Reductionism About Personal Identity

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Reductionism About Personal Identity 1 I give permission for public access to my thesis and for any copying to be done at the discretion of the archives librarian and/or the College librarian. _______________________ _______________________ Signature Date 2 Preserving “Simple Suppositions” A Humean Response to Reductionism about Personal Identity A Thesis Submitted to the Philosophy Department Faculty of Mount Holyoke College in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for The Degree of Bachelors of Arts with Honors. Summa cum laude. Lindsay Crawford Mount Holyoke College 2005 3 Acknowledgements I am honored to thank formally my primary thesis advisor, Jay Garfield of Smith College, for his confidence in my work, the breadth of his wisdom and vision, and his untiring commitment to seeing this project reach fruition from its most embryonic stages. I am indebted to Jay for his guidance, patience, and his thoughtful feedback, including both his fairest praise and harshest criticism. Without Jay, I would not have a thesis to defend. Additionally, I thank my second thesis advisor, James Harold, for his dedication and close attention to my project, as well as his helpful comments and advice. I also thank the University of Colorado-Boulder philosophy faculty and graduate students, who introduced me to Derek Parfit’s “Reasons and Persons” and whose help and insight provided a strong foundation for this work. Additionally, I thank those professors whose influences on my intellectual development have been invaluable: Lee Bowie, Stiv Fleishman, Sam Mitchell, Ann Murphy, and William Quillian. Finally, I thank my colleagues, Constance Kassor, Kathryn Lindeman, Carolyn O’Mara, and Katia Vavova. These women have set remarkable examples of tireless academic rigor and commitment to philosophy, which have profoundly motivated and shaped the nature of my philosophical interests and pursuits. I am unspeakably fortunate for having found such a strong community of dedicated philosophers. This work is dedicated to Henry E. Crawford. 4 Contents CHAPTER ONE: PERSONAL IDENTITY AND REDUCTIONISM........................... 5 “My Division”................................................................................................... 6 Parfit’s Reductionist Thesis............................................................................ 12 Conclusion ...................................................................................................... 16 CHAPTER TWO: THE REDUCTIONIST ACCOUNT OF AGENCY....................... 20 Common Sense Egoism .................................................................................. 24 Reductionism and the Unity of Consciousness............................................... 32 IMPLICATIONS OF THE REDUCTIONIST VIEW .................................................... 36 HOW REDUCTIONISM BEARS ON PRUDENTIAL CONCERN................................. 39 BEYOND PRUDENTIAL CONCERN ..................................................................... 42 AGENCY FROM THE REDUCTIONIST STANDPOINT............................................. 44 Kant’s Two Perspectives View....................................................................... 46 Korsgaard on the Unity of Agency ................................................................. 49 An Assessment of Korsgaard’s Strategy ........................................................ 56 CHAPTER THREE: HUME’S FICTIONALISM ................................................... 61 Hume’s Book One: A “Bundle” Theory of Persons ....................................... 64 Hume’s Book Two: Persons and their Passions ............................................. 82 Hume’s Second Thoughts............................................................................... 90 Conclusion ...................................................................................................... 92 CHAPTER FOUR: REDUCTIONISM AND MORALITY ....................................... 94 Rejecting the Unity of Agency ....................................................................... 99 COMMITMENTS AND THE LANGUAGE OF SUCCESSIVE SELVES......................... 99 COMMITMENTS AND THE LAW: HONORING PRIOR DIRECTIVES ..................... 107 DESERT .......................................................................................................... 113 Rejecting the Separateness of Persons.......................................................... 128 DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE................................................................................... 128 Conclusion .................................................................................................... 134 CHAPTER FIVE: FICTIONALISM AND MINIMALISM..................................... 