy Supervisor: Doç. Dr. Samet Bağçe May 2012, 148 pages The purpose of the present study is to signify the explanatory value of the Meno on the coherence as well as the disparateness of the Plato’s early and middle dialogues. Indeed, the Meno exposes the transition on the content and form of these dialogues. The first part of the dialogue resembles the Socrates’ way of investigation, the so-called Elenchus, whereas Plato presents his own philosophical project in the second part of the dialogue. Three fundamental elements of Plato’s middle dialogues explicitly arise for the very first time in the Meno, namely; the recollection, the hypothetical method and reasoning out the explanation. Therefore, the connexion of the early and middle dialogues can be understood better if the structure of the Meno is analyzed properly. In other words, the Meno is the keystone dialogue which enables the readers of Plato to sense the development in Socratic-Platonic philosophy. Keywords: Plato, Socrates, the Meno, recollection, elenctic investigation. iv ÖZ ERKEN DÖNEM DİALOGLARDAN ORTA DÖNEME GEÇİŞTE MENON’UN ÖNEMİ Seferoğlu, Tonguç Yüksek Lisans, Felsefe Bölümü Tez Yöneticisi: Doç. Dr. Samet Bağçe Mayıs 2012, 148 sayfa Bu çalışmanın amacı Menon’un Plato’un erken ve orta dialoglarının uyumluluğunu olduğu kadar farklılıklarını da açıklayan bir değer taşıdığını işaret etmektir. Gerçekten de, Menon bu dialoglar arasındaki içeriksel ve biçimsel değişikliği ortaya koymaktadır. Dialoğun ilk kısmı Socrates’in araştırma yolunu, yani Elenkus’u, çağrıştırırıken, Platon ikinci kısımda kendi felsefi planını sunmaya başlamıştır. Orta dönem dialoglarının temel parçaları ilk kez Menon’da karşımıza çıkar: anımsama, hipotez yöntemi ve açıklamayı çözümlemek. Bu yüzden, eğer Menon’un yapısı uygun biçimde incelenirse erken ve orta dialoglar daha iyi bir şekilde anlaşılabilir. Bir başka değişle, Menon Platon’un okuyucularının Sokratik-Platonik felsefede gelişmeyi sezmesinde kilit bir rol oynamaktadır. Anahtar kelimeler: Platon, Sokrates, Menon, anımsama, elenktik sorgulama. v To my first tutor, Binali Seferoğlu vi ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS Firstly, I would like to express my sincere appreciation to my supervisor, Doç. Dr. Samet Bağçe for his guidance, comments and contributions throughout the evolution of the text. I would also like to express my thankfulness to my committee members, Doç. Dr. Barış Parkan and Doç. Dr. Erdoğan Yıldırım for their important suggestions and valuable comments that made this work possible. I would like to thank the many other people who facilitated for me the process of writing, among whom are Feyza Eşim, Özgür Uçak, Nevzat Kaya, Serkan Acar, Haydar Öztürk and Başta Başar Binici. My family’s support made everything easier for me, for whom I am always thankful. I also thank to the staff of Kadıköy Belediyesi Ambalaj Atıkları Toplama ve Ayrıştırma Merkezi. I am also grateful to Şahan Evren and Besim Karakadılar for their illuminative and substantial comments on the earlier drafts of this work. I owe special thanks to Mehmet Fazıl Çelik and Zöhre Koçkan who have helped throughout the process of the preparation of the text. Their support have been incalculable to this day, their candidness is priceless which I cannot ask for more. vii TABLE OF CONTENTS PLAGIARISM……………………………………………………………………iii ABSTRACT………………………………………………………………………iv ÖZ…………………………………………………..……………………………..v DEDICATION……………………………………………………………………vi ACKNOWLEDGMENTS………...……………………………………………..vii TABLE OF CONTENTS………………………………………………………..viii CHAPTER 1. INTRODUCTION…….……………………………………………….………1 2. THE DIALOGUES OF PLATO………………………………...…..………..7 2.1. Constitution of Platonic Corpus……...……………………………………7 2.2. Ancient and Modern Interpretations of Plato………...………...………...10 2.3. Who is Socrates?……………………...………………………………….21 3. THE EARLY DIALOGUES………………………………………………...29 3.1. Socrates Moral Aspiration...……………………………………………...29 3.2. Socrates' Epistemology (the Elenchus)……………………..……………32 3.3. Disavowal of Knowledge……………………..………………………….39 4. THE EARLY AND MIDDLE DIALOGUES: A DIVISION?.....................48 4.1. Epistemic Differences……………………………………………………49 4.2. Ontological Differences …………………....……………………………51 4.3 Methodological Differences......…………………………………………55 viii 4.4. Mathematical Differences………………………………………………..64 4.5. The Beginnings of Transition……..………………………………...……69 5. THE MENO………………..