Philosophy of Law

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Philosophy of Law The Catholic Lawyer Volume 3 Number 1 Volume 3, January 1957, Number 1 Article 12 Philosophy of Law William F. Cahill Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.stjohns.edu/tcl Part of the Catholic Studies Commons This Book Review is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at St. John's Law Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in The Catholic Lawyer by an authorized editor of St. John's Law Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. BOOK REVIEWS PHILOSOPHY OF LAW, by Giorgio Del Vecchio, translated by Thomas Owen Martin. The Catholic University of America Press, Washington, D. C., 1953. Pp. xxiii-461. $6.50, cloth. Reviewed by WILLIAM F. CAHILL* Professor Del Vecchio's lectures on the his appraisal of Catholic writers. Yet, even Philosophy of Law are here published for in these essays, and particularly in that on the first time in English. Even before 1930, St. Thomas, there is to be desired a better when the first printed edition appeared in application of the author's acknowledged Italian, the lectures circulated widely and powers. His neglect to present, either in this spread everywhere the fame of their author. historical or in the later doctrinal section, They have since been translated into eight even a summary of the work of the Fathers other languages. The author's reputation for of the Church who adapted and developed broad inquiry, acute analysis and clarity of the natural law doctrines of the Roman exposition will be further enhanced by the jurists, seems a serious omission. Nor is it present lucid and graceful translation. a mere oversight, for he says "only in the age of the Renaissance . was the classic The introduction describes the concept doctrine reaffirmed according to which Law and functions of Philosophy of Law, indi- is derived from human nature independently cates its relations to other sciences, and out- of Theology".' That the classical doctrine lines its methods. In this brilliantly succinct never went beyond human nature, and that essay, one cannot fail to perceive a mind the Fathers and Scholastics made all depend whose breadth and profundity returns al- on premises of revelation, are implications ways to that disciplined harmony which is which the author does not attempt to justify. the hallmark of integrated education. No indication is made of the contributions The body of the work has two major of Gratian and other medieval writers to divisions. The first of these comprises over the development of the doctrine on custom two hundred pages devoted to a summary as a source of law. Bracton is not even history of the Philosophy of Law. The ex- named, and we feel he should be, both for pogitions of the teachings of the Greek phil- his recognized doctrinal contributions and osophers, of Grotius, Hobbes, Thomasius, for his enormous influence upon the devel- Rousseau, and Kant, are especially notable, opment of law in the English-speaking coun- as well for the accuracy of their material as tries. The presentation of modem writers for the clear precision of their expression. on the Philosophy of Law includes a useful The studies on St. Thomas Aquinas and list of names of writers and their works. Suarez are the best work of the author in For the nations other than Italy, there is little more. *A. B., Manhattan College (1932); J. C. D., Lat- eran University (1952); Professor of Comparative I DEL VECCHIO, PHILOSOPHY OF LAw 46 (8th ed., Law, St. John's University School of Law. Martin transl. 1953). BOOK REVIEWS The second major division of the work is the jurisprudential philosophies of Skepti- the "Systematic Treatise." It begins with a cism, Empirical Realism, the Historical section in which consideration is given to School, and Utilitarianism. the concept of law - a section so well or- From his statement of the ultimate ra- ganized as to be most interesting and in- tional basis of law, that law is an "a priori structive. The careful reader will note, form of the spirit," we dissent. Moderate however, that all absolute concepts, that of realism, asserting that experience is the ulti- justice included, are made to depend upon mate basis of all ideas - that the intellect 2 the Kantian postulate of a priori ideas. abstracts the universal from the particular While the importance of motive in deter- which is known by experience, cannot ac- 5 mining the juridical quality of acts is well cept any ideas as innate. demonstrated, the author goes too far when Del Vecchio calls "theologists" 6 all those he extends the field of law to all human who trace a necessary relation between God 3 actions, even internal ones. and the law. For him, the "theologist" point of view has two forms: it identifies law with The treatment of the origins and histori- the will of the divinity, or it postulates a di- cal evolution of law in the second section vine reason which determines what is just - of the "Systematic Treatise" covers only that determination is adopted by the divine twenty-four pages. The consequently com- will and must be accepted by men. He is not pendious quality of its statements leaves satisfied that either is truly rational, for the much room for distinctions, qualifications, first prescinds from reason, and the second additions and positive emendations, if the offends by invoking reason in reference to reader is to form an objective view of these the divinity which "is, by definition, absolute problems. and superior to reason, consequently it must In the last section of the "Systematic be accepted only as such, thanks to faith." Treatise," on the rational foundation of This view, that the existence and nature of law, Del Vecchio discusses the chief adver- God are not knowable by reason is, of saries of his position, and presents his own course, contrary to Thomistic philosophy views on "human nature as foundation of and even to Catholic doctrine. It has its law." To nearly everything he says of natural philosophical root in the Kantian view that law, and of its relation to positive law, we the principle of causality is valid only in the 4 7 can assent. As an "absolutist," he rejects world of phenomena. 2 DEL VECCIO, op. cit. supra note 1, at 252-255. It is true that much of Del Vecchio's phil- 3 DEL VECCHIO, op. cit. supra note 1, at 255-260. osophy of law, when it descends to more St. Thomas distinguishes thus: " . there is no virtue whose exercise the law cannot command. (1952); see also Book Note (3d ed.), 10 APOLLI- But human law does not prescribe all the acts of NARIS 301 (1937). all the virtues." SUMMA THEOLOGICA I-I, q.96,a.3, 5 The view here criticized was expressed in the c. (Emphasis added.) And the reason St. Thomas third Italian edition. See 10 APOLLINARIS 301 offers for this distinction is pregnant with impli- (1937). cations ".. to the political community, man is 6 Msgr. Graneris noted that Del Vecchio began, in not ordained in the totality of his being nor in the the fifth Italian edition, to use the term "theologist" totality of his resources." SUMMA THEOLOGICA I-II, instead of "theological" to describe these points of q.21, a.4, ad 3. view. 20 APOLLINARIS 148 (1947). 4 See Graneris, Book Review (5th and 8th ed.), 7 DEL VECCHIO, PHILOSOPHY OF LAW 432-433 (8th 20 APOLLINARIS 148 (1947), 25 APOLLINARIS 440 ed., Martin transl. 1953). 3 CATHOLIC LAWYER, JANUARY, 1957 particular problems, is acceptable to the the ultimate basis of law may find himself Thomist and the Catholic. Yet it would be worshipping idols. erroneous to assume that his metaphysical If we had in English an adequate litera- absolutism has no influence in his evaluation ture of the Thomistic philosophy of law, of matters which may seem remote from the present work would be most welcome criteriology and theodicy. When Del Vec- as illustrating interesting parallels erected 8 chio discussed the problem of whether a upon a different epistemological founda- man might ever, in any circumstances, dis- tion." But in the confusion of views and simulate, he was led - by his metaphysically expressions now prevailing in the English absolute commitment to truth -to deny that writings on natural law, one may be per- dissimulation is ever virtuous or even mor- mitted to suggest that by seeming to promote 9 ally admissible. In a work which clearly alliances which are ambiguous,"2 natural law manifested Del Vecchio's devotion to fascist philosophers may impede rather than ad- 0 theory, he discussed the need for a moral vance the development of jurisprudence on as well as a legal bond among the citizens a sound philosophical basis. of a state. And he described the moral bond 11 Of the eighth Italian edition Msgr. Graneris had in these terms: "an identity of wills, a true only this to say: "There is no need for us to discuss communion of minds, a single order of faith the work of Del Vecchio, for its acceptance is evi- in the civil religion of the Fatherland." It denced by the frequency of successive editions. His seems that a metaphysical absolutist who is doctrine is well known, and agrees with our own in many respects." 25 APOLLNARIs 440 (1952). offended by postulates of divine reason as 12 The reviews of earlier Italian editions of Del Vecchio's PHILOSOPHY OF LAW and of his other 8 DEL VECCHIO, VERITA E INGANNO NELLA MORALE works, pointed out the subjective character of his E NEL DIRITTO (1947), Palazzini, Book Review, 20 philosophical foundations.