139 The Supervenience Structure of Reductionism ............................................ 140 Minimalism................................................................................................... 142 THE MINIMALIST DEFENSE OF NON-DERIVATIVE CONCERN ......................... 144 Fictionalism on the Justificatory Status of Person-directed Beliefs ............. 149 Conclusion .................................................................................................... 154 BIBLIOGRAPHY ............................................................................................. 157 5 Chapter One: Personal Identity and Reductionism Thought experiments deriving from recent developments in neuroscience have come to dominate debates about personal identity. One response to these thought experiments, which are often rooted in wildly counterfactual scenarios, is to argue that they are simply so implausible that they are essentially uninformative. Quine writes dismissively, “to seek what is ‘logically required’ for sameness of persons under unprecedented circumstances is to suggest that words have some logical force beyond what our past needs have invested them with.”1 Here Quine is suggesting that our concept of a person is one that can be explained sufficiently by appealing to our ordinary uses of the concept; to act as if the concept of a person survived in hypothetical cases where we could isolate these ordinary uses would be to misuse the concept entirely and render it unintelligible. Some, however, argue that these thought experiments are sufficiently plausible such that our intuitive responses to them should be taken seriously. The idea is that by conceptually isolating certain features of our ordinary concept of persons, we can come to understand what the crucial feature is that bases the concept of a person. And deciding what this crucial feature is depends on our intuitive responses to the work these thought experiments do in conceptually isolating certain features. 1 Quine (1972): 490. 6 Parfit2 defends this view, and such thought experiments motivate his reductionist analysis of persons. His reductionist analysis has two primary components: a metaphysical view of what matters about persons, and a moral view of what matters about persons. Parfit takes the latter view to be a necessary consequent of the former. So we must note on the outset that there are two distinct claims being made, united by the implicit conditional that if our metaphysical view is correct, it ought to structure our moral view. In what follows, I will first introduce “My Division,” the primary thought experiment that Parfit uses to introduce the problem of personal identity.3 I will examine in this chapter what Parfit believes to be the problem of personal identity, and how this problem motivates his reductionist claims. I will then explicate Parfit’s metaphysical picture, and show the way in which this picture is supposed to bring us to a certain view of persons. Parfit holds that this view of persons structures further claims about agency and morality, which will be unpacked in the coming chapters. “My Division” Suppose I have been involved in a near fatal accident, from which I emerge with a badly degenerated body, and the right hemisphere of my brain is rendered irreversibly damaged and utterly useless. Because my body is 2 Parfit (1984) 7 degenerating, my heart will eventually stop, and I will eventually lose everything, including my fully functional left hemisphere. The only way I can survive is by transplanting my left hemisphere into the de-brained and receptive body of another person. Let’s call the person who receives my fully functional left hemisphere “Lefty.” On many accounts of personal identity, Lefty would be my former self. This is because, in the absence of any other options, Lefty can preserve what is believed to be most central about my identity – my brain. It should first be noted that what gives this thought experiment force is that it has been proven that the two upper hemispheres of the brain can be disconnected, yet still be fully functional. Indeed, there exist cases where people must remove, or are born without, the corpus collosum that connects the left and right hemispheres of the brain.4 Parfit dismisses the objection that because we have, as of yet, not been able to transplant one hemisphere of a brain into a de-brained body, that the “My Division” case is impossible and therefore ought not to be entertained. Its impossibility is merely technical. What motivates this thought experiment is the fact that a person’s consciousness can be divided into independent streams. This, Parfit says, has been proven by advances in neuroscience.5 Only if this claim were false would we have a real objection to the use of this 3 Parfit (1984): 255. 4 Parfit (1984): 254. 5 Ibid.
