6 X 10.Long New.P65

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

6 X 10.Long New.P65 Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-87266-9 - The Cambridge Companion to Boethius Edited by John Marenbon Index More information index: references to boethius’ works SURVIVING WORKS On Division (D), 36–7, 44, 133, 153 On Hypothetical Syllogisms (SH), 4, TEXTBOOKS ON THE LIBERAL ARTS: 1, 10 36–8, 44, 59–60, 67–78, 80, 222 On Arithmetic, 10, 28, 230 On Music, 10, 28 WORKS ON TOPICAL REASONING: 4 TRANSLATIONS OF ARISTOTLE AND Commentary on Cicero’s Topics, 36, 78–9 133 139 PORPHYRY: 3, 28, 35–7, 78, 82, 164 , , On Topical Differentiae, 36–8, 68–70, 78–80 103 159 LOGICAL COMMENTARIES: 1, 3–4, 6, 35–6, , , 56, 183 their sources, 46–9 THEOLOGICAL TREATISES (OPUSCULA Commentary on Aristotle’s Categories SACRA): 4–7, 30, 39, 105, 155–7, (CAT), 31, 36–7, 40–2, 45–9, 85, 101, 162–3, 197, 205 103, 130, 153, 176 Boethius’s authorship proved, 241 Commentary on Aristotle’s On On the Trinity (OS I), 5, 106–13, 115, Interpretation, prima editio (1IN), 121, 129, 133–4, 136–7, 139, 141, 36–7, 45–9, 101, 204, 207, 211, 213, 144, 148–51, 156–62, 166, 169, 222, 224 171, 173 Commentary on Aristotle’s On Whether the Father … (OS II), 113–15, 117 Interpretation, secunda editio (2IN), De hebdomadibus (OS III), 5, 59–60, 106, 36–7, 43–9, 60–7, 85–93, 95, 99, 207, 126, 129, 137, 152, 156–7, 160–3, 170, 211, 213–14, 222–5 172–3, 177 Commentary on Porphyry’s Isagoge, On Faith (OS IV), 115–18, 204 prima editio (1IS), 23, 45, 85, 126, 230 authorship of, 33, 115–16 Commentary on Porphyry’s Isagoge, Against Eutyches and Nestorius (OS V), 5, secunda editio (2IS), 37–40, 45, 57–8, 30, 118, 121–4, 129, 134–6, 141, 144, 85, 93–7, 130, 139, 153, 169, 176, 202, 146–8, 151, 157–8, 160, 164 230, 261–2 circumstances of composition, 105–6, 118 LOGICAL MONOGRAPHS: 1, 3–4, 6, 50, 56 Commentaries on the Opuscula sacra: Introduction to Categorical Syllogisms see Clarembald of Arras; Gilbert of (ISC), 36–7, 44, 64, 66, 245 Poitiers; John Scottus (Eriugena) On Categorical Syllogisms (SC), 36–7, (pseudo-); Thierry of Chartres (and 44, 64 his circle) 340 © Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-87266-9 - The Cambridge Companