Long-Distance Paradox and the Hybrid Nature of Language Lorenzo G

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Long-Distance Paradox and the Hybrid Nature of Language Lorenzo G 23/8/2018 e.Proofing Long-Distance Paradox and the Hybrid Nature of Language Lorenzo G. Long-Distance Paradox and the Hybrid Nature of Language ✉ Guillermo Lorenzo, 1 Phone 00­34­985104653 provided by Repositorio Institucional de la Universidad de Oviedo View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk CORE Email glorbroughte to you byn [email protected] 1 Department of Spanish Philology / Linguistics, Faculty of Humanities, University of Oviedo, C/ Amparo Pedregal s/n, E­ 33011 Oviedo, Spain Received: 7 February 2018 / Accepted: 18 August 2018 Abstract Non­adjacent or long­distance dependencies (LDDs) are routinely considered to be a distinctive trait of language, which purportedly locates it higher than other sequentially organized signal systems in terms of structural complexity. This paper argues that particular languages display specific resources (e.g. non­interpretive morphological agreement paradigms) that help the brain system responsible for dealing with LDDs to develop the capacity of acquiring and processing expressions with such a human­typical degree of computational complexity. Independently obtained naturalistic data is discussed and put to the service of the idea that the above­mentioned resources exert their developmental role from the outside, but in compliance with other internal resources, ultimately compounding an integrated developmental system. Parallels with other human and nonhuman developmental phenomena are explored, which point to the conclusion that the developmental system of concern can be assimilated to cases currently been conceptualized as ‘cue­ response systems’ or ‘developmental hybrids’ within the ecological­ developmental paradigm in theoretical biology. Such a conclusion is used to support the idea that both current externalist and internalist concepts fall short of a correct characterization of language. Keywords Externalism http://eproofing.springer.com/journals_v2/printpage.php?token=FHrh5saHR9SPfdCyjnNGopism5m0Y0rDSKaA-qHVPMg 1/27 23/8/2018 e.Proofing Internalism Eco­devo biology Cue­response mechanisms Developmental hybrids Introduction Long­distance—or non­adjacent—dependencies (LDDs) are pervasive in language, manifest in such diverse phenomena as discontinuous phrases across embedded constituents (1a), pronominal and anaphoric co­reference (1b), wh­ word/gap or NP/gap connections in relative clauses (1c), interrogative (1d), and passive constructions (1e), etc. (Zushi 2013)1: (1) a. The man was saying [that his wife had been shot] with a desperate voice b. The woman1 that you2 visited is worried about herself1/your2 sons c. The man who1 she visited t1 yesterday is completely out of control d. Who1 did you visited t1 last night? e. She1 was declared guilty t1 In many accounts, LDDs are taken to be the hallmark of language uniqueness, as compared to the cognitive makeup of nonhuman species (Corballis 2011), or even in the context of human cognition (Hauser et al. 2002). The rationale for this tenet is that LDDs reveal that the powers the computational the powers of the computational resources of humans or language exceed anything hitherto known in other species or abilities. To begin with, the capacity for nested embedding— as in (1a), which illustrates the kind of recursion customarily associated to context­freeness, is widely believed to be lacking in nonhuman cognition—see below. Among LDDs, special mention should be given to the family of cases routinely referred to as ‘agreement’ phenomena, in which an item adopts a morphological appearance that mirrors the feature composition of another designated one. Agreement covers, from an interlinguistic point of view, an extremely wide range of related phenomena, which may be epitomized by the relatively simple case of subject agreement in English. In this language, as in many others, it is common for the verb and the agreeing subject to appear as adjacent units in the linear http://eproofing.springer.com/journals_v2/printpage.php?token=FHrh5saHR9SPfdCyjnNGopism5m0Y0rDSKaA-qHVPMg 2/27 23/8/2018 e.Proofing order of utterances—as in (2a); however, (2b) clearly illustrates the LDD character of the relation: (2) a. The girl1 wants1 to know who is afraid of her b. The girl1 who is afraid of the boy wants1 to know who is afraid of her Crucially, note that in (2b) there is a matching item that is closer (actually, adjacent) to the relevant verb—namely, the boy, which however does not qualify as a better candidate for agreement than the six­item­distant correct one—the girl. Note, also, that (2b) further illustrates that different agreement relations may concur and interfere in a single utterance—namely, the girl is also the semantic controller of the abstract subject of to know, as well as the antecedent of the pronoun her. In each of these different instances of LDD, the second relatum is increasingly more distant from the first one, without hindering the interpretation of the whole utterance. These kinds of observations have served to rank natural language in a relatively high position within the standard Chomsky hierarchy of computational complexity (Chomsky 1956): Namely, an area above the context­free recursive languages—i.e. those that accept discontinuous dependencies created by embedding segments within larger segments, since natural language accepts dependencies that hold across segments belonging to different levels of embedding. (3a) offers a suitable illustration, which is shown as an abstract pattern in (3b)—different capital letters represent that units belong to different embedded segments: (3) a. The girl1/3 who said that the boy2 hated her3 loves1 him2 b. X1/3 … Y … Z2 … Z3 … X1 X2 The reason why context­freeness is customarily seen as critical in the literature on comparative cognition is the more or less consensual claim that no clear cases of bona fide structural embedding have to date been found in any example of nonhuman sequential behavior whatsoever, while human language appears to be situated even some steps ahead of such a level of computational complexity. Context freeness thus represents a kind of chasm between human and nonhuman cognition (see Fitch and Hauser 2004; van Heijningen et al. 2009; Beckers et al. 2012). http://eproofing.springer.com/journals_v2/printpage.php?token=FHrh5saHR9SPfdCyjnNGopism5m0Y0rDSKaA-qHVPMg 3/27 23/8/2018 e.Proofing Agreement dependencies are worth special mention in this context because, unlike other kinds of LDDs, they exhibit the peculiar trait of not being interpretable, in the sense that they make no specific contribution to the compositional meaning of the sentence (Chomsky 1995). Rather, agreement merely involves associating some morphological material to an item, which mirrors the (interpretable) feature composition of another (potentially distant) item—e.g. –s in not required to contribute the meaning ‘subject, 3rd person, singular’ in (2a), which is already contributed by the constituent the girl itself. For this reason, it is also commonly said that agreement is an asymmetric relation, since it is the verb that agrees with the subject, but not the other way around; in other words, the subject is a meaningful constituent, but the subject­ agreement bearer item affixed to the verb is meaningless. The fact that agreement features are in many cases uninterpretable replicas of interpretable ones is certainly confounding (Adger and Svenonius 2011). Some features function both within interpretable and uninterpretable bundles in many languages; moreover, homologues of certain features may be interpretable in some languages and uninterpretable in some others (Van Valin 2003). In any event, the kind of features and morphology that I am interested in here are those displayed in LDDs without any conceptual import. Such property raises an important question, to which no clear, consensual answer exists to date: Why are agreement relations so pervasive, if they do not appear to make any clear meaningful contribution to utterances? This is one of the main issues on which this paper will focus. I shall specifically defend that neither cognitive/functionalist approaches (Barlow and Ferguson 1988) or formalist/generativist counterparts (Boeckx 2006) have hitherto provided an account of the ultimate raison d’être of agreement systems in natural language. In a nutshell, functionalist/cognitive approaches try to make sense of agreement by ascribing some communicative role to its bearers (e.g. fixing discourse referents, creating noise­preventing redundancies, etc.), while formal/generativist approaches conceptualize it as a kind of imperfection that the language system needs to get rid of when processing expressions. The alternative that I shall suggest is a developmental one, which is not incompatible with prior suggestions along the lines of those referred to above, but which is more basic and closer to a ‘first cause’ for the existence of such linguistic entities. Another point of interest of this paper has to do with a further characteristic of agreement relations, which illustrates an aspect of language in a way that other kinds of LDDs do not, or, at least, not as straightforwardly. The ways in which agreement relations instantiate in different languages are manifold and sensitive to a very wide range of criteria. To cite a few, agreement may be sensitive to a http://eproofing.springer.com/journals_v2/printpage.php?token=FHrh5saHR9SPfdCyjnNGopism5m0Y0rDSKaA-qHVPMg 4/27 23/8/2018 e.Proofing particular syntactic relation—e.g. subject agreement, as in (2) above; or sensitive to a particular morphological feature—e.g. number agreement, as in (4), where the affix may indistinctly refer to the subject or the object, which must be a plural one; or sensitive to complex combinations thereof—as in (5), where the affix responds to a person/number hierarchy (1st/2nd > 3rd pl. > 3rd sg.), but only when the agent is focused and the transitive verb turned into an intransitive: (4) Georgian (from Nevins 2011) g­xedav­t. 2obj­saw­pl ‘I saw you all; we saw you all; he saw you all; we saw you’ (indistinctly) (5) Quichean (from Preminger 2014) a. ja yïn x­in­ax­an ri achinfoc me asp­1sg.abs­hear­af the man ‘It was me that heard the man’ b.
