Reflections on Arrow's Theorem and Voting Rules
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Load more
Recommended publications
-
California Institute of Technology
View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Caltech Authors - Main DIVISION OF THE HUM ANITIES AND SO CI AL SCIENCES CALIFORNIA INSTITUTE OF TECHNOLOGY PASADENA, CALIFORNIA 91125 IMPLEMENTATION THEORY Thomas R. Palfrey � < a: 0 1891 u. "')/,.. () SOCIAL SCIENCE WORKING PAPER 912 September 1995 Implementation Theory Thomas R. Palfrey Abstract This surveys the branch of implementation theory initiated by Maskin (1977). Results for both complete and incomplete information environments are covered. JEL classification numbers: 025, 026 Key words: Implementation Theory, Mechanism Design, Game Theory, Social Choice Implementation Theory* Thomas R. Palfrey 1 Introduction Implementation theory is an area of research in economic theory that rigorously investi gates the correspondence between normative goals and institutions designed to achieve {implement) those goals. More precisely, given a normative goal or welfare criterion for a particular class of allocation pro blems (or domain of environments) it formally char acterizes organizational mechanisms that will guarantee outcomes consistent with that goal, assuming the outcomes of any such mechanism arise from some specification of equilibrium behavior. The approaches to this problem to date lie in the general domain of game theory because, as a matter of definition in the implementation theory litera ture, an institution is modelled as a mechanism, which is essentially a non-cooperative game. Moreover, the specific models of equilibrium behavior -
I'll Have What She's Having: Reflective Desires and Consequentialism
I'll Have What She's Having: Reflective Desires and Consequentialism by Jesse Kozler A thesis submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Bachelor of Arts with Honors Department of Philosophy in the University of Michigan 2019 Advisor: Professor James Joyce Second Reader: Professor David Manley Acknowledgments This thesis is not the product of solely my own efforts, and owes its existence in large part to the substantial support that I have received along the way from the many wonderful, brilliant people in my life. First and foremost, I want to thank Jim Joyce who eagerly agreed to advise this project and who has offered countless insights which gently prodded me to refine my approach, solidify my thoughts, and strengthen my arguments. Without him this project would never have gotten off the ground. I want to thank David Manley, who signed on to be the second reader and whose guidance on matters inside and outside of the realm of my thesis has been indispensable. Additionally, I want to thank Elizabeth Anderson, Peter Railton, and Sarah Buss who, through private discussions and sharing their own work, provided me with inspiration at times I badly needed it and encouraged me to think about previously unexamined issues. I am greatly indebted to the University of Michigan LSA Honors Program who, through their generous Honors Summer Fellowship program, made it possible for me to stay in Ann Arbor and spend my summer reading and thinking intentionally about these issues. I am especially grateful to Mika LaVaque-Manty, who whipped me into shape and instilled in me a work ethic that has been essential to the completion of this project. -
Review of Paradoxes Afflicting Various Voting Procedures Where One out of M Candidates (M ≥ 2) Must Be Elected
Dan S. Felsenthal Review of paradoxes afflicting various voting procedures where one out of m candidates (m ≥ 2) must be elected Workshop Paper Original citation: Felsenthal, Dan S. (2010) Review of paradoxes afflicting various voting procedures where one out of m candidates (m ≥ 2) must be elected. In: Assessing Alternative Voting Procedures, London School of Economics and Political Science, London, UK. This version available at: http://eprints.lse.ac.uk/27685/ Available in LSE Research Online: April 2010 © 2010 Dan S. Felsenthal LSE has developed LSE Research Online so that users may access research output of the School. Copyright © and Moral Rights for the papers on this site are retained by the individual authors and/or other copyright owners. Users may download and/or print one copy of any article(s) in LSE Research Online to facilitate their private study or for non-commercial research. You may not engage in further distribution of the material or use it for any profit-making activities or any commercial gain. You may freely distribute the URL (http://eprints.lse.ac.uk) of the LSE Research Online website. Review of Paradoxes Afflicting Various Voting Procedures Where One Out of m Candidates (m ≥ 2) Must Be Elected* Dan S. Felsenthal University of Haifa and Centre for Philosophy of Natural and Social Science London School of Economics and Political Science Revised 3 May 2010 Prepared for presentation in a symposium and a workshop on Assessing Alternative Voting Procedures Sponsored by The Leverhulme Trust (Grant F/07-004/AJ) London School of Economics and Political Science, 27 May 2010 and Chateau du Baffy, Normandy, France, 30 July – 2 August, 2010 Please send by email all communications regarding this paper to the author at: [email protected] or at [email protected] * I wish to thank Rudolf Fara and Moshé Machover for helpful comments, and Hannu Nurmi for sending me several examples contained in this paper. -
Game Theory 2021