Recommended publications
  • Editorial Preface to This Volume
    University of Michigan Law School University of Michigan Law School Scholarship Repository Other Publications Faculty Scholarship 1914 Editorial Preface to This Volume Joseph H. Drake Available at: https://repository.law.umich.edu/other/153 Follow this and additional works at: https://repository.law.umich.edu/other Part of the Law and Philosophy Commons, and the Legal History Commons THE FORMAL BASES OF LAW BY GIORGIO DEL VECCHIO Professor of Philosophy of Law in the University of Bologna TRANSLATED BY JOHN LISLE of the PhiladelphiaBar WITH AN EDITORIAL PREFACE BY JOSEPH H. DRAKE Professor of Law in the University of Michigan AND WITH INTRODUJCTIONS BY SIR JOHN MACDONELL Professor of ComparativeLaw in University College, London AND SHEPARD BARCLAY Former Chief Justice of the Supreme Court of Missouri First Published 1914 (Boston: The Boston Book Company) Reprinted 1969 By Arrangement with the Macmillan Company EDITORIAL PREFACE TO THIS VOLUME By JOSEPH H. DRAKE' I. The Author and the Translator. GIORGIO DEL VECCHIO (born at Bologna, August 26, 1878) studied at the universities of Genoa, Rome and Berlin, obtaining in the University of Genoa his doctor's degree in the philosophy of law. In the year 1903 he was nominated professor of that subject in the University of Ferrara, where he began his teaching with the discourse "Right and Human Personality in the History of Thought." He occupied that chair till the end of 1906, giving also a course of lectures as docent in the University of Bologna during the years 1905 and 1906. In 1906 he was nominated for the professorate of the philosophy of law in the University of Sassari and remained there until the end of 1909.
    [Show full text]
  • Jhering En Ortega Y Gasset Jhering in Ortega Y Gasset
    Doxa. Cuadernos de Filosofía del Derecho, (2020), 43 e-ISSN: 2386-4702 | ISSN: 0214-8676 Jhering en Ortega y Gasset Jhering in Ortega y Gasset Juan José Gil Cremades Autor: Resumen Juan José Gil Cremades Universidad de Zaragoza, España A partir de 1933, abandonada la política activa, Ortega [email protected] https://orcid.org/0000-0002-2704-9352 dedicó su atención, entre otros temas, a la filosofía social; particularmente a desentrañar el «hecho social», que creyó Recibido: 8-4-2019 Aceptado: 13-11-2019 radicaba en los «usos», quizá bajo la inspiración de Jhe- ring. Cómo llegó a él, fallecido en 1892, qué lectura hizo Citar como: Gil Cremades, Juan José, (2020). Jhering en Ortega de su obra, cómo modificó sus planteamientos y cómo su y Gasset. Doxa. Cuadernos de Filosofía del Derecho, propuesta fue recibida por la coetánea filosofía española 43, pp. 31-58. https://doi.org/10.14198/ DOXA2020.43.02 del derecho, son las cuestiones estudiadas en este trabajo. Licencia: Palabras clave: Jhering; Ortega y Gasset; hecho social; Este trabajo se publica bajo una Licencia Creative uso social. Commons Atribución 4.0 Internacional. Abstract © Juan José Gil Cremades After 1933, when he abandoned active politics, Ortega devoted his attention, among other topics, to social phi- losophy; particularly to unraveling the «social fact», which he believed was rooted in «customs», perhaps under the inspiration of Jhering. How he came to it, died in 1892, what reading he made of his work, how he modified his approaches and how his proposal was received by the con- temporary spanish philosophy of law are the questions studied in this work.