Recommended publications
  • Handedness Development: a Model for Investigating the Development of Hemispheric Specialization and Interhemispheric Coordination
    S S symmetry Review Handedness Development: A Model for Investigating the Development of Hemispheric Specialization and Interhemispheric Coordination George F. Michel Psychology Department, University of North Carolina Greensboro, P.O. Box 26170, Greensboro, NC 27402-6170, USA; [email protected] Abstract: The author presents his perspective on the character of science, development, and handed- ness and relates these to his investigations of the early development of handedness. After presenting some ideas on what hemispheric specialization of function might mean for neural processing and how handedness should be assessed, the neuroscience of control of the arms/hands and interhemi- spheric communication and coordination are examined for how developmental processes can affect these mechanisms. The author’s work on the development of early handedness is reviewed and placed within a context of cascading events in which different forms of handedness emerge from earlier forms but not in a deterministic manner. This approach supports a continuous rather than categorical distribution of handedness and accounts for the predominance of right-handedness while maintaining a minority of left-handedness. Finally, the relation of the development of handedness to the development of several language and cognitive skills is examined. Keywords: development; handedness; lateralization; hemispheric specialization; interhemispheric Citation: Michel, G.F. Handedness coordination; embodiment Development: A Model for Investigating the Development of Hemispheric Specialization and Interhemispheric Coordination. 1. Introduction Symmetry 2021, 13, 992. https:// There is a general consensus among neuroscientists that the human left and right doi.org/10.3390/sym13060992 hemispheres of the brain have different perceptual, motor, emotional, and cognitive func- tions with the most distinctive difference of a left-hemisphere predominance in praxis (e.g., Academic Editor: Gillian Forrester gestures and tool use) and language (speech and comprehension) functions [1].
    [Show full text]
  • Evolutionary Cognitive Neuroscience Cognitive Neuroscience Michael S
    MD DALIM #870693 9/24/06 GREEN PURPLE Evolutionary Cognitive Neuroscience Cognitive Neuroscience Michael S. Gazzaniga, editor Gary Lynch, Synapses, Circuits, and the Beginning of Memory Barry E. Stein and M. Alex Meredith, The Merging of the Senses Richard B. Ivry and Lynn C. Robertson, The Two Sides of Perception Steven J. Luck, An Introduction to the Event-Related Potential Technique Roberto Cabeza and Alan Kingstone, eds., Handbook of Functional Neuroimaging of Cognition Carl Senior, Tamara Russell, and Michael S. Gazzaniga, eds., Methods in Mind Steven M. Platek, Julian Paul Keenan, and Todd K. Shackelford, eds., Evolutionary Cognitive Neuroscience Evolutionary Cognitive Neuroscience Edited by Steven M. Platek, Julian Paul Keenan, and Todd K. Shackelford The MIT Press Cambridge, Massachusetts London, England © 2007 Massachusetts Institute of Technology All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced in any form by any electronic or mechanical means (including photocopying, recording, or informa- tion storage and retrieval) without permission in writing from the publisher. MIT Press books may be purchased at special quantity discounts for business or sales promotional use. For information, please email special_sales@mitpress. mit.edu or write to Special Sales Department, The MIT Press, 55 Hayward Street, Cambridge, MA 02142. This book printed and bound in the United States of America. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Evolutionary cognitive neuroscience / edited by Steven M. Platek, Julian Paul Keenan, and Todd K. Shackelford. p. cm.—(Cognitive neuroscience) Includes bibliographical references and index. ISBN 13: 978-0-262-16241-8 ISBN 10: 0-262-16241-5 1. Cognitive neuroscience. 2.
