Foundations of Mathematics.Pdf

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Foundations of Mathematics.Pdf Copyright c 1995{2000 by Stephen G. Simpson Foundations of Mathematics Stephen G. Simpson March 13, 2000 Department of Mathematics The Pennsylvania State University University Park, State College PA 16802 [email protected] This is a set of lecture notes for my course, Foundations of Mathematics I, offered as Mathematics 558 at the Pennsylvania State University, Spring 2000. Contents List of Figures iii Chapter 1. Computable Functions 1 1. Primitive Recursive Functions 1 2. The Ackermann Function 6 3. Computable Functions 7 4. Partial Recursive Functions 13 5. The Enumeration Theorem 14 6. Consequences of the Enumeration Theorem 18 7. Unsolvable Problems 20 8. The Recursion Theorem 24 9. The Arithmetical Hierarchy 25 Chapter 2. Undecidability of Arithmetic 29 1. Terms, Formulas, and Sentences 29 2. Arithmetical Definability 30 3. G¨odel Numbers of Formulas 35 Chapter 3. The Real Number System 37 1. Quantifier Elimination 37 2. Decidability of the Real Number System 42 Chapter 4. Informal Set Theory 43 1. Operations on Sets 43 2. Cardinal Numbers 45 3. Well-Orderings and Ordinal Numbers 47 4. Cardinal Numbers, Continued 51 5. Pure Well-Founded Sets 55 Chapter 5. Axiomatic Set Theory 60 1. The Language and Axioms of Set Theory 60 2. Models of Set Theory 63 3. Transitive Models and Inaccessible Cardinals 66 4. Constructible Sets 69 5. Forcing 72 Chapter 6. Topics in Set Theory 73 1. Stationary Sets 73 2. Large Cardinals 74 3. Ultrafilters and Ultraproducts 75 4. Measurable Cardinals 77 i CONTENTS ii 5. Ramsey's Theorem 77 Index 78 List of Figures 1 Types of Register Machine Instructions 7 2 An Addition Program 8 3 The Initial Functions 9 4 A Multiplication Program 10 5 Generalized Composition 11 6 Primitive Recursion 12 7 Minimization 14 8 A Program with Labeled Instructions 15 9 Parametrization 23 iii CHAPTER 1 Computable Functions We use N to denote the set of natural numbers, N = 0; 1; 2;::: : f g For k 1, the k-fold Cartesian product ≥ N N ×···× k is denoted Nk.Ak-place function| is a{z function} f : Nk N and is sometimes indicated with the lambda-notation, ! f = λx1 xk [ f(x1;:::;xk)]: ··· A number-theoretic function is a k-place function for some k 1. The purpose of this chapter is to define and study an important≥ class of number- theoretic functions, the recursive functions (sometimes called the computable func- tions). We begin with a certain subclass known as the primitive recursive functions. 1. Primitive Recursive Functions Loosely speaking, a recursion is any kind of inductive definition, and a primitive recursion is an especially straightforward kind of recursion, in which the value of a number-theoretic function at argument x + 1 is defined in terms of the value at argument x. For example, the factorial function λx [ x! ] is defined by the primitive recursion equations 0! = 1, (x +1)!=x!(x + 1). A number-theoretic function is said to be primitive recursive if it can be built up by means of primitive recursions. This concept is made precise in the following definition. Definition 1.1 (Primitive Recursive Functions). The class PR of primitive recursive functions is the smallest class C of number-theoretic functions having the following closure properties. 