    [Show full text]
  • The Art of Judging and Power, Pedagogy, & Praxis: Article 4 Moving the Classroom to Action
    Loyola of Los Angeles Law Review Volume 32 Number 3 Symposia—The Brennan Legacy: The Art of Judging and Power, Pedagogy, & Praxis: Article 4 Moving the Classroom to Action 4-1-1999 The Brennan Legacy: The Art of Judging Ruggero J. Aldisert Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.lmu.edu/llr Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Ruggero J. Aldisert, The Brennan Legacy: The Art of Judging, 32 Loy. L.A. L. Rev. 673 (1999). Available at: https://digitalcommons.lmu.edu/llr/vol32/iss3/4 This Symposium is brought to you for free and open access by the Law Reviews at Digital Commons @ Loyola Marymount University and Loyola Law School. It has been accepted for inclusion in Loyola of Los Angeles Law Review by an authorized administrator of Digital Commons@Loyola Marymount University and Loyola Law School. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE BRENNAN LEGACY: TIE ART OF JUDGING Judge Ruggero J. Aldisert* I. INTRODUCTION What does ajudge do when he or she decides a case? Benjamin Cardozo posed this question in 1921 and answered it in what has become a classic of American legal literature, The Na- ture of the Judicial Process.' Drawing from his wealth of scholar- ship and experience as Chief Judge of the New York Court of Ap- peals, he described the ingredients that enter "that strange compound which is brewed daily in the caldron of the courts."2 Cardozo's analysis and philosophy examined the accepted definition of the ju- dicial process: What courts do and should do, and how judges rea- 3 son and should reason in deciding particular cases.
    [Show full text]
  • Review of Justice. an Historical and Philosophical Essay by Giorgio Del
    THE UNIVERSITY OF CHICAGO LAW REVIEW [Vol. 22 Justice. An Historical and Philosophical Essay. By Giorgio Del Vecchio. Edited with additional notes by A H. Campbell. New York: Philosophical Library, 1953. Pp. xxi, 236. $6.00. i Natural Right and History. By Leo Strauss. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1953. Pp. x, 327. $5.00. Plato's Modem Enemies and the Theory of Natural Law. By John Wild. Chi- cago: University of Chicago Press, 1953. Pp. 259. $5.50. These are three recent books on natural law. The first is a translation from an Italian philosopher of law; the other two are American books, the one by a social, the other by a general philosopher. Del Vecchio's Justice is the first English translation of this work, published in the United Kingdom by the Edinburgh University Press. Del Vecchio's 'Formal Bases of Law" were published in English in the Ten Modern Legal PhilosophiesSeries in 1914. An article by him appeared in English in the Roscoe Pound Festschrift, and his "Truth and Untruth in Morals and Law" was re- cently published in the Iowa Law Review.' The text of this small book occupies only eighty pages; the bulk of the book consists of notes. The author poses the problem of justice in its relation to law; the essence of justice is a certain proportionality (Leibniz) between men, Dante's hominis ad hominem proportio. Del Vecchio presents a historical survey of the ideas on justice, from the Greeks via the Patristic to Scholastic philosophy. The principal emphasis is put on Plato, Aristotle, St.
    [Show full text]
  • Answers Parsed from Works of Two International Lawyers
    THE INTERNATIONAL LAWYER A TRIANNUAL PUBLICATION OF THE ABA/SECTION OF INTERNATIONAL LAW Why We Read The International Lawyer - Answers Parsed from Works of Two International Lawyers PATRICK DEL DUCA* The InternationalLawyer's penetrating, permeating, multi-faceted, multi- cultural, cross-boundary, cross-disciplinary, and global treatment of the many dimensions of international law fascinates me, and no publication over the last fifty years has so consistently engaged practicing lawyers in creating that fascination. Nowhere else does such a diverse assortment of practitioners of international law of all kinds lay out the issues that they address in perspectives keenly grounded in both practice and theory. The contributors to The InternationalLawyer and its readers share an appreciation not only of the importance of the rule of law, but also an appreciation of how an understanding of the law in multiple contexts and of how the law bridges those contexts can advance the law and the interests of those subject to it, as well as the careers of those who seek to practice it. We, the readers of, and contributors to, The International Lawyer are restless souls, ever seeking fresh perspectives on the challenges that we confront in our professional lives, motivated not only by immediate client needs, but also by a sense that the law is a global endeavor, fundamental to human achievement. Of course, we are lawyers and hence not timid in claiming that our chosen profession offers, perhaps even uniquely, the tools to resolve the truly important problems, much as economists, political scientists, philosophers, and theologians might likewise argue that their respective professions afford.