    [Show full text]
  • A Differential–Developmental Model (DDM): Mental Speed, Attention Lapses, and General Intelligence (G)
    Commentary A Differential–Developmental Model (DDM): Mental Speed, Attention Lapses, and General Intelligence (g) Thomas R. Coyle Department of Psychology, University of Texas at San Antonio, San Antonio, TX 78249, USA; [email protected]; Tel.: +1-210-458-7407; Fax: +1-210-458-5728 Academic Editors: Andreas Demetriou and George Spanoudis Received: 23 December 2016; Accepted: 6 June 2017; Published: 12 June 2017 Abstract: The aim of this paper is to provide a parsimonious account of developmental and individual differences in intelligence (measured as g). The paper proposes a Differential– Developmental Model (DDM), which focuses on factors common to intelligence and cognitive development (e.g., mental speed and attention lapses). It also proposes a complementary method based on Jensen’s box, namely a chronometric device. The device systematically varies task complexity, and separates two components of mental speed that differentially predict intelligence and cognitive development (reaction time and movement time). The paper reviews key assumptions of DDM, preliminary findings relevant to DDM, and future research on DDM. Keywords: cognitive development; differential–developmental model (DDM); Jensen’s box; intelligence; mental speed; attention lapses; reaction time; movement time 1. Introduction All models are wrong, but some are useful. ([1], p. 202). The aim of this paper is to provide a parsimonious account of developmental and individual difference in intelligence (measured as g). 1 To this end, the paper proposes a Differential– Developmental Model (DDM), which focuses on factors common to cognitive development and intelligence (e.g., mental speed and attention lapses). The model attempts to bridge the two disciplines at the heart of the Special Issue: differential psychology, which focuses on individual differences in intelligence, and cognitive development, which focuses on age differences in intelligence.
    [Show full text]
  • The Causal Role of Consciousness: a Conceptual Addendum to Human Evolutionary Psychology
    Review of General Psychology Copyright 2004 by the Educational Publishing Foundation 2004, Vol. 8, No. 4, 227–248 1089-2680/04/$12.00 DOI: 10.1037/1089-2680.8.4.227 The Causal Role of Consciousness: A Conceptual Addendum to Human Evolutionary Psychology Jesse M. Bering Todd K. Shackelford University of Arkansas Florida Atlantic University By concentrating on the unconscious processes driving evolutionary mechanisms, evolutionary psychology has neglected the role of consciousness in generating human adaptations. The authors argue that there exist several “Darwinian algorithms” that are grounded in a novel representational system. Among such adaptations are information- retention homicide, the killing of others who are believed to possess information about the self that has the potential to jeopardize inclusive fitness, and those generating suicide, which may necessitate the capacity for self-referential emotions such as shame. The authors offer these examples to support their argument that human psychology is characterized by a representational system in which conscious motives have inserted themselves at the level of the gene and have fundamentally changed the nature of hominid evolution. Evolutionary psychologists frequently reca- However, in certain cases, this approach may pitulate the theme that adaptive behaviors are not accurately capture the complexities of hu- guided by unconscious processes servicing ge- man evolution because it tends to ignore the role netic selection in individual organisms (Buss, of consciousness in the emergence of unique 1995, 1999; Daly & Wilson, 1999; Dawkins, human adaptations. We define consciousness as 1986; Leger, Kamil, & French, 2001; Symons, that naturally occurring cognitive representa- 1992). Among many other examples, such tional capacity permitting explicit and reflective “blind” fitness-enhancing algorithms include accounts of the—mostly causative—contents of those that are devoted to mate selection, child mind, contents harbored by the psychological rearing, and altruism.