1. The constant zero function Z = λx [ 0 ] belongs to C. 2. The successor function S = λx [ x + 1 ] belongs to C. 3. For each k 1and1 i k, the projection function Pki = λx1 xk [ xi ] belongs to C≥. ≤ ≤ ··· 4. C is closed under generalized composition. This means that whenever the k-place functions λx1 xk [ g1(x1;:::;xk)];:::,λx1 xk [ gm(x1;:::;xk)] ··· ··· and the m-place function λy1 ym [ h(y1;:::;ym) ] all belong to C,then the k-place function ··· f = λx1 xk [ h(g1(x1;:::;xk);:::;gm(x1;:::;xk)) ] ··· 1 1. PRIMITIVE RECURSIVE FUNCTIONS 2 also belongs to C.Heref is defined by f(x1;:::;xk)=h(g1(x1;:::;xk);:::;gm(x1;:::;xk)) : 5. C is closed under primitive recursion. This means that whenever the k-place function λx1 xk [ g(x1;:::;xk)] andthe(k + 2)-place function ··· λyzx1 xk [ h(y;z;x1;:::;xk)] ··· belong to C, then the (k + 1)-place function λyx1 xk [ f(y;x1;:::;xk)] defined by ··· f(0;x1;:::;xk)=g(x1;:::;xk) f(y +1;x1;:::;xk)=h(y;f(y;x1;:::;xk);x1;:::;xk) also belongs to C. We now list some examples of primitive recursive functions. Examples 1.2. 1. The recursion equations x +0 = x x +(y +1) = (x + y)+1 show that the addition function λxy [ x + y ] is primitive recursive. 2. The recursion equations x 0=0 · x (y +1) = (x y)+x · · show that the multiplication function λxy [ x y ] is primitive recursive. 3. The recursion equations · x0 =1 xy+1 = xy x · show that the exponentiation function λxy [ xy ] is primitive recursive. 4. As already mentioned, the recursion equations 0! = 1 (x +1)! = x! (x +1) · show that the factorial function λx [ x! ] is primitive recursive. We now proceed to further enlarge our library of primitive recursive functions. First, the recursion equations P (0) = 0, P (x +1)=x show that the \predecessor" function x 1ifx>0, P (x)= − (0ifx =0 is primitive recursive. We can then obtain the truncated subtraction function x y if x y , x y = − ≥ −· (0ifx<y 1. PRIMITIVE RECURSIVE FUNCTIONS 3 using primitive recursion equations x 0=x, x (y +1)=P (x y). (Truncated −· −· −· subraction is useful because ordinary subtraction is not a function from N2 into N.) We shall also have use for x y =(x y)+(y x) j − j −· −· and α(x)=1 x.Notethat −· 0ifx>0, α(x)= (1ifx =0. The following exercise will become easy after we have developed a little more machinery. Exercise 1.3. Show that the Fibonacci function, defined by fib(0) = 0 ; fib(1) = 1 ; fib(x +2) = fib(x) + fib(x +1) is primitive recursive. (The first few values of this function are 0, 1, 1, 2, 3, 5, 8, 13, 21, 34, 55, ::: .) In addition to primitive recursive functions, we shall want to consider primitive recursive predicates. By a k-place predicate we mean a subset of Nk.IfR Nk is ⊆ a k-place predicate and x1;:::;xk are elements of N,wesaythatR(x1;:::;xk)is true if x1;:::;xk R,otherwisefalse.Anumber-theoretic predicate is a k-place predicateh for somei2k 1. ≥ Definition 1.4. A k-place predicate R Nk is said to be primitive recursive if its characteristic function ⊆ 1ifR(x1;:::;xk)istrue χR(x1;:::;xk)= (0ifR(x1;:::;xk)isfalse is primitive recursive. For example, the 2-place predicates x = y and x<yare primitive recursive, since χ=(x; y)=α( x y )andχ<(x; y)=α(α(y x)). j − j −· Lemma 1.5 (Boolean Connectives). If P and Q are primitive recursive predi- cates, then so are P , P Q,andP Q.