More Mechanism Design Game Theory 2021 Game Theory 2021 Ulle Endriss Institute for Logic, Language and Computation University of Amsterdam Ulle Endriss 1 More Mechanism Design Game Theory 2021 Plan for Today In this second lecture on mechanism design we are going to generalise beyond the basic scenario of auctions|as much as we can manage: • Revelation Principle: can focus on direct-revelation mechanisms • formal model of direct-revelation mechanisms with money • incentive compatibility of the Vickrey-Clarke-Groves mechanism • other properties of VCG for special case of combinatorial auctions • impossibility of achieving incentive compatibility more generally Much of this is also (somewhat differently) covered by Nisan (2007). N. Nisan. Introduction to Mechanism Design (for Computer Scientists). In N. Nisan et al. (eds.), Algorithmic Game Theory. Cambridge University Press, 2007. Ulle Endriss 2 More Mechanism Design Game Theory 2021 Reminder Last time we saw four auction mechanisms for selling a single item: English, Dutch, first-price sealed-bid, Vickrey. The Vickrey auction was particularly interesting: • each bidder submits a bid in a sealed envelope • the bidder with the highest bid wins, but pays the price of the second highest bid (unless it's below the reservation price) It is a direct-revelation mechanism (unlike English and Dutch auctions) and it is incentive-compatible, i.e., truth-telling is a dominant strategy (unlike for Dutch and FPSB auctions). Ulle Endriss 3 More Mechanism Design Game Theory 2021 The Revelation Principle Revelation Principle: Any outcome that is implementable in dominant strategies via some mechanism can also be implemented by means of a direct-revelation mechanism making truth-telling a dominant strategy. -
Designing Mechanisms to Make Welfare- Improving Strategies Focal∗
Designing Mechanisms to Make Welfare- Improving Strategies Focal∗ Daniel E. Fragiadakis Peter Troyan Texas A&M University University of Virginia Abstract Many institutions use matching algorithms to make assignments. Examples include the allocation of doctors, students and military cadets to hospitals, schools and branches, respec- tively. Most of the market design literature either imposes strong incentive constraints (such as strategyproofness) or builds mechanisms that, while more efficient than strongly incentive compatible alternatives, require agents to play potentially complex equilibria for the efficiency gains to be realized in practice. Understanding that the effectiveness of welfare-improving strategies relies on the ease with which real-world participants can find them, we carefully design an algorithm that we hypothesize will make such strategies focal. Using a lab experiment, we show that agents do indeed play the intended focal strategies, and doing so yields higher overall welfare than a common alternative mechanism that gives agents dominant strategies of stating their preferences truthfully. Furthermore, we test a mech- anism from the field that is similar to ours and find that while both yield comparable levels of average welfare, our algorithm performs significantly better on an individual level. Thus, we show that, if done carefully, this type of behavioral market design is a worthy endeavor that can most promisingly be pursued by a collaboration between institutions, matching theorists, and behavioral and experimental economists. JEL Classification: C78, C91, C92, D61, D63, Keywords: dictatorship, indifference, matching, welfare, efficiency, experiments ∗We are deeply indebted to our graduate school advisors Fuhito Kojima, Muriel Niederle and Al Roth for count- less conversations and encouragement while advising us on this project. -
Trump, Condorcet and Borda: Voting Paradoxes in the 2016 Republican Presidential Primaries
Munich Personal RePEc Archive Trump, Condorcet and Borda: Voting paradoxes in the 2016 Republican presidential primaries Kurrild-Klitgaard, Peter University of Copenhagen 15 December 2016 Online at https://mpra.ub.uni-muenchen.de/75598/ MPRA Paper No. 75598, posted 15 Dec 2016 16:00 UTC Trump, Condorcet and Borda: Voting paradoxes in the 2016 Republican presidential primaries1 PETER KURRILD-KLITGAARD Dept. of Political Science, University of Copenhagen Abstract. The organization of US presidential elections make them potentially vulnerable to so-called “voting paradoxes”, identified by social choice theorists but rarely documented empirically. The presence of a record high number of candidates in the 2016 Republican Party presidential primaries may have made this possibility particularly latent. Using polling data from the primaries we identify two possible cases: Early in the pre-primary (2015) a cyclical majority may have existed in Republican voters’ preferences between Bush, Cruz and Walker—thereby giving a rare example of the Condorcet Paradox. Furthermore, later polling data (March 2016) suggests that while Trump (who achieved less than 50% of the total Republican primary vote) was the Plurality Winner, he could have been beaten in pairwise contests by at least one other candidate—thereby exhibiting a case of the Borda Paradox. The cases confirm the empirical relevance of the theoretical voting paradoxes and the importance of voting procedures. Key words: Social choice; Condorcet Paradox; Borda Paradox; US presidential election 2016; Jeb Bush; Chris Christie; Ted Cruz; John Kasich; Marco Rubio; Donald Trump; Scot Walker; voting system. JEL-codes: D71; D72. 1. Introduction Since the 1950s social choice theory has questioned the possibility of aggregating individual preferences to straightforward, meaningful collective choices (Arrow [1951] 1963). -