    [Show full text]
  • Comment Main Trends of Italian Legal Philosophy
    COMMENT MAIN TRENDS OF ITALIAN LEGAL PHILOSOPHY* Sergio Cotta** I The philosophical reflection on law has followed a rather steady course in Italy since the Middle Ages. The scholastic reflection on law (or still better-laws) centered around the problem of natural law and, having its organic exposition in Aquinas' systematization, went side by side with the secular theories of Marsilius of Padua, who elaborated a conception of law as an expression of State will. As to the mediaeval jurists, natural law was discussed (even though often rather naively) by the glossators; the problems of the legal method and the characteristics of law engaged much attention by the commentators. In the "civil philosophy" of humanism and renaissance, a prominent place belongs to problems of justice, to the relations between law and morals, and to the end of laws. From the second half of the sixteenth century to the eighteenth century, we do not find in Italy anything comparable with the systematic research and doctrines on natural law that flourished in the other parts of Europe due especially to the work of the Spanish catholic school (ranging from Vitoria to Suarez) and of the so-called lay school of natural law (ranging from Grotius to the younger Fichte). However, in the eighteenth century a striking revival of legal-philosophical studies took place in Italy. Only two authors (whose renown abroad is inversely proportional to their philo- sophical significance) need be mentioned here-Giambattista Vico and Cesare Beccaria, in whom the main tendencies of this revival are embodied. With Vico's two chief works, Diritto universale (1720-1721) and Principi di una Scienza nuova (1725-1730), a clearly speculative trend, centered on the problem of the relations between truth and history, is as- serting itself.
    [Show full text]
  • Universidade Federal Fluminense Programa De Pós-Graduação Stricto Sensu Em Direito Constitucional
    UNIVERSIDADE FEDERAL FLUMINENSE PROGRAMA DE PÓS-GRADUAÇÃO STRICTO SENSU EM DIREITO CONSTITUCIONAL WINGLER ALVES PEREIRA O DILEMA DO IMAGINÁRIO CONSTITUCIONAL BRASILEIRO: TUPI OR NOT TUPI Niterói 2016 WINGLER ALVES PEREIRA O DILEMA DO IMAGINÁRIO CONSTITUCIONAL BRASILEIRO: TUPI OR NOT TUPI Dissertação de Mestrado apresentada ao Programa de Pós-Graduação em Direito Constitucional da Universidade Federal Fluminense, como requisito parcial para obtenção do grau de Mestre na Área de Concentração em Direito Constitucional. Orientador: Prof. Dr. André Saddy Coorientador: Prof. Dr. Carlos Sávio Gomes Teixeira Niterói 2016 WINGLER ALVES PEREIRA O DILEMA DO IMAGINÁRIO CONSTITUCIONAL BRASILEIRO: TUPI OR NOT TUPI Dissertação de Mestrado apresentada ao Programa de Pós-Graduação em Direito Constitucional da Universidade Federal Fluminense, como requisito parcial para obtenção do grau de Mestre na Área de Concentração de Direito Constitucional. _______________, em ____ de março de 2016. BANCA EXAMINADORA ___________________________________________________________ Prof. Dr. André Saddy (orientador) – Universidade Federal Fluminense ___________________________________________________________ Prof. Dr. Carlos Sávio Gomes Teixeira (coorientador) – Universidade Federal Fluminense ___________________________________________________________ Prof. Dr. Eduardo Manuel Val – Universidade Federal Fluminense ___________________________________________________________ Prof. Dr. Anderson Vichinkeski Teixeira – Universidade do Vale do Rio dos Sinos Niterói 2016 AGRADECIMENTOS
    [Show full text]
  • Fundamentos Teóricos E Filosóficos Do Novo Direito Constitucional Brasileiro*
    FUNDAMENTOS TEÓRICOS E FILOSÓFICOS DO NOVO DIREITO CONSTITUCIONAL BRASILEIRO* LUÍS ROBERTO BARROSO Professor Titular de Direito Constitucional da UERJ. Mestre em Direito pela Yale Law School. Advogado no Rio de Janeiro. CAPÍTULO I - PRÉ-COMPREENSÃO DO TEMA I. A Pós-modernidade e o Direito1. Planeta Terra. Início do sécu- lo XXI. Ainda sem contato com outros mundos habitados. Entre luz e som- bra, descortina-se a pós-modernidade. O rótulo genérico abriga a mistura de estilos, a descrença no poder absoluto da razão, o desprestígio do Estado. A era da velocidade. A imagem acima do conteúdo. O efêmero e o volátil parecem derrotar o permanente e o essencial. Vive-se a angústia do que não pôde ser e a perplexidade de um tempo sem verdades seguras. Uma época aparentemente pós-tudo: pós-marxista, pós-kelseniana, pós- freudiana2. * Tema da palestra proferida na EMERJ/Conselho de Vitaliciamento do TJ/RJ por ocasião do Seminário “Direito Constitucional”, realizado em 24.06.01. 