(Here , ,and denote negation, conjunction, and (nonexclusive): ^ disjunction,_ respectively.): ^ _ Proof. We have χ P = α(χP )andχP Q = χP χQ.Also : ^ · χP Q = α(α(χP ) α(χQ)) _ · since P Q (( P ) ( Q)) (de Morgan's law). _ ≡ : : ^ : Lemma 1.6 (Iterated Sums and Products). If f(x; y; z1;:::;zk) is a primitive recursive function, then so are y 1 − g(y;z1;:::;zk)= f(x; y; z1;:::;zk)(=0ify =0) x=0 X 1. PRIMITIVE RECURSIVE FUNCTIONS 4 and y 1 − h(y;z1;:::;zk)= f(x; y; z1;:::;zk)(=1ify =0): x=0 Y Proof. We have g(y;z1;:::;zk)=g∗(y;y;z1;:::;zk)where w 1 − g∗(w; y; z1;:::;zk)= f(x; y; z1;:::;zk) : x=0 X The recursion equations g∗(0;y;z1;:::;zk)=0 g∗(w +1;y;z1;:::;zk)=g∗(w; y; z1;:::;zk)+f(w; y; z1;:::;zk) show that g∗ is primitive recursive, hence g is primitive recursive. The treatment of h is similar. Lemma 1.7 (Finite Conjuction and Disjunction). If R(x; y; z1;:::;zk) is a primitive recursive predicate, then so are y 1 − P (y;z1;:::;zk) R(x; y; z1;:::;zk) ≡ x=0 ^ and y 1 − Q(y;z1;:::;zk) R(x; y; z1;:::;zk) : ≡ x=0 _ Proof. We have y 1 − χP (y;z1;:::;zk)= χR(x; y; z1;:::;zk) x=0 Y and y 1 − χQ(y;z1;:::;zk)=α α(χR(x; y; z1;:::;zk)) x=0 ! Y so our result follows from the previous lemma. y 1 y 1 Note that x−=0 and x−=0 can be paraphrased as \for all x in the range 0 x<y" and \there exists x in the range 0 x<y", respectively. These operators≤ are sometimesV called boundedW quantifiers. ≤ The above lemmas make it easy to show that many familiar predicates are primitive recursive. For example, the set (i.e., 1-place predicate) of prime numbers is primitive recursive, since Prime (x) x is a prime number ≡ x>1 (x = u v u>1 v>1) : : ≡ ^ u<x v<x · ^ ^ _ _ Similarly, the following lemma can be used to show that many familiar functions are primitive recursive. 1. PRIMITIVE RECURSIVE FUNCTIONS 5 Lemma 1.8 (Bounded Least Number Operator). If R(x; y; z1;:::;zk)isaprim- itive recursive predicate, then the function least x<ysuch that R(x; y; z1;:::;zk)holds, f(y;z1;:::;zk)=8 if such x exists , <>y otherwise is primitive recursive. :> Proof. We have y 1 x 1 − − f(y;z1;:::;zk)= x χR(x; y; z1;:::;zk) α(χR(w; y; z1;:::;zk)) · · x=0 w=0 ! X Y y 1 − + y α(χR(x; y; z1;:::;zk)) ; · x=0 Y so f is primitive recursive.
Recommended publications
  • The Polynomial Hierarchy
    ij 'I '""T', :J[_ ';(" THE POLYNOMIAL HIERARCHY Although the complexity classes we shall study now are in one sense byproducts of our definition of NP, they have a remarkable life of their own. 17.1 OPTIMIZATION PROBLEMS Optimization problems have not been classified in a satisfactory way within the theory of P and NP; it is these problems that motivate the immediate extensions of this theory beyond NP. Let us take the traveling salesman problem as our working example. In the problem TSP we are given the distance matrix of a set of cities; we want to find the shortest tour of the cities. We have studied the complexity of the TSP within the framework of P and NP only indirectly: We defined the decision version TSP (D), and proved it NP-complete (corollary to Theorem 9.7). For the purpose of understanding better the complexity of the traveling salesman problem, we now introduce two more variants. EXACT TSP: Given a distance matrix and an integer B, is the length of the shortest tour equal to B? Also, TSP COST: Given a distance matrix, compute the length of the shortest tour. The four variants can be ordered in "increasing complexity" as follows: TSP (D); EXACTTSP; TSP COST; TSP. Each problem in this progression can be reduced to the next. For the last three problems this is trivial; for the first two one has to notice that the reduction in 411 j ;1 17.1 Optimization Problems 413 I 412 Chapter 17: THE POLYNOMIALHIERARCHY the corollary to Theorem 9.7 proving that TSP (D) is NP-complete can be used with DP.