…………………………………………………75 5.1. Significance of theDialogue…………………………………….…….….75 5.2. Priority of Definition……………………………………...……………...78 5.3. The Dialectical Requirement (DR)…………………………………….....84 5.4. Meno's Paradox……………………………………...…………………...88 5.5. The Anamnesis…………….............………..……………………………93 5.5.1. Religious and Mythical Content……...……………………………..94 5.5.2. Epistemological and Metaphysical Aspects…………..…………...100 5.5.3. The Slave Boy Demonstration……………………………………..101 5.6. The Distinction between True Belief and Knowledge…………...……..111 5.7. Hypotheses………….………..………………………………………….116 5.8. Aitias Logismos…………...……...……………………………………..121 6. CONCLUSION………………………………………...…………...……….128 BIBLIOGRAPHY…………………………..…………………………………135 APPENDICES ix CHAPTER 1 INTRODUCTION: PLATO’S PROJECT Vlastos (1991), as well as many other scholars, remarks that the style and theme of Socratic-Platonic philosophy changes dramatically in the so-called transition from early dialogues to the middle ones, that is; the content, format and subject of Platonic works come through a metamorphosis, if not a radical variation. Indeed, Plato - unlike his hero Socrates' apathy to such domains - puts an epistemological and ontological model in and after the Meno.1 I believe, among all the transitional dialogues, the Meno involves outstanding philosophical implications. In other words, the development of Plato’s ideas in the Meno indicates the transformation from pretty much moral content of the early dialogues to a theoretical and systematic framework of the middle dialogues. In the middle dialogues, Plato undervalues Socrates' “disavowal of knowledge”, and then he claims certain knowledge can be grounded and “reasoned out from explanation.” In fact, whereas logos is instrumentally used in the moral investigations in the early dialogues, it becomes an essential element to have knowledge in the middle and late dialogues. That is to say, Plato, unlike Socrates, aims to give an elaborated reason and method for the pursuit of knowledge. In this 1 The Meno is “the first dialogue in which the impact of these new [mathematical] studies on the content and method of his philosophizing is allowed to surface freely.” (Vlastos, 1991, p.118) The Meno, according to Day, seems to be last of the early dialogues (1994, pp. 9-12). 1 respect, throughout this work, I intend to show the epistemic, ontological and methodological enhancements in Socratic-Platonic philosophy which lead the way to the Plato’s most complex and comprehensive works. That is, my intention of writing on this subject is to re-evaluate the more or less diverging philosophical perspectives and motives of Plato and “Socrates” in Plato's dialogues. I suppose Plato's new epistemology which is more or less initiated with the Meno, i.e.; recollection, hypothetical method and reasoning out the explanation (aitias logoi), can be distinguished from Socrates' way of examination, i.e.; the elenchus.2 I none the less have to note that I do not mean to take apart Plato’s philosophy from Socratic perspective. That is to say, I will neither try to depict a non-Socratic Plato nor Socrates without Plato, on the contrary, I think that the Socratic elenchus may also be found at the core of Plato’s middle dialogues, if not solely. I also believe Plato has never abandoned “Sokratikoi logoi” in his works, which is “textually recreation of accounts of Socrates with his friends and interlocutors”.3 Another objective of this present thesis is to show the reason and format of the changeover from the early dialogues to the middle ones. In that sense, I come to believe that Plato systematizes a new philosophical outlook by developing Socrates’ moral investigations and their implications. In fact, Plato, in my opinion, has “reconstructed” Socrates’ philosophy by purposing a method to have certain and stable
Recommended publications
  • Plato's Euthyphro and Meno