    [Show full text]
  • Theory of Mind for a Humanoid Robot
    Theory of Mind for a Humanoid Robot Brian Scassellati MIT Artificial Intelligence Lab 545 Technology Square – Room 938 Cambridge, MA 02139 USA [email protected] http://www.ai.mit.edu/people/scaz/ Abstract. If we are to build human-like robots that can interact naturally with people, our robots must know not only about the properties of objects but also the properties of animate agents in the world. One of the fundamental social skills for humans is the attribution of beliefs, goals, and desires to other people. This set of skills has often been called a “theory of mind.” This paper presents the theories of Leslie [27] and Baron-Cohen [2] on the development of theory of mind in human children and discusses the potential application of both of these theories to building robots with similar capabilities. Initial implementation details and basic skills (such as finding faces and eyes and distinguishing animate from inanimate stimuli) are introduced. I further speculate on the usefulness of a robotic implementation in evaluating and comparing these two models. 1 Introduction Human social dynamics rely upon the ability to correctly attribute beliefs, goals, and percepts to other people. This set of metarepresentational abilities, which have been collectively called a “theory of mind” or the ability to “mentalize”, allows us to understand the actions and expressions of others within an intentional or goal-directed framework (what Dennett [15] has called the intentional stance). The recognition that other individuals have knowl- edge, perceptions, and intentions that differ from our own is a critical step in a child’s development and is believed to be instrumental in self-recognition, in providing a perceptual grounding during language learning, and possibly in the development of imaginative and creative play [9].
    [Show full text]
  • Comparative Studies of Human Cognitive Evolution: the Future of Anthropology? Pp
    Using comparative studies of primate and canid social cognition to model our Miocene minds A thesis presented by Brian Alexander Hare to The Department of Anthropology in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the subject of Anthropology Harvard University Cambridge, Massachusetts January 2004 1 © 2004 – Brian Alexander Hare 2 Table of contents Abstract pp. iv Acknowledgements pp. v Introduction Part I: Comparative studies of human cognitive evolution: The future of anthropology? pp. 1 Identifying derived features of hominin cognition Part II: Do chimpanzees know what conspecifics know? pp. 22 Part III: Chimpanzees deceive a human competitor by hiding pp. 54 Evidence for selection pressures on social cognition Part IV: Do capuchin monkeys know what conspecifics can and cannot see? pp. 89 Part V: Chimpanzees are more skillful in competitive than cooperative cognitive tasks pp. 99 Part VI: The domestication of social cognition in dogs pp. 132 The future of comparative studies on human cognitive evolution Part VII: Can competitive paradigms increase the validity of experiments on primate social cognition? pp. 140 Part VIII: Tempering Darwin’s greatest difficulty: How, when, and why did the human mind evolve? pp. 173 References pp. 208 3 4 Brian Alexander Hare Using comparative studies of primate and canid social cognition to model our Miocene minds Thesis Advisors: Professors Richard Wrangham, Marc Hauser, and Michael Tomasello Abstract The greatest challenge facing anthropology is in explaining the evolution of human cognition. The evolution of unique social problem solving skills likely explain much of what is unique about our phenotype including language and culture.
    [Show full text]
  • Developmental Differentiation of Executive Functions on the NIH Toolbox Cognition Battery
    Neuropsychology © 2018 American Psychological Association 2018, Vol. 32, No. 7, 777–783 0894-4105/18/$12.00 http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/neu0000476 Developmental Differentiation of Executive Functions on the NIH Toolbox Cognition Battery Natacha Akshoomoff and Timothy T. Brown Roger Bakeman University of California, San Diego Georgia State University Donald J. Hagler Jr. On Behalf of the University of California, San Diego Pediatric Imaging, Neurocognition, and Genetics Study Objective: The NIH Toolbox Cognition Battery (NTCB) is a brief computerized method for evaluating neuropsychological functions in children, adolescents, and adults. We examined how performance on the 2 executive function measures of cognitive flexibility and inhibitory control was related to performance on the other NTCB measures across development. Method: Participants were 1,020 typically developing individuals between the ages of 3 and 21 from the Pediatric Imaging, Neurocognition, and Genetics Study who were divided into 5 age groups (3–6, 7–9, 10–13, 14–17, and 18–21). Scores were adjusted for sex, level of parental education, and family income. Results: Although the correlations between the 2 executive function measures were moderate and consistent across age groups, their correlations with the other 5 cognitive measures were highest in the youngest age group and decreased across the older age groups. Exploratory factor analysis revealed that all NTCB measures loaded onto a single factor for the 3- to 6-year-olds. Across the older age groups, the executive function and processing speed measures loaded onto one factor, and the vocabulary knowledge, oral reading, and working memory measures loaded onto a second factor.