Recommended publications
  • Generics Analysis Canberra Plan.Pdf
    Philosophical Perspectives, 26, Philosophy of Mind, 2012 CONCEPTS, ANALYSIS, GENERICS AND THE CANBERRA PLAN1 Mark Johnston Princeton University Sarah-Jane Leslie2 Princeton University My objection to meanings in the theory of meaning is not that they are abstract or that their identity conditions are obscure, but that they have no demonstrated use.3 —Donald Davidson “Truth and Meaning” From time to time it is said that defenders of conceptual analysis would do well to peruse the best empirically supported psychological theories of concepts, and then tailor their notions of conceptual analysis to those theories of what concepts are.4 As against this, there is an observation — traceable at least as far back to Gottlob Frege’s attack on psychologism in “The Thought” — that might well discourage philosophers from spending a week or two with the empirical psychological literature. The psychological literature is fundamentally concerned with mental representations, with the mental processes of using these in classification, characterization and inference, and with the sub-personal bases of these processes. The problem is that for many philosophers, concepts could not be mental items. (Jerry Fodor is a notable exception, we discuss him below.) We would like to set out this difference of focus in some detail and then propose a sort of translation manual, or at least a crucial translational hint, one which helps in moving between philosophical and psychological treatments of concepts. Then we will consider just how, given the translation, the relevant
    [Show full text]
  • ATINER's Conference Paper Series PHI2014-1077
    ATINER CONFERENCE PAPER SERIES No: PHI2014-1077 Athens Institute for Education and Research ATINER ATINER's Conference Paper Series PHI2014-1077 An Attempt to Undermine the Extreme Claim Sinem Elkatip Hatipoğlu Assistant Professor of Philosophy İstanbul Şehir University Turkey 1 ATINER CONFERENCE PAPER SERIES No: PHI2014-1077 An Introduction to ATINER's Conference Paper Series ATINER started to publish this conference papers series in 2012. It includes only the papers submitted for publication after they were presented at one of the conferences organized by our Institute every year. The papers published in the series have not been refereed and are published as they were submitted by the author. The series serves two purposes. First, we want to disseminate the information as fast as possible. Second, by doing so, the authors can receive comments useful to revise their papers before they are considered for publication in one of ATINER's books, following our standard procedures of a blind review. Dr. Gregory T. Papanikos President Athens Institute for Education and Research This paper should be cited as follows: Hatipoğlu, S.E., (2014) "An Attempt to Undermine the Extreme Claim”, Athens: ATINER'S Conference Paper Series, No: PHI2014-1077. Athens Institute for Education and Research 8 Valaoritou Street, Kolonaki, 10671 Athens, Greece Tel: + 30 210 3634210 Fax: + 30 210 3634209 Email: [email protected] URL: www.atiner.gr URL Conference Papers Series: www.atiner.gr/papers.htm Printed in Athens, Greece by the Athens Institute for Education and Research. All rights reserved. Reproduction is allowed for non-commercial purposes if the source is fully acknowledged.
    [Show full text]
  • UTILITARIANISM and PERSONAL IDENTITY 183 © 1999 Kluwer Academic Publishers
    The Journal of Value Inquiry 33: 183–199, 1999. UTILITARIANISM AND PERSONAL IDENTITY 183 © 1999 Kluwer Academic Publishers. Printed in the Netherlands. Utilitarianism and Personal Identity DAVID W. SHOEMAKER Department of Philosophy, University of Memphis, 327 Clement Hall, Memphis, TN 38152, USA 1. Introduction Ethical theories must include an account of the concept of a person. They also need a criterion of personal identity over time. This requirement is most needed in theories involving distributions of resources or questions of moral responsibility. For instance, in using ethical theories involving com- pensations of burdens, we must be able to keep track of the identities of persons earlier burdened in order to ensure that they are the same people who now are to receive the compensatory benefits. Similarly, in order to attribute moral responsibility to someone for an act, we must be able to determine that that person is the same person as the person who performed the act. Unfortunately, ethical theories generally include a concept of a person and criteria of personal identity either as notions implied or presupposed by the already worked out theory, with little or no argument given in support of them. But both approaches are unsatisfactory, for each runs the risk of ignoring certain fundamental features of the way persons actually are. What is needed first is a plausible metaphysical account of persons and personal identity to which an ethical theory might then conform and apply. Derek Parfit has attempted to provide such an account in Reasons and Persons, where he argues for what he calls the reductionist view of persons and personal identity and then attempts to show how such a conception provides a metaphysical background that lends important partial support to utilitarianism.1 But Parfit’s metaphysical view is neutral between two possible conceptions of personhood, and utilitarianism presupposes the truth of the more radical of the two conceptions, which precludes the possibility of there being a class of goods crucial to any plausible ethical theory.
    [Show full text]
  • Theories of Personal Identity
    Dean Zimmerman Materialism, Dualism, and “Simple” Theories of Personal Identity “Complex” and “Simple” Theories of Personal Identity Derek Parfit introduced “the Complex View” and “the Simple View” as names for contrasting theories about the nature of personal identity. He detects a “reductionist tradition”, typified by Hume and Locke, and continuing in such twentieth‐century philosophers as Grice, Ayer, Quinton, Mackie, John Perry, David Lewis, and Parfit himself. According to the Reductionists, “the fact of personal identity over time just consists in the holding of certain other facts. It consists in various kinds of psychological continuity, of memory, character, intention, and the like, which in turn rest upon bodily continuity.” The Complex View comprises “[t]he central claims of the reductionist tradition” (Parfit 1982, p. 227). The Complex View about the nature of personal identity is a forerunner to what he later calls “Reductionism”. A Reductionist is anyone who believes (1) that the fact of a person’s identity over time just consists in the holding of certain more particular facts, and (2) that these facts can be described without either presupposing the identity of this person, or explicitly claiming that the experiences in this person’s life are had by this person, or even explicitly claiming that this person exists. (Parfit 1984, p. 210) Take the fact that someone remembers that she, herself, witnessed a certain event at an earlier time. When described in those terms, it “presupposes” or “explicitly claims” that the same person is involved in both the episode of witnessing and of remembering. Purging the psychological facts of all those that 1 immediately imply the cross‐temporal identity of a person will leave plenty of grist for the mills of psychological theories of persistence conditions.