    Plato's Euthyphro and Meno Reading and Essays Questions Exeter College, Oxford University, HT13 Tutor: Simona Aimar E-mail: [email protected] Weekly Meetings: TBA General Information This is a syllabus for eight weeks work for the first-year course on Plato’s Meno and Euthyphro. Please email your assignments to me 24h before the tutorials. I am afraid that I will not be able to write comments on essays that are handed in later than this (unless – for exceptional reasons, e.g. illness – I have agreed to this beforehand). You are required to do at least five essays in the course of the term, plus one set of gobbets. You should each write an essay for the first tutorial. In week 7, you will write gobbets (comments on passages) instead of an essay. In any week when you do not do an essay/gobbets, you should do the reading and think about the question in advance of the tutorial, so that you are ready to discuss the essay question in the tutorial. We shall focus each week on one of the essays in the tutorial, alternating between you and the other student who will be attending the tutorials with you. If we are focusing on your essay, I’ll ask you to summarize it at the start of the tutorial. If we are focusing on someone else’s essay, you should have read her/his essay before the tutorial, and have spent some time thinking about whether you agree with it and how it might be improved.
    [Show full text]
  • Glaucon's Dilemma. the Origins of Social Order
    [Working draft. Please do not circulate or cite without author’s permission] Glaucon’s Dilemma. The origins of social order. Josiah Ober Chapter 2 of The Greeks and the Rational (book-in-progress, provisional title) Draft of 2019.09.20 Word count: 17,200. Abstract: The long Greek tradition of political thought understood that cooperation among multiple individuals was an imperative for human survival. The tradition (here represented by passages from Plato’s Republic, Gorgias, and Protagoras, and from Diodorus of Sicily’s universal history) also recognized social cooperation as a problem in need of a solution in light of instrumental rationality and self-interest, strategic behavior, and the option of free riding on the cooperation of others. Ancient “anthropological” theories of the origins of human cooperation proposed solutions to the problem of cooperation by varying the assumed motivations of agents and postulating repeated interactions with communication and learning. The ways that Greek writers conceived the origins of social order as a problem of rational cooperation can be modeled as strategic games: as variants of the non-cooperative Prisoners Dilemma and cooperative Stag Hunt games and as repeated games with incomplete information and updating. In book 2 of the Republic Plato’s Glaucon offered a carefully crafted philosophical challenge, in the form of a narrative thought experiment, to Socrates’ position that justice is supremely choice-worthy, the top-ranked preference of a truly rational person. Seeking to improve the immoralist argument urged by Thrasymachus in Republic book 1 (in order to give Socrates the opportunity to refute the best form of that argument), Glaucon told a tale of Gyges and his ring of invisibility.1 In chapter 1, I suggested that Glaucon’s story illustrated a pure form of rational and self-interested behavior, through revealed preferences when the ordinary constraints of uncertainty, enforceable social conventions, and others’ strategic choices were absent.
    [Show full text]
  • The Highest Good for Plato Goodness Is an Abstract Concept That Is Very
    The Highest Good for Plato Goodness is an abstract concept that is very difficult to define, and saying what counts as the highest good is perhaps even more so. In Republic, Plato attempts to say something about what makes things good, but his answer is very vague in the end. Still, we can get some clarity on what he would have answered if asked what the highest good is, from what he says in this text. What counts as the highest good for Plato can be said to be knowledge of the Form of the Good, because it is necessary for knowing and using the other Forms well. The nature of the Forms is not clear in Republic; Plato writes about them as if his audience already knows what they are. Still, we can get some sense of what forms are like from the text. In several places he says that when two or more things share the same name, then they share a form. For example, in Book IV Socrates and Glaucon talk about the form of justice: “…are things called by the same name, whether they are bigger or smaller than one another, like or unlike with respect to that to which the name applies? Alike. Then a just man won’t differ at all from a just city in respect to the form of justice; rather he’ll be like the city” (435 a-b). But what is a Form, exactly? We can start to get a sense of what Plato means by a Form by looking back at Euthyphro.