Strategyproof Exchange with Multiple Private Endowments
Proceedings of the Twenty-Eighth AAAI Conference on Artificial Intelligence Strategyproof Exchange with Multiple Private Endowments Taiki Todo, Haixin Sun, Makoto Yokoo Dept. of Informatics Kyushu University Motooka 744, Fukuoka, JAPAN ftodo, sunhaixin, [email protected] Abstract efficient and individually rational. Moreover, it is the only We study a mechanism design problem for exchange rule that satisfies those three properties (Ma 1994). Due to economies where each agent is initially endowed with these advantages, TTC has been attracting much attention a set of indivisible goods and side payments are not al- from both economists and computer scientists. lowed. We assume each agent can withhold some en- In this paper we consider exchange economies where each dowments, as well as misreport her preference. Under this assumption, strategyproofness requires that for each agent is endowed with a set of multiple goods, instead of agent, reporting her true preference with revealing all a single good. Under that model, Pareto efficiency, indi- her endowments is a dominant strategy, and thus implies vidual rationality, and strategyproofness cannot be simulta- individual rationality. Our objective in this paper is to neously satisfied (Sonmez¨ 1999). Therefore, one main re- analyze the effect of such private ownership in exchange search direction on exchanges with multiple endowments is economies with multiple endowments. As fundamental to achieve strategyproof rules that guarantee a limited notion results, we first show that the revelation principle holds of efficiency. In particular, Papai´ (2003) defined a class of under a natural assumption and that strategyproofness exchange rules and gave a characterization by strategyproof- and Pareto efficiency are incompatible even under the ness and individual rationality with some other weak effi- lexicographic preference domain. -
Proportionality and Strategyproofness in Multiwinner Elections
Session 43: Social Choice Theory 3 AAMAS 2018, July 10-15, 2018, Stockholm, Sweden Proportionality and Strategyproofness in Multiwinner Elections Dominik Peters University of Oxford Oxford, UK [email protected] ABSTRACT focussed on cases where there are no parties, and preferences are Multiwinner voting rules can be used to select a fixed-size com- expressed directly over the candidates [23]. The latter setting allows mittee from a larger set of candidates. We consider approval-based for applications in areas outside the political sphere, such as in committee rules, which allow voters to approve or disapprove can- group recommendation systems. didates. In this setting, several voting rules such as Proportional To formalise the requirement of proportionality in this party-free Approval Voting (PAV) and Phragmén’s rules have been shown to setting, it is convenient to consider the case where input preferences produce committees that are proportional, in the sense that they are given as approval ballots: each voter reports a set of candidates proportionally represent voters’ preferences; all of these rules are that they find acceptable. Even for this simple setting, there isa strategically manipulable by voters. On the other hand, a generalisa- rich variety of rules that exhibit different behaviour [31], and this tion of Approval Voting gives a non-proportional but strategyproof setting gives rise to a rich variety of axioms. voting rule. We show that there is a fundamental tradeoff between One natural way of selecting a committee of k candidates when these two properties: we prove that no multiwinner voting rule can given approval ballots is to extend Approval Voting (AV): for each simultaneously satisfy a weak form of proportionality (a weakening of the m candidates, count how many voters approve them (their of justified representation) and a weak form of strategyproofness. -
Political Knowledge and the Paradox of Voting
Political Knowledge and the Paradox of Voting Edited by Sofia Magdalena Olofsson We have long known that Americans pay local elections less attention than they do elections for the Presidency and Congress. A recent Portland State University study showed that voter turnout in ten of America’s 30 largest cities sits on average at less than 15% of eligible voters. Just pause and think about this. The 55% of voting age citizens who cast a ballot in last year’s presidential election – already a two-decade low and a significant drop from the longer-term average of 65-80% – still eclipses by far the voter turnout at recent mayoral elections in Dallas (6%), Fort Worth (6%), and Las Vegas (9%). What is more, data tells us that local voter turnout is only getting worse. Look at America’s largest city: New York. Since the 1953 New York election, when 93% of residents voted, the city’s mayoral contests saw a steady decline, with a mere 14% of the city’s residents voting in the last election. Though few might want to admit it, these trends suggest that an unspoken hierarchy exists when it comes to elections. Atop this electoral hierarchy are national elections, elections that are widely considered the most politically, economically, and culturally significant. Extensively covered by the media, they are viewed as high-stakes moral contests that naturally attract the greatest public interest. Next, come state elections: though still important compared to national elections, their political prominence, media coverage, and voter turnout is already waning. At the bottom of this electoral hierarchy are local elections that, as data tells us, a vast majority of Americans now choose not to vote in. -