    [Show full text]
  • Heterochrony in Chimpanzee and Bonobo Spatial Memory Development
    Rosati Alexandra (Orcid ID: 0000-0002-6906-7807) Heterochrony in chimpanzee and bonobo spatial memory development Alexandra G. Rosati Correspondence Departments of Psychology and Anthropology University of Michigan 530 Church St Ann Arbor, MI 48109 [email protected] Keywords: Comparative cognition; spatial cognition; life history; ecology; apes Funding information: This work was supported by an L.S.B. Leakey Foundation, and AGR was supported by NIA R01AG04395. Figures and tables: 5 Black-and-white figures, 2 tables This is the author manuscript accepted for publication and has undergone full peer review but has not been through the copyediting, typesetting, pagination and proofreading process, which may lead to differences between this version and the Version of Record. Please cite this article as doi: 10.1002/ajpa.23833 This article is protected by copyright. All rights reserved. Abstract Objectives: The emergence of human-unique cognitive abilities has been linked to our species’ extended juvenile period. Comparisons of cognitive development across species can provide new insights into the evolutionary mechanisms shaping cognition. This study examined the development of different components of spatial memory, cognitive mechanisms that support complex foraging, by comparing two species with similar life history that vary in wild ecology: bonobos (Pan paniscus) and chimpanzees (Pan troglodytes). Materials and Methods: Spatial memory development was assessed using a cross- sectional experimental design comparing apes ranging from infancy to adulthood. Study 1 tested 73 sanctuary-living apes on a task examining recall of a single location after a one-week delay, compared to an earlier session. Study 2 tested their ability to recall multiple locations within a complex environment.
    [Show full text]
  • Human Frontal Lobes Are Not Relatively Large
    Human frontal lobes are not relatively large Robert A. Bartona,1 and Chris Vendittib aEvolutionary Anthropology Research Group, Department of Anthropology, Durham University, Durham DH1 3LE, United Kingdom; and bSchool of Biological Sciences, University of Reading, Reading RG6 6AS, United Kingdom Edited by Katerina Semendeferi, University of California, San Diego, La Jolla, CA, and accepted by the Editorial Board March 12, 2013 (received for review September 10, 2012) One of the most pervasive assumptions about human brain evolu- logged—volumes) (3–5, 7). These measures suggest that human tion is that it involved relative enlargement of the frontal lobes. We frontal cortices are larger as a proportion of total brain size than show that this assumption is without foundation. Analysis of five in other species. However, proportional size differences conflate independent data sets using correctly scaled measures and phylo- selective enlargement with allometric scaling. Volumes of dif- genetic methods reveals that the size of human frontal lobes, and of ferent brain structures change at different rates as brain and body specific frontal regions, is as expected relative to the size of other size evolve (14, 15), and with different implications for variables brain structures. Recent claims for relative enlargement of human more directly related to information processing than volume, such frontal white matter volume, and for relative enlargement shared by as numbers of neurons and synapses (16). For example, the vol- all great apes, seem to be mistaken.