    [Show full text]
  • Theory of Forms 1 Theory of Forms
    Theory of Forms 1 Theory of Forms Plato's theory of Forms or theory of Ideas[1] [2] [3] asserts that non-material abstract (but substantial) forms (or ideas), and not the material world of change known to us through sensation, possess the highest and most fundamental kind of reality.[4] When used in this sense, the word form is often capitalized.[5] Plato speaks of these entities only through the characters (primarily Socrates) of his dialogues who sometimes suggest that these Forms are the only true objects of study that can provide us with genuine knowledge; thus even apart from the very controversial status of the theory, Plato's own views are much in doubt.[6] Plato spoke of Forms in formulating a possible solution to the problem of universals. Forms Terminology: the Forms and the forms The English word "form" may be used to translate two distinct concepts that concerned Plato—the outward "form" or appearance of something, and "Form" in a new, technical nature, that never ...assumes a form like that of any of the things which enter into her; ... But the forms which enter into and go out of her are the likenesses of real existences modelled after their patterns in a wonderful and inexplicable manner.... The objects that are seen, according to Plato, are not real, but literally mimic the real Forms. In the allegory of the cave expressed in Republic, the things that are ordinarily perceived in the world are characterized as shadows of the real things, which are not perceived directly. That which the observer understands when he views the world mimics the archetypes of the many types and properties (that is, of universals) of things observed.
    [Show full text]
  • Dr. Ionescu's CV
    Dr. Cristina Ionescu Associate Professor School of Philosophy The Catholic University of America Washington, D.C. Tel. 202 319 6641 [email protected] Academic Positions: 2015- present: Associate Professor, School of Philosophy, The Catholic University of America 2009 –2015: Assistant Professor, School of Philosophy, The Catholic University of America 2005–2009: Assistant Professor, Campion College, University of Regina, Canada Education: 2000–2005: Ph.D., University of Guelph. Title of Ph.D. Dissertation: “Plato’s Meno: An Interpretation.” Advisor: Kenneth Dorter 1999–2000: M.A., University of Bucharest, Faculty of Philosophy 1995–1999: B.A., University of Bucharest, Faculty of Philosophy Area of Specialization: Ancient Greek Philosophy (Plato) Area of Competency: Metaphysics, Heidegger, Modern Philosophy Publications: Books: On the Good Life: Thinking through the Intermediaries in Plato’s Philebus, SUNY Press, NY: 2019. Plato’s Meno: An Interpretation, Maryland: Rowman & Littlefield, Lexington Books, MD: 2007. Journal articles: “Elenchus and the Method of Division in Plato’s Sophist”, Platonic Dialectic (Routledge Press, forthcoming 2021). “Images and Paradigms in Plato’s Sophist and Statesman”, Ancient Philosophy 40, 2020. “Elenchus, Recollection, and the Method of Hypothesis in the Meno”, The Plato Journal 17, 2017: 9-29. “Due Measure and the Dialectical Method in Plato’s Statesman”, Journal of Philosophical Research 41, 2016: 77-104. “The Place of Pleasure and Knowledge in the Fourfold Articulation of 1 Reality in Plato’s Philebus” in Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy, XXX: 1-32: 2015. “Dialectical Method and Myth in Plato’s Statesman”, Ancient Philosophy 34, 2014: 1-18 “Dialectic in Plato’s Sophist: Division and the Communion of Kinds”, Arethusa 46, 2013: 41-64.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Arrangement of the Platonic Dialogues