    [Show full text]
  • Complexity Theory
    Complexity Theory Course Notes Sebastiaan A. Terwijn Radboud University Nijmegen Department of Mathematics P.O. Box 9010 6500 GL Nijmegen the Netherlands [email protected] Copyright c 2010 by Sebastiaan A. Terwijn Version: December 2017 ii Contents 1 Introduction 1 1.1 Complexity theory . .1 1.2 Preliminaries . .1 1.3 Turing machines . .2 1.4 Big O and small o .........................3 1.5 Logic . .3 1.6 Number theory . .4 1.7 Exercises . .5 2 Basics 6 2.1 Time and space bounds . .6 2.2 Inclusions between classes . .7 2.3 Hierarchy theorems . .8 2.4 Central complexity classes . 10 2.5 Problems from logic, algebra, and graph theory . 11 2.6 The Immerman-Szelepcs´enyi Theorem . 12 2.7 Exercises . 14 3 Reductions and completeness 16 3.1 Many-one reductions . 16 3.2 NP-complete problems . 18 3.3 More decision problems from logic . 19 3.4 Completeness of Hamilton path and TSP . 22 3.5 Exercises . 24 4 Relativized computation and the polynomial hierarchy 27 4.1 Relativized computation . 27 4.2 The Polynomial Hierarchy . 28 4.3 Relativization . 31 4.4 Exercises . 32 iii 5 Diagonalization 34 5.1 The Halting Problem . 34 5.2 Intermediate sets . 34 5.3 Oracle separations . 36 5.4 Many-one versus Turing reductions . 38 5.5 Sparse sets . 38 5.6 The Gap Theorem . 40 5.7 The Speed-Up Theorem . 41 5.8 Exercises . 43 6 Randomized computation 45 6.1 Probabilistic classes . 45 6.2 More about BPP . 48 6.3 The classes RP and ZPP .
    [Show full text]
  • Syllabus Computability Theory
    Syllabus Computability Theory Sebastiaan A. Terwijn Institute for Discrete Mathematics and Geometry Technical University of Vienna Wiedner Hauptstrasse 8–10/E104 A-1040 Vienna, Austria [email protected] Copyright c 2004 by Sebastiaan A. Terwijn version: 2020 Cover picture and above close-up: Sunflower drawing by Alan Turing, c copyright by University of Southampton and King’s College Cambridge 2002, 2003. iii Emil Post (1897–1954) Alonzo Church (1903–1995) Kurt G¨odel (1906–1978) Stephen Cole Kleene Alan Turing (1912–1954) (1909–1994) Contents 1 Introduction 1 1.1 Preliminaries ................................ 2 2 Basic concepts 3 2.1 Algorithms ................................. 3 2.2 Recursion .................................. 4 2.2.1 Theprimitiverecursivefunctions . 4 2.2.2 Therecursivefunctions . 5 2.3 Turingmachines .............................. 6 2.4 Arithmetization............................... 10 2.4.1 Codingfunctions .......................... 10 2.4.2 Thenormalformtheorem . 11 2.4.3 The basic equivalence and Church’s thesis . 13 2.4.4 Canonicalcodingoffinitesets. 15 2.5 Exercises .................................. 15 3 Computable and computably enumerable sets 19 3.1 Diagonalization............................... 19 3.2 Computablyenumerablesets . 19 3.3 Undecidablesets .............................. 22 3.4 Uniformity ................................. 24 3.5 Many-onereducibility ........................... 25 3.6 Simplesets ................................. 26 3.7 Therecursiontheorem ........................... 28 3.8 Exercises