    [Show full text]
  • Survival by Redescription: Parfit on Consolation and Death
    Survival by Redescription: Parfit on Consolation and Death Patrik Hummel Friedrich-Alexander University, Erlangen-Nürnberg Abstract Parfit argues that if we come to believe his theory of personal identity, we should care differently about the future. Amongst others, we can redescribe death in ways that make it seem less bad. I consider three challenges to his reasoning. First, according to the Argument from Above, a fact, event, or state of affairs can be good or bad independently of the value or disvalue of its constituents. Death could thus be bad even if R-relatedness matters and some degree of it is gets pre- served. Second, I argue that the Extreme Claim and the Moderate Claim suggest that it is unclear whether what we are left with in Parfit’s picture is less bad than death. Third, I propose that in light of the foregoing, we might still regard Parfit’s redescription and its suggested effects on our concern as rationally permissible. However, I claim that rational permissibility does not fully deliver upon the promise that the redescription is also consoling. Despite these challenges, I con- clude that Parfit has given us valuable prompts for reconsidering our attitudes to- wards death. He has set an inspiring example for how philosophical arguments can show us new ways of thinking about ourselves and our practical concerns. Keywords: Parfit, Death, Concern, Personal identity, Rationality. 1. Introduction Parfit argues that if we come to believe his theory of personal identity, we should care differently about the future. Amongst others, we can redescribe death in ways that make it seem less bad.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy of Mind Contents
    w 页码,1/177(W) Philosophy of Mind Jaegwon Kim BROWN UNIVERSITY Westview Press A Subsidiary of Perseus Books, L.L.C. -v- Dimensions of Philosophy Series All rights reserved. Printed in the United States of America. No part of this publication may be reproduced or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopy, recording, or any information storage and retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publisher. Copyright © 1998 by Westview Press, Inc., A subsidiary of Perseus Books, L.L.C. Published in 1996 in the United States of America by Westview Press, Inc., 5500 Central Avenue, Boulder, Colorado 80301-2877, and in the United Kingdom by Westview Press, 12 Hid's Copse Road, Cumnor Hill, Oxford OX2 9JJ A CIP catalog record for this book is available from the Library of Congress. ISBN 0-8133-0775-9; ISBN 0-8133-0776-7 (pbk.) The paper used in this publication meets the requirements of the American National Standard for Permanence of Paper for Printed Library Materials Z39.48-1984. 10 9 8 -vi- Contents Preface xi 1 INTRODUCTION 1 Minds as Souls: Mental Substances , 2 Mental Properties, Events, and Processes , 5 Philosophy of Mind , 7 Supervenience, Dependence, and Minimal Physicalism , 9 Varieties of Mental Phenomena , 13 Is There a "Mark of the Mental"? 15 Further Readings , 23 Notes , 24 2 MIND AS BEHAVIOR: BEHAVIORISM 25 Reactions Against the Cartesian Conception , 26 What Is Behavior? 28 Logical Behaviorism: Hempel's Argument , 29 A Behavioral Translation of "Paul Has a Toothache," 31 Difficulties
    [Show full text]
  • To Begin at the Beginning: Wittgenstein and the Problem of Metaphysics Michael R
    Maine State Library Maine State Documents Academic Research and Dissertations Special Collections 6-2012 To Begin at the Beginning: Wittgenstein and the Problem of Metaphysics Michael R. Smith Jr. IDSVA Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalmaine.com/academic Recommended Citation Smith, Michael R. Jr., "To Begin at the Beginning: Wittgenstein and the Problem of Metaphysics" (2012). Academic Research and Dissertations. Book 2. http://digitalmaine.com/academic/2 This Text is brought to you for free and open access by the Special Collections at Maine State Documents. It has been accepted for inclusion in Academic Research and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Maine State Documents. For more information, please contact [email protected]. TO BEGIN AT THE BEGINNING: WITTGENSTEIN AND THE PROBLEM OF METAPHYSICS Michael R. Smith, Jr. Submitted to the faculty of The Institute for Doctoral Studies in the Visual Arts in partial satisfaction of the requirements for the degree Doctor of Philosophy June, 2012 Accepted by the faculty of the Institute for Doctoral Studies in the Visual Arts in partial fulfillment of the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. ______________________________ George Smith, Ph.D. Doctoral Committee ______________________________ Simonetta Moro, Ph.D. ______________________________ Sigrid Hackenberg, Ph.D. June 15, 2012 ii © 2012 Michael R. Smith, Jr. ALL RIGHTS RESERVED iii It is so difficult to find the beginning. Or, better: it is difficult to begin at the beginning. And not try to go further back. –LUDWIG WITTGENSTEIN, On Certainty Dedicated to the memory of my grandfather. iv ACKNOWLEDGMENTS Giving thanks is at once a humbling and precarious activity.