    Ryan C. Fowler 25th Hour On the Arrangement of the Platonic Dialogues I. Thrasyllus a. Diogenes Laertius (D.L.), Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers 3.56: “But, just as long ago in tragedy the chorus was the only actor, and afterwards, in order to give the chorus breathing space, Thespis devised a single actor, Aeschylus a second, Sophocles a third, and thus tragedy was completed, so too with philosophy: in early times it discoursed on one subject only, namely physics, then Socrates added the second subject, ethics, and Plato the third, dialectics, and so brought philosophy to perfection. Thrasyllus says that he [Plato] published his dialogues in tetralogies, like those of the tragic poets. Thus they contended with four plays at the Dionysia, the Lenaea, the Panathenaea and the festival of Chytri. Of the four plays the last was a satiric drama; and the four together were called a tetralogy.” b. Characters or types of dialogues (D.L. 3.49): 1. instructive (ὑφηγητικός) A. theoretical (θεωρηµατικόν) a. physical (φυσικόν) b. logical (λογικόν) B. practical (πρακτικόν) a. ethical (ἠθικόν) b. political (πολιτικόν) 2. investigative (ζητητικός) A. training the mind (γυµναστικός) a. obstetrical (µαιευτικός) b. tentative (πειραστικός) B. victory in controversy (ἀγωνιστικός) a. critical (ἐνδεικτικός) b. subversive (ἀνατρεπτικός) c. Thrasyllan categories of the dialogues (D.L. 3.50-1): Physics: Timaeus Logic: Statesman, Cratylus, Parmenides, and Sophist Ethics: Apology, Crito, Phaedo, Phaedrus, Symposium, Menexenus, Clitophon, the Letters, Philebus, Hipparchus, Rivals Politics: Republic, the Laws, Minos, Epinomis, Atlantis Obstetrics: Alcibiades 1 and 2, Theages, Lysis, Laches Tentative: Euthyphro, Meno, Io, Charmides and Theaetetus Critical: Protagoras Subversive: Euthydemus, Gorgias, and Hippias 1 and 2 :1 d.
    [Show full text]
  • All of a Sudden: the Role of Ἐξαίφνης in Plato's Dialogues
    Duquesne University Duquesne Scholarship Collection Electronic Theses and Dissertations Spring 1-1-2014 All of a Sudden: The Role of Ἐξαιφ́ νης in Plato's Dialogues Joseph J. Cimakasky Follow this and additional works at: https://dsc.duq.edu/etd Recommended Citation Cimakasky, J. (2014). All of a Sudden: The Role of Ἐξαιφ́ νης in Plato's Dialogues (Doctoral dissertation, Duquesne University). Retrieved from https://dsc.duq.edu/etd/68 This Worldwide Access is brought to you for free and open access by Duquesne Scholarship Collection. It has been accepted for inclusion in Electronic Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Duquesne Scholarship Collection. For more information, please contact [email protected]. ALL OF A SUDDEN: THE ROLE OF ἘΧΑΙΦΝΗΣ IN PLATO’S DIALOGUES A Dissertation Submitted to the McAnulty College and Graduate School of Liberal Arts Duquesne University In partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy By Joseph Cimakasky May 2014 Copyright by Joseph Cimakasky 2014 ALL OF A SUDDEN: THE ROLE OF ἘΧΑΙΦΝΗΣ IN PLATO’S DIALOGUES By Joseph Cimakasky Approved April 9, 2014 ________________________________ ________________________________ Ronald Polansky Patrick Lee Miller Professor of Philosophy Professor of Philosophy (Committee Chair) (Committee Member) ________________________________ John W. McGinley Professor of Philosophy (Committee Member) ________________________________ ________________________________ James Swindal Ronald Polansky Dean, McAnulty College Chair, Philosophy Department Professor of Philosophy Professor of Philosophy iii ABSTRACT ALL OF A SUDDEN: THE ROLE OF ἘΧΑΙΦΝΗΣ IN PLATO’S DIALOGUES By Joseph Cimakasky May 2014 Dissertation supervised by Professor Ronald Polansky There are thirty-six appearances of the Greek word ἐξαίφνης in Plato’s dialogues.