    [Show full text]
  • Logic and Complexity
    o| f\ Richard Lassaigne and Michel de Rougemont Logic and Complexity Springer Contents Introduction Part 1. Basic model theory and computability 3 Chapter 1. Prepositional logic 5 1.1. Propositional language 5 1.1.1. Construction of formulas 5 1.1.2. Proof by induction 7 1.1.3. Decomposition of a formula 7 1.2. Semantics 9 1.2.1. Tautologies. Equivalent formulas 10 1.2.2. Logical consequence 11 1.2.3. Value of a formula and substitution 11 1.2.4. Complete systems of connectives 15 1.3. Normal forms 15 1.3.1. Disjunctive and conjunctive normal forms 15 1.3.2. Functions associated to formulas 16 1.3.3. Transformation methods 17 1.3.4. Clausal form 19 1.3.5. OBDD: Ordered Binary Decision Diagrams 20 1.4. Exercises 23 Chapter 2. Deduction systems 25 2.1. Examples of tableaux 25 2.2. Tableaux method 27 2.2.1. Trees 28 2.2.2. Construction of tableaux 29 2.2.3. Development and closure 30 2.3. Completeness theorem 31 2.3.1. Provable formulas 31 2.3.2. Soundness 31 2.3.3. Completeness 32 2.4. Natural deduction 33 2.5. Compactness theorem 36 2.6. Exercices 38 vi CONTENTS Chapter 3. First-order logic 41 3.1. First-order languages 41 3.1.1. Construction of terms 42 3.1.2. Construction of formulas 43 3.1.3. Free and bound variables 44 3.2. Semantics 45 3.2.1. Structures and languages 45 3.2.2. Structures and satisfaction of formulas 46 3.2.3.
    [Show full text]
  • On the Weakness of Sharply Bounded Polynomial Induction
    On the Weakness of Sharply Bounded Polynomial Induction Jan Johannsen Friedrich-Alexander-Universit¨at Erlangen-N¨urnberg May 4, 1994 Abstract 0 We shall show that if the theory S2 of sharply bounded polynomial induction is extended 0 by symbols for certain functions and their defining axioms, it is still far weaker than T2 , which has ordinary sharply bounded induction. Furthermore, we show that this extended 0 b 0 system S2+ cannot Σ1-define every function in AC , the class of functions computable by polynomial size constant depth circuits. 1 Introduction i i The theory S2 of bounded arithmetic and its fragments S2 and T2 (i ≥ 0) were defined in [Bu]. The language of these theories comprises the usual language of arithmetic plus additional 1 |x|·|y| symbols for the functions ⌊ 2 x⌋, |x| := ⌈log2(x + 1)⌉ and x#y := 2 . Quantifiers of the form ∀x≤t , ∃x≤t are called bounded quantifiers. If the bounding term t is furthermore of the form b b |s|, the quantifier is called sharply bounded. The classes Σi and Πi of the bounded arithmetic hierarchy are defined in analogy to the classes of the usual arithmetical hierarchy, where the i counts alternations of bounded quantifiers, ignoring the sharply bounded quantifiers. i S2 is axiomatized by a finite set of open axioms (called BASIC) plus the schema of poly- b nomial induction (PIND) for Σi -formulae ϕ: 1 ϕ(0) ∧ ∀x ( ϕ(⌊ x⌋) → ϕ(x) ) → ∀x ϕ(x) 2 i b T2 is the same with the ordinary induction scheme for Σi -formulae replacing PIND.