    [Show full text]
  • A Puzzle About Further Facts∗
    A Puzzle about Further Facts∗ Vincent Conitzer Duke University Abstract In metaphysics, there are a number of distinct but related questions about the existence of “further facts”—facts that are contingent relative to the physical structure of the universe. These include further facts about qualia, personal identity, and time. In this article I provide a se- quence of examples involving computer simulations, ranging from one in which the protagonist can clearly conclude such further facts exist to one that describes our own condition. This raises the question of where along the sequence (if at all) the protagonist stops being able to soundly conclude that further facts exist. Keywords: metaphysics, philosophy of mind, epistemology. Case A. Fonda has just attended an inspiring department colloquium. On her way out, she absent- mindedly takes a wrong turn and wanders into a computer lab. She approaches one of the computers. ∗This paper appears in Erkenntnis (DOI: 10.1007/s10670-018-9979-6) and is also available as arXiv:1802.01161. 1 On it, a simulation of a number of humanoid agents in a virtual universe is being run. The perspective of one of these agents—call it Alpha—is continuously displayed on the monitor. Fonda is enthralled and continues to watch from Alpha’s perspective. Because Alpha takes a large variety of interesting actions in the simulated universe, it does not take Fonda long to learn the laws of physics governing it. Moreover, Fonda—whose undergraduate degree was in computer science—can easily imagine how one would write the code for simulating the environment according to these laws.
    [Show full text]
  • Can We Do Without a Metaphysical Theory of Personal Identity in Practice? 317 Cally Distinct People
    Prolegomena 13 (2) 2014: 315–334 View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE Can We Do Without a Metaphysical Theory of provided by PhilPapers Personal Identity in Practice? RADIM BĚLOHRAD Department of Philosophy, Masaryk University in Brno, Arna Nováka 1, 602 00 Brno, Czech Republic [email protected] ORIGINAL SCIENTIFIC ARTICLE / RECEIVED: 270114 ACCEPTED: 170614 ABSTRACT: In this paper I defend the idea that we need a metaphysical theory to justify identity-related practical concerns, such as self-concern. I outline D. Parfit’s theory, in which the concerns receive a metaphysical justification. Then, I focus on two ob- jections: C. Korsgaard’s claim that the concerns are justified by the unity of agency, and M. Johnston’s contention that the concerns are prima facie justified independ- ently of a metaphysical theory. I argue that even if these theories have a point, they do not cover a range of situations in which justification may be sought. It is in these situations that a metaphysical theory may find its place. KEYWORDS: Justification, metaphysics, personal identity, practical concerns. Introduction There are at least two major trends that can be traced in the metaphysics of personal identity. One trend seeks to develop a theory of personal identity to cohere with the broader picture of the identity and persistence of spatio- temporal objects. The other attempts to develop a theory of personal identity to justify some of the practical concerns and attitudes that have tradition- ally been taken to presuppose the concept of personal identity, such as self- concern, responsibility, compensation, blame, among others.