    [Show full text]
  • Functional Independence and Cognitive Architecture
    (forthcoming in The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science) Functional independence and cognitive architecture Vincent Bergeron Abstract In cognitive science, the concept of dissociation has been central to the functional individuation and decomposition of cognitive systems. Setting aside debates about the legitimacy of inferring the existence of dissociable systems from behavioral dissociation data, the main idea behind the dissociation approach is that two cognitive systems are dissociable, and therefore viewed as distinct, if each can be damaged, or impaired, without affecting the other system’s functions. In this paper, I propose a notion of functional independence that does not require dissociability, and describe an approach to the functional decomposition and modelling of cognitive systems that complements the dissociation approach. I show that highly integrated cognitive and neurocognitive systems can be decomposed into non-dissociable but functionally independent components, and argue that this approach can provide a general account of cognitive specialization in terms of stable structure-function relationship. 1. Introduction 2. Functional Independence Without Dissociability 3. FI Systems and Cognitive Architecture 4. FI Systems and Cognitive Specialization 1 Introduction In cognitive science, the concept of dissociation has been central to the functional individuation and decomposition of cognitive systems. The main idea behind the dissociation approach is that two cognitive systems are dissociable, and therefore viewed as distinct, if each can be damaged, or impaired, without affecting the other system’s functions. More precisely, consider two cognitive systems A and B. If B can be damaged (or impaired) without affecting A’s functions, and A can be damaged (or impaired) without affecting B’s functions, then A and B are dissociable (and distinct) systems (even if the two might share some of their components).
    [Show full text]
  • Investigating Models of Social Development Using a Humanoid
    Investigating Models of Social Development Using a Humanoid Robot (Invited Paper) Brian Scassellati Yale University Department of Computer Science 51 Prospect Street New Haven, CT 06520 Email: [email protected] Abstract— Human social dynamics rely upon the ability to the structures that these models propose. Finally, we will correctly attribute beliefs, goals, and percepts to other people. describe a hybrid model called embodied theory of mind The set of abilities that allow an individual to infer these hidden that links together ideas from both Baron-Cohen and Leslie mental states based on observed actions and behavior has been called a “theory of mind” [1]. Drawing from the models of Baron- with a grounded perceptual system. The hybrid model was Cohen [2] and Leslie [3], a novel architecture called embodied implemented on a humanoid robot and evaluated using a theory of mind was developed to link high-level cognitive skills simple social learning scenario. to the low-level perceptual abilities of a humanoid robot. The implemented system determines visual saliency based on inherent II. LESLIE’S MODEL object attributes, high-level task constraints, and the attentional states of others. Objects of interest are tracked in real-time to Leslie’s [3] theory treats the representation of causal events produce motion trajectories which are analyzed by a set of naive as a central organizing principle to theories of object mechan- physical laws designed to discriminate animate from inanimate ics and theories of other minds much in the same way that movement. Animate objects can be the source of attentional the notion of number may be central to object representation.
    [Show full text]
  • Comparative Primate Psychology D Maestripieri, the University of Chicago, Chicago, IL, USA
    Comparative Primate Psychology D Maestripieri, The University of Chicago, Chicago, IL, USA ã 2012 Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved. Glossary Homologous traits Similar traits possessed by Adaptation A genetically controlled trait that has evolved by different species as a result of inheritance from a common natural selection. ancestor. Analogous traits Similar traits that evolved independently Phylogeny The evolutionary development and in different species in response to similar environmental history of a species or higher taxonomic grouping of pressures. organisms. Comparative psychology The study of mind and behavior Primatology The discipline that studies nonhuman in nonhuman animals. primates. Convergent evolution The process by which natural Trait A morphological, physiological, or behavioral selection produces similar adaptations in different species characteristic of an organism. that live in similar environments. Evolutionary Foundations of Comparative related behavior in human beings” (pp. 311–312). Evolutionary Primate Psychology arguments do not figure prominently in comparative research conducted with the animal model approach. Particular organ- Psychology is the discipline that studies mind and behavior. isms are selected mainly on the basis of practical criteria, such as Within psychology, there are many subfields including, among they are small and cheap to maintain in the laboratory, they others, biological, clinical, cognitive, comparative, develop- reproduce frequently, and it is easier to conduct experimental mental, educational, evolutionary, industrial/organizational, studies that may require highly invasive procedures. The most personality and individual differences, and social psychology. common organisms that fit these criteria and are used in com- Some of these subfields are often recognized as independent parative psychological research include fruit flies, cockroaches, disciplines.
    [Show full text]