    [Show full text]
  • An Introduction to Computability Theory
    AN INTRODUCTION TO COMPUTABILITY THEORY CINDY CHUNG Abstract. This paper will give an introduction to the fundamentals of com- putability theory. Based on Robert Soare's textbook, The Art of Turing Computability: Theory and Applications, we examine concepts including the Halting problem, properties of Turing jumps and degrees, and Post's Theo- rem.1 In the paper, we will assume the reader has a conceptual understanding of computer programs. Contents 1. Basic Computability 1 2. The Halting Problem 2 3. Post's Theorem: Jumps and Quantifiers 3 3.1. Arithmetical Hierarchy 3 3.2. Degrees and Jumps 4 3.3. The Zero-Jump, 00 5 3.4. Post's Theorem 5 Acknowledgments 8 References 8 1. Basic Computability Definition 1.1. An algorithm is a procedure capable of being carried out by a computer program. It accepts various forms of numerical inputs including numbers and finite strings of numbers. Computability theory is a branch of mathematical logic that focuses on algo- rithms, formally known in this area as computable functions, and studies the degree, or level of computability that can be attributed to various sets (these concepts will be formally defined and elaborated upon below). This field was founded in the 1930s by many mathematicians including the logicians: Alan Turing, Stephen Kleene, Alonzo Church, and Emil Post. Turing first pioneered computability theory when he introduced the fundamental concept of the a-machine which is now known as the Turing machine (this concept will be intuitively defined below) in his 1936 pa- per, On computable numbers, with an application to the Entscheidungsproblem[7].
    [Show full text]
  • LANDSCAPE of COMPUTATIONAL COMPLEXITY Spring 2008 State University of New York at Buffalo Department of Computer Science & Engineering Mustafa M
    LANDSCAPE OF COMPUTATIONAL COMPLEXITY Spring 2008 State University of New York at Buffalo Department of Computer Science & Engineering Mustafa M. Faramawi, MBA Dr. Kenneth W. Regan A complete language for EXPSPACE: PIM, “Polynomial Ideal Arithmetical Hierarchy (AH) Membership”—the simplest natural completeness level that is known PIM not to have polynomial‐size circuits. TOT = {M : M is total, K(2) TOT e e ∑n Πn i.e. halts for all inputs} EXPSPACE Succinct 3SAT Unknown ∑2 Π2 but Commonly Believed: RECRE L ≠ NL …………………….. L ≠ PH NEXP co‐NEXP = ∃∀.REC = ∀∃.REC P ≠ NP ∩ co‐NP ……… P ≠ PSPACE nxn Chess p p K D NP ≠ ∑ 2 ∩Π 2 ……… NP ≠ EXP D = {Turing machines M : EXP e Best Known Separations: Me does not accept e} = RE co‐RE the complement of K. AC0 ⊂ ACC0 ⊂ PP, also TC0 ⊂ PP QBF REC (“Diagonal Language”) For any fixed k, NC1 ⊂ PSPACE, …, NL ⊂ PSPACE = ∃.REC = ∀.REC there is a PSPACE problem in this P ⊂ EXP, NP ⊂ NEXP BQP: Bounded‐Error Quantum intersection that PSPACE ⊂ EXPSPACE Polynomial Time. Believed larger can NOT be Polynomial Hierarchy (PH) than P since it has FACTORING, solved by circuits p p k but not believed to contain NP. of size O(n ) ∑ 2 Π 2 L WS5 p p ∑ 2 Π 2 The levels of AH and poly. poly. BPP: Bounded‐Error Probabilistic TAUT = ∃∀ P = ∀∃ P SAT Polynomial Time. Many believe BPP = P. NC1 PH are analogous, NLIN except that we believe NP co‐NP 0 NP ∩ co‐NP ≠ P and NTIME [n2] TC QBF PARITY ∑p ∩Πp NP PP Probabilistic NP FACT 2 2 ≠ P , which NP ACC0 stand in contrast to P PSPACE Polynomial Time MAJ‐SAT CVP RE ∩ co‐RE = REC and 0 AC RE P P ∑2 ∩Π2 = REC GAP NP co‐NP REG NL poly 0 0 ∃ .