    [Show full text]
  • I, Zombie [Penultimate Draft – December, 2000] Paul Skokowski Symbolic Systems Stanford University Stanford, CA, 94305 [email protected]
    I, Zombie [Penultimate Draft – December, 2000] Paul Skokowski Symbolic Systems Stanford University Stanford, CA, 94305 [email protected] Abstract It used to be that zombies were merely the stuff of horror fiction or Hollywood movies. But certain recent philosophical theories offer the prospect that zombies are possible. These theories argue that experiential contents, or qualia, are non-physical properties. The arguments are based on conceivability of alternate worlds in which physical laws and properties remain the same, but in which qualia either differ, or are absent altogether. This paper maintains that qualia are, on the contrary, physical properties in the world. It is shown how conceivability fails under the burden of the a posteriori identification of qualia with physical properties, and how a reasoned choice can be made between the two types of theories; which ultimately favors materialism, and rejects zombies. In the Monadology, Leibniz asks us to “Suppose that there were a machine so constructed as to produce thought, feeling and perception, we could imagine it increased in size while retaining the same proportions, so that one could enter it as one might a mill. On going inside we should only see the parts impinging on one another; we should not see anything that would explain a perception.”(Leibniz, p. 181) The lesson to take away from Leibniz is this: You can’t find thought by peering into the brain. There is nothing red or leaf-shaped in the brain when you perceive a red leaf. You have to look elsewhere for the content. The same is true for experience.
    [Show full text]
  • Arxiv:1802.01161V1 [Physics.Hist-Ph] 4 Feb 2018 Aea
    A Puzzle about Further Facts∗ Vincent Conitzer Duke University Abstract In metaphysics, there are a number of distinct but related questions about the existence of “further facts”—facts that are contingent relative to the physical structure of the universe. These include further facts about qualia, personal identity, and time. In this article I provide a se- quence of examples involving computer simulations, ranging from one in which the protagonist can clearly conclude such further facts exist to one that describes our own condition. This raises the question of where along the sequence (if at all) the protagonist stops being able to soundly conclude that further facts exist. Keywords: metaphysics, philosophy of mind, epistemology. arXiv:1802.01161v1 [physics.hist-ph] 4 Feb 2018 Case A. Fonda has just attended an inspiring department colloquium. On her way out, she absent- mindedly takes a wrong turn and wanders into a computer lab. She approaches one of the computers. ∗This paper will appear in Erkenntnis. 1 On it, a simulationof a number of humanoidagentsin a virtual universe is being run. The perspective of one of these agents—call it Alpha—is continuously displayed on the monitor. Fonda is enthralled and continues to watch from Alpha’s perspective. Because Alpha takes a large variety of interesting actions in the simulated universe, it does not take Fonda long to learn the laws of physics governing it. Moreover, Fonda—whose undergraduate degree was in computer science—can easily imagine how one would write the code for simulating the environment according to these laws. Then, she has the following thought.
    [Show full text]
  • Qualia and Introspection
    Michael Beaton Qualia and Introspection Qualia and Introspection Abstract The claim that behaviourally undetectable inverted spectra are possible has been endorsed by many physicalists. I explain why this starting point rules out standard forms of scientific explanation for qualia. The modern ‘phenomenal concept strategy’ is an updated way of defending problematic intuitions like these, but I show that it cannot help to recover standard scientific explanation. I argue that Chalmers is right: we should accept the falsity of physicalism if we accept this problematic starting point. I further argue that accepting this starting point amounts to at least implicitly endorsing certain theoretical claims about the nature of introspection. I therefore suggest that we allow ourselves to be guided, in our quest to understand qualia, by whatever independently plausible theories of introspection we have. I propose that we adopt a more moderate definition of qualia, as those introspectible properties which cannot be fully specified simply by specifying the non-controversially introspectible ‘propositional attitude’ mental states (including seeing x, experiencing x, and so on, where x is a specification of a potentially public state of affairs). Qualia thus defined may well fit plausible, naturalisable accounts of introspection. If so, such accounts have the potential to explain, rather than explain away, the problematic intuitions discussed earlier; an approach that should allow integration of our understanding of qualia with the rest of science. 1. Introduction We are concerned with the definition of consciousness; that is, we are discussing the nature of the target of explanation in our scientific or philosophical study of consciousness. As Vimal (this issue) clarifies, there are many views about how to pin the target down.
    [Show full text]