    [Show full text]
  • Plato's Hypothetical Inquiry in the Meno Naoya Iwata
    Plato’s Hypothetical Inquiry in the Meno Naoya Iwata At Meno 86e2–4 Socrates proposes to Meno that they should consider the question whether virtue is teachable on a hypothesis. Partly because its concrete procedure is illustrated by a baffling geometrical example, there has still been wide disagreement among scholars as to how he actually carries out this hypothetical inquiry into virtue. The basic structure of the argument at 87b2–89a5 appears very simple: Socrates converts the original question whether virtue is teachable to the question whether it is knowledge, and then examines the latter on the basis of his agreement with Meno that virtue is good. Apart however from that agreement being, as it is explicitly called, a ‘hypothesis’, opinion is divided on what other hypothesis Socrates posited. Some think of it as the conditional ‘if virtue is knowledge, it is teachable’ or as ‘knowledge is teachable’ (Bedu-Addo 1984, 7–9; Wolfsdorf 2008, 44–6 and 58–60),1 and others as the bi-conditional ‘if virtue is knowledge, it is teachable, but if not, not’ or as ‘knowledge alone is teachable’ (Grgić 1999, 34–6; Weiss 2001, 131; Zyskind and Sternfeld 1976, 132). 2 But most scholars, in contrast, identify it with the simple proposition ‘virtue is knowledge’ (Bedu-Addo 1984, 7–9; Benson 2003, 107–25; Bluck 1961, 17–19 and 85–91; Bostock 1986, 165–6; Canto-Sperber 1991, 98–102; Cherniss 1947, 140; Hackforth 1955, 140–1; Kahn 1996, 310; Robinson 1953, 116–18; Rose 1970, 3–7; Sayre 1969, 29 n. 40; Scott 2006, 137–40 and 221–4; Sharples 1985, 167).3 It is also suggested that Socrates’ new philosophical tool does not involve any process of positing a hypothesis but only aims to establish the equivalence between teachability and knowledge (Ebrey 2013, 76 and 83–4).
    [Show full text]
  • The Form of the Good in Plato's Timaeus
    THANASSIS GKATZARAS | 71 One of the many philosophical problems The Form of the Good in that we face in the Timaeus is raised by the Plato’s Timaeus claim that the God who created the world (from now on we shall call him ‘Demiurge’)1 is good (Tim. 29d7-30a2). A satisfying explanation of Demiurge’s goodness is far from easy, and dif- ferent approaches have been proposed. How- ever, in this paper I’ll try to show that a clear, sufficient and relatively simple interpretation is possible, if we are based on the hypothesis that Timaeus follows the theory of causation in the Phaedo (including the distinction between ‘safe’ and ‘elegant’ cause) and the concept of the Thanassis Gkatzaras Form of the Good in the Republic.2 University of Ioannina [email protected] To be more specific, I’ll try to show that the Form of the Good of the Republic is also presupposed in the Timaeus and it plays the same role, and we should consider it as a first principle of platonic cosmology, independ- ent from the existence of Demiurge or even the Divine Paradigm (i.e. the model accord- ing to which the Demiurge creates the world). On first impression, this interpretation looks barely possible, since there is no direct refer- ence in the text to this particular Form, with the possible exception of what is said at Tim. 46c7-d1.3 In my opinion, this absence has to do ABSTRACT with specific purposes Timaeus serves, and not with the abandonment of the Good as a cause.