Economic Growth, Capitalism and Unknown Economic Paradoxes
Sustainability 2012, 4, 2818-2837; doi:10.3390/su4112818 OPEN ACCESS sustainability ISSN 2071-1050 www.mdpi.com/journal/sustainability Article Economic Growth, Capitalism and Unknown Economic Paradoxes Stasys Girdzijauskas *, Dalia Streimikiene and Andzela Mialik Vilnius University, Kaunas Faculty of Humanities, Muitines g. 8, LT-44280, Kaunas, Lithuania; E-Mails: [email protected] (D.S.); [email protected] (A.M.) * Author to whom correspondence should be addressed; E-Mail: [email protected]; Tel.: +370-37-422-566; Fax: +370-37-423-222. Received: 28 August 2012; in revised form: 9 October 2012 / Accepted: 16 October 2012 / Published: 24 October 2012 Abstract: The paper deals with failures of capitalism or free market and presents the results of economic analysis by applying a logistic capital growth model. The application of a logistic growth model for analysis of economic bubbles reveals the fundamental causes of bubble formation—economic paradoxes related with phenomena of saturated markets: the paradox of growing returnability and the paradoxes of debt and leverage trap. These paradoxes occur exclusively in the saturated markets and cause the majority of economic problems of recent days including overproduction, economic bubbles and cyclic economic development. Unfortunately, these paradoxes have not been taken into account when dealing with the current failures of capitalism. The aim of the paper is to apply logistic capital growth models for the analysis of economic paradoxes having direct impact on the capitalism failures such as economic bubbles, economic crisis and unstable economic growth. The analysis of economic paradoxes and their implication son failures of capitalism provided in the paper presents the new approach in developing policies aimed at increasing economic growth stability and overcoming failures of capitalism. -
A Phase Transition in Arrow's Theorem
A Phase Transition in Arrow's Theorem Frederic Koehler∗ Elchanan Mossely Abstract Arrow's Theorem concerns a fundamental problem in social choice theory: given the individual preferences of members of a group, how can they be aggregated to form rational group preferences? Arrow showed that in an election between three or more candidates, there are situations where any voting rule satisfying a small list of natural \fairness" axioms must produce an apparently irrational intransitive outcome. Fur- thermore, quantitative versions of Arrow's Theorem in the literature show that when voters choose rankings in an i.i.d. fashion, the outcome is intransitive with non-negligible probability. It is natural to ask if such a quantitative version of Arrow's Theorem holds for non-i.i.d. models. To answer this question, we study Arrow's Theorem under a natural non-i.i.d. model of voters inspired by canonical models in statistical physics; indeed, a version of this model was previously introduced by Raffaelli and Marsili in the physics literature. This model has a parameter, temperature, that prescribes the correlation between different voters. We show that the behavior of Arrow's Theorem in this model undergoes a striking phase transition: in the entire high temperature regime of the model, a Quantitative Arrow's Theorem holds showing that the probability of paradox for any voting rule satisfying the axioms is non-negligible; this is tight because the probability of paradox under pairwise majority goes to zero when approaching the critical temperature, and becomes exponentially small in the number of voters beyond it. -
Relaxing Strategyproofness in One-Sided Matching
Relaxing Strategyproofness in One-sided Matching TIMO MENNLE and SVEN SEUKEN University of Zurich We consider the one-sided matching problem, where agents must be matched to indivisible ob- jects. Our first result is a novel characterization of strategyproof mechanisms by three intuitive axioms. Furthermore, we introduce partial strategyproofness, a new relaxation of strategyproof- ness that bridges the gap between full and weak strategyproofness. Partial strategyproofness finds application in the incentive analysis of non-strategyproof mechanisms, such as Probabilistic Serial, different variants of the Boston mechanism, and hybrid mechanisms. In this letter, we summarize the main results from [Mennle and Seuken 2014a] and demonstrate how they can be used for the design and analysis of matching mechanisms.1 Categories and Subject Descriptors: J.4.a [Social and Behavioral Sciences]: Economics General Terms: Economics; Theory Additional Key Words and Phrases: Matching, Mechanism Design, Strategyproofness 1. INTRODUCTION The (probabilistic) one-sided matching problem is concerned with the allocation of indivisible goods to self-interested agents with privately known preferences in domains where monetary transfers are not permitted. Such problems often arise in situations that are of great importance to peoples' lives. For example, students must be matched to schools, teachers to training programs, or tenants to houses. Strategyproof mechanisms, such as Random Serial Dictatorship (RSD), are ap- pealing because they make truthful reporting a dominant strategy for all agents. Participation in the mechanism becomes an easy task as there is no need for delib- eration about the best response, thus reducing cognitive costs for the agents and (likely) endowing the mechanism with correct information about agents' preferences.