    [Show full text]
  • Contributions to the Study of Resource-Bounded Measure
    Contributions to the Study of ResourceBounded Measure Elvira Mayordomo Camara Barcelona abril de Contributions to the Study of ResourceBounded Measure Tesis do ctoral presentada en el Departament de Llenguatges i Sistemes Informatics de la Universitat Politecnica de Catalunya para optar al grado de Do ctora en Ciencias Matematicas por Elvira Mayordomo Camara Dirigida p or el do ctor Jose Luis Balcazar Navarro Barcelona abril de This dissertation was presented on June st in the Departament de Llenguatges i Sistemes Informatics Universitat Politecnica de Catalunya The committee was formed by the following members Prof Ronald V Bo ok University of California at Santa Barbara Prof Ricard Gavalda Universitat Politecnica de Catalunya Prof Mario Ro drguez Universidad Complutense de Madrid Prof Marta Sanz Universitat Central de Barcelona Prof Jacob o Toran Universitat Politecnica de Catalunya Acknowledgements Iwant to thank sp ecially two p eople Jose Luis Balcazar and Jack Lutz Without their help and encouragement this dissertation would never have b een written Jose Luis Balcazar was my advisor and taughtmemostofwhatIknow ab out Structural Complexity showing me with his example how to do research I visited Jack Lutz in Iowa State University in several o ccasions from His patience and enthusiasm in explaining to me the intuition behind his theory and his numerous ideas were the starting p ointofmostoftheresults in this dissertation Several coauthors have collab orated in the publications included in the dierent chapters Jack Lutz Steven
    [Show full text]
  • On Infinite Variants of NP-Complete Problems
    Journal of Computer and System Sciences SS1432 journal of computer and system sciences 53, 180193 (1996) article no. 0060 View metadata, citation and similarTaking papers at core.ac.uk It to the Limit: On Infinite Variants brought to you by CORE of NP-Complete Problems provided by Elsevier - Publisher Connector Tirza Hirst and David Harel* Department of Applied Mathematics H Computer Science, The Weizmann Institute of Science, Rehovot 76100, Israel Received November 1, 1993 We first set up a general way of obtaining infinite versions We define infinite, recursive versions of NP optimization problems. of NP maximization and minimization problems. If P is the For example, MAX CLIQUE becomes the question of whether a recursive problem that asks for a maximum by graph contains an infinite clique. The present paper was motivated by trying to understand what makes some NP problems highly max |[wÄ : A<,(wÄ , S)]|, undecidable in the infinite case, while others remain on low levels of S the arithmetical hierarchy. We prove two results; one enables using knowledge about the infinite case to yield implications to the finite where ,(wÄ , S) is first-order and A is a finite structure (say, case, and the other enables implications in the other direction. a graph), we define P as the problem that asks whether Moreover, taken together, the two results provide a method for proving there is an S, such that the set [wÄ : A<,(w, S)] is infinite, (finitary) problems to be outside the syntactic class MAX NP, and, where A is an infinite recursive structure. Thus, for example, hence, outside MAX SNP too, by showing that their infinite versions are 1 Max Clique becomes the question of whether a recursive 71-complete.