    [Show full text]
  • Plato's Meno: Knowledge Is Justified True Belief
    Plato’s Meno: Knowledge is Justified True Belief: This Socratic dialogue introduces two dominate themes in Western philosophy: 402 BC What counts as virtue and what counts as knowledge. Part 1: 70-86c: Part 2: 86d-end: Can Virtue Be Taught? Knowledge Search for a definition of “arete.” MENO’S CHALLENGE: “Opinion” vs. “Knowledge” WHAT IS “ARETE”? 70-79b STRATEGY: : 80d-e 1. may be useful as knowledge, Socrates asks Meno for a formal definition of If you don’t know what “arete” is Socrates proposes that we first determine if virtue is a but often fails to stay in their “arete” for how can we know if arete can be already, you can’t even look for it, kind of knowledge. If it is, it can be taught. If virtue taught we don’t have a clear idea what it is. because if you don’t know what it place; must be tethered by All the examples of “arete” have something in is already, then even if you look, isn’t knowledge, then it can’t be taught (86d-e) anamnesis: certain common: The “essence” or “form” of “arete.” you will not know when you’ve [recognize that virtue is used interchangeably found it. Argument # 1: Virtue can be taught: (87-89c); knowledge is innate & recollected by the soul through with “the good”]. Argument # 2: Virtue is not knowledge (89c): KNOWLEDGE IS proper inquiry. RECOLLECTION: 70a: Can virtue be taught? 71b; Must know what virtue is before Everyone agrees that there are teachers for certain knowing its qualities. What is virtue? Meno responds: (71e-72a).
    [Show full text]
  • Albert Camus and Absurd Communication: from Undecidability to Übercommunication
    Albert Camus and Absurd Communication: From Undecidability to Übercommunication by Jorge Lizarzaburu B.A., USFQ, 2010 A thesis submitted to the Faculty of the Graduate School of the University of Colorado in partial fulfillment of the requirement for the degree of Master of Arts Department of Communication 2012 This thesis entitled: Albert Camus and Absurd Communication: From Undecidability to Übercommunication written by Jorge M. Lizarzaburu has been approved for the Department of Communication Gerard Hauser Janice Peck Robert Craig Date 5/31/2012 The final copy of this thesis has been examined by the signatories, and we Find that both the content and the form meet acceptable presentation standards Of scholarly work in the above mentioned discipline iii Lizarzaburu, Jorge M. (M.A., Communication, Department of Communication) Albert Camus and Absurd Communication: From Undecidability to Übercommunication Thesis directed by professor Gerard Hauser Communication conceived as understanding is a normative telos among scholars in the field. Absurdity, in the work of Albert Camus, can provide us with a framework to go beyond communication understood as a binary (understanding and misunderstanding) and propose a new conception of communication as absurd. That is, it is an impossible task, however necessary thus we need to embrace its absurdity and value the effort itself as much as the result. Before getting into Camus’ arguments I explain the work of Friedrich Nietzsche to understand the French philosopher in more detail. I describe eternal recurrence and Übermensch as two concepts that can be related to communication as absurd. Then I explain Camus’ notion of absurdity using a Nietzschean lens.
    [Show full text]
  • Albert Camus' Dialogue with Nietzsche and Dostoevsky Sean Derek Illing Louisiana State University and Agricultural and Mechanical College, [email protected]
    Louisiana State University LSU Digital Commons LSU Doctoral Dissertations Graduate School 2014 Between nihilism and transcendence : Albert Camus' dialogue with Nietzsche and Dostoevsky Sean Derek Illing Louisiana State University and Agricultural and Mechanical College, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_dissertations Part of the Political Science Commons Recommended Citation Illing, Sean Derek, "Between nihilism and transcendence : Albert Camus' dialogue with Nietzsche and Dostoevsky" (2014). LSU Doctoral Dissertations. 1393. https://digitalcommons.lsu.edu/gradschool_dissertations/1393 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Graduate School at LSU Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in LSU Doctoral Dissertations by an authorized graduate school editor of LSU Digital Commons. For more information, please [email protected]. BETWEEN NIHILISM AND TRANSCENDENCE: ALBERT CAMUS’ DIALOGUE WITH NIETZSCHE AND DOSTOEVSKY A Dissertation Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of the Louisiana State University and Agricultural and Mechanical College in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in The Department of Political Science by Sean D. Illing B.A., Louisiana State University, 2007 M.A., University of West Florida, 2009 May 2014 ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS This dissertation is the product of many supportive individuals. I am especially grateful for Dr. Cecil Eubank’s guidance. As a teacher, one can do no better than Professor Eubanks. Although his Socratic glare can be terrifying, there is always love and wisdom in his instruction. It is no exaggeration to say that this work would not exist without his support. At every step, he helped me along as I struggled to articulate my thoughts.
    [Show full text]