1. Zygmunt Bauman, A globalização: as conseqüências humanas, 1999; Ignacio Ramonet, “O pensamento único e os regimes globalitários”, in Globalização: o fato e o mito, 1998; André- Jean Arnaud, O direito entre modernidade e globalização, 1999; Boaventura de Souza Santos, “Uma cartografia simbólica das representações sociais: prolegômenos a uma concepção pós-mo- derna do direito”, Revista Brasileira de Ciências Criminais, 1996; José Eduardo Faria, “Globalização, autonomia decisória e política”, in Margarida Maria Lacombe Camargo (org.), 1988-1998: uma década de Constituição, 1999; Daniel Sarmento, “Constituição e globalização: a crise dos paradigmas do direito constitucional”, Revista de Direito Administrativo, 215/19, 1999; Marilena Chaui, “Público, privado, despotismo”, in Adauto Novaes (org.), Ética, 1992; Antônio Junqueira de Azevedo, “O direito pós-moderno e a codificação”, in Anais da XVII Conferência Nacional da Ordem dos Advogados do Brasil, v.
    [Show full text]
  • Cash Savings to the Court and the Probation Service Were Estimated at U.S
    1978] BOOK REVIEWS 549 Cash savings to the court and the probation service were estimated at U.S. $1,040,563 plus 27,715 work-hours over two years. This seems to indicate one direction for further progress not only, I suggest, with respect to status offenders, but also other juvenile offenders. Both are indicia of family failure and, to quote Floyd Feeney (p. 257): "The issue . is not really whose fault the problem is but rather what is to be done about it." It would seem obvious that the solution cannot lie in isolating the child with whose upbringing the family is failing, subjecting the child alone to the judicial process and frequently detaining him with others similarly placed at vast expense to the public and great detriment to the child. The solution must lie in counselling and the attainment of minimum standards within the family setting (please note the use of the words "family setting" instead of "family unit". The family is not and must never again be considered as a static unit into which any of its members is locked. It is a constantly-changing complex of interacting relationships between each of its members). Two programs in California have now demonstrated that developments on these lines are both more efficient and much cheaper than the existing system. It is now for other jurisdictions, including Alberta, to explore solutions along these lines, at a saving of public money, judicial and professional expertise and-not least-a happy and law-abiding future for the young. -OLIVE M. STONE* • Of the Institute of Law Research and Reform, Edmonton, Alberta.
    [Show full text]
  • John Henry Wigmore and the Uses of American Formalism
    Northwestern University School of Law Public Law and Legal Theory Papers Year 2001 Paper 39 Encountering Amateurism: John Henry Wigmore and the Uses of American Formalism Annelise Riles∗ ∗Cornell University - School of Law This working paper is hosted by The Berkeley Electronic Press (bepress) and may not be commer- cially reproduced without the permission of the copyright holder. http://law.bepress.com/nwwps-plltp/art39 Copyright c 2001 by the author. Encountering Amateurism: John Henry Wigmore and the Uses of American Formalism Annelise Riles Abstract This article explores the productive uses of amateurism in comparative law through a close reading of the life and work of John Henry Wigmore, the founder of the American tradition of comparative law who first came to the subject as a young missionary for the Langdellian style of American legal education in turn-of-the- century Japan. Drawing on anthropological and linguistic theory, the article ex- plains amateurism as a post-Realist epithet for formalism. It seeks to counter the received view of the discipline as a pure product of American and European critiques of legal classicism by demonstrating how Wigmore’s turn to the perfor- mative dimensions of legal formalism, at a moment when formalism found itself under Realist attack, provided a sustaining vision of the discipline. The power and creativity of formalist performance, as well as its limitations and even dangers, as deployed by Wigmore, raise questions relevant beyond comparative law about the aesthetic dimensions of American formalism. 1 Chapter 5 Encountering Amateurism: John Henry Wigmore and the Uses of American Formalism Annelise Riles* One of the recurring complaints about comparative law is that it is amateuristic.