    [Show full text]
  • Computational Complexity: a Modern Approach PDF Book
    COMPUTATIONAL COMPLEXITY: A MODERN APPROACH PDF, EPUB, EBOOK Sanjeev Arora,Boaz Barak | 594 pages | 16 Jun 2009 | CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS | 9780521424264 | English | Cambridge, United Kingdom Computational Complexity: A Modern Approach PDF Book Miller; J. The polynomial hierarchy and alternations; 6. This is a very comprehensive and detailed book on computational complexity. Circuit lower bounds; Examples and solved exercises accompany key definitions. Computational complexity: A conceptual perspective. Redirected from Computational complexities. Refresh and try again. Brand new Book. The theory formalizes this intuition, by introducing mathematical models of computation to study these problems and quantifying their computational complexity , i. In other words, one considers that the computation is done simultaneously on as many identical processors as needed, and the non-deterministic computation time is the time spent by the first processor that finishes the computation. Foundations of Cryptography by Oded Goldreich - Cambridge University Press The book gives the mathematical underpinnings for cryptography; this includes one-way functions, pseudorandom generators, and zero-knowledge proofs. If one knows an upper bound on the size of the binary representation of the numbers that occur during a computation, the time complexity is generally the product of the arithmetic complexity by a constant factor. Jason rated it it was amazing Aug 28, Seller Inventory bc0bebcaa63d3c. Lewis Cawthorne rated it really liked it Dec 23, Polynomial hierarchy Exponential hierarchy Grzegorczyk hierarchy Arithmetical hierarchy Boolean hierarchy. Convert currency. Convert currency. Familiarity with discrete mathematics and probability will be assumed. The formal language associated with this decision problem is then the set of all connected graphs — to obtain a precise definition of this language, one has to decide how graphs are encoded as binary strings.
    [Show full text]
  • Computability Theory of Hyperarithmetical Sets
    WESTFALISCHE¨ WILHELMS-UNIVERSITAT¨ MUNSTER¨ INSTITUT FUR¨ MATHEMATISCHE LOGIK UND GRUNDLAGENFORSCHUNG Computability Theory of Hyperarithmetical Sets Lecture by Wolfram Pohlers Summer–Term 1996 Typeset by Martina Pfeifer Preface This text contains the somewhat extended material of a series of lectures given at the University of M¨unster. The aim of the course is to give an introduction to “higher” computability theory and to provide background material for the following courses in proof theory. The prerequisites for the course are some basic facts about computable functions and mathe- matical logic. Some emphasis has been put on the notion of generalized inductive definitions. Whenever it seemed to be opportune we tried to obtain “classical” results by using generalized inductive definitions. I am indebted to Dipl. Math. INGO LEPPER for the revising and supplementing the original text. M¨unster, September 1999 WOLFRAM POHLERS 2 Contents Contents 1 Computable Functionals and Relations ....................... 5 1.1FunctionalsandRelations................................ 5 1.2TheNormal–formTheorem............................... 10 1.3 Computability relativized . ............................... 13 2 Degrees ......................................... 15 2.1 m–Degrees....................................... 15 2.2 TURING–Reducibility . ............................... 16 2.3 TURING–Degrees.................................... 18 3 The Arithmetical Hierarchy ............................. 25 3.1TheJumpoperatorrevisited.............................. 25
    [Show full text]
  • Arithmetical Hierarchy
    Arithmetical Hierarchy Klaus Sutner Carnegie Mellon University 60-arith-hier 2017/12/15 23:18 1 The Turing Jump Arithmetical Hierarchy Definability Formal Systems Recall: Oracles 3 We can attach an orcale to a Turing machine without changing the basic theory. fegA eth function computable with A A A We = domfeg eth r.e. set with A The constructions are verbatim the same. For example, a universal Turing machine turns into a universal Turing machine plus oracle. The Use Principle 4 We continue to confuse a set A ⊆ N with its characteristic function. For any n write A n for the following finite approximation to the characteristic function: ( A(z) if z < n, (A n)(z) ' " otherwise. For any such function α write α < A if α = A n for some n. Then fegA(x) = y () 9 α < A fegα(x) = y with the understanding that the computation on the right never asks the oracle any questions outside of its domain. Of course, a divergent computation may use the oracle infinitely often. Generalized Halting 5 Definition Let A ⊆ N. The (Turing) jump of A is defined as A0 = KA = f e j fegA(e) # g So ;0 = K; = K is just the ordinary Halting set. The nth jump A(n) is obtained by iterating the jump n times. Jump Properties 6 Let A; B ⊆ N. Theorem A0 is r.e. in A. A0 is not Turing reducible to A. 0 B is r.e. in A iff B ≤m A . Proof. The first two parts are verbatim re-runs of the oracle-free argument.
    [Show full text]