    [Show full text]
  • La Estética Del Derecho
    LA ESTÉTICA DEL DERECHO Dr. Paulino Rueda Romero1 "Situad la belleza en la percepción de las relaciones, y tendréis la historia de sus progresos desde el nacimiento del mundo hasta nuestros días". Diderot. RESUMEN. El presente artículo explica en forma alegórica la expresión del Derecho en uno de los capítulos poco difundidos en el marco de la Filosofía del Derecho. Los clásicos escritos acerca del tema por filósofos fundamentalmente, Platón, Aristóteles, Hegel, Schopenhauer, C.J.Friedrich, Gustav Radbruch, Kant entre otros, explicaron en su momento, grandes capítulos de la belleza del Derecho en las diferentes facetas donde el Derecho tiene su razón de ser. Toca a nosotros, aplicar dichos conceptos, a la realidad de los hechos actuales. Las sentencias de los jueces cuando se ajustan al derecho solicitado y a las reglas del Derecho, constituyen una estética hecha realidad en la voluntad del juez. 1 Profesor investigador del Instituto de Investigaciones Jurídicas y titular del Curso Filosofía del Derecho. Los juicios que se ventilan en los Tribunales, cuyas resoluciones finales dan claro ejemplo de justicia a favor de los solicitantes, tienen una bella expresión en la sociedad, que ven con buenos ojos, las sentencias emitidas de acuerdo al Derecho. La estética del Derecho, también va a tener respuesta en la literatura, en el drama, en el lenguaje que hace propicio un mejor entendimiento de esa realidad que el mundo espera de los operadores jurídicos. El mundo globalizado y las nuevas formas de administración de justicia en las Cortes Internacionales así como la admisión y aceptación generalizada de los Derechos Humanos como denominador común de la humanidad, hace del Derecho una belleza cuando los jueces administran justicia en su nombre.
    [Show full text]
  • The Nature of the General Theory of Law
    “Ovidius” University Annals, Economic Sciences Series Volume XVII, Issue 2 /2017 The Nature of the General Theory of Law Trandafirescu Bogdan Cristian “Ovidius University” of Constanţa, Law and Administrative Sciences Faculty [email protected] Abstract The present paper is intended to ascertain the problem of the nature of the general theory of law, is it an emanation of the philosophy of law or is it just one of the legal sciences with the only difference that it does not study a branch of the law, but the law in its entirety? It is our opinion that the general theory of law is a positivist science which has objective law as exclusive object of study and that it is part of the category of legal sciences (in opposition with the auxiliary sciences studied in law school – legal sociology, legal philosophy, criminology, criminalistics, forensic medicine, etc.). Nevertheless, the total elimination of contributions from other sciences (sociology, politology, economy, philosophy, etc.) would only unjustifiably emasculate the explanations of the general theory of law. Key words: general theory of law; science of law; philosophy of law; positive law J.E.L. classification: K 00; K 10 1. Introduction The object of study and the nature of the general theory of law have long been discussed with the specialised literature. Points of view have oscillated between considering the general theory of law as an emanation of the philosophy of law and considering it a positivist discipline, limiting it strictly to objective law. „The general theory of law, born out of the success of positivist sciences at the end of the 19th century, was known as a way to exceed the simple description of objective law, and free of the theories of natural law at the same time; its fundamental idea lay in the fact that law can be « the object of study of a positive science ».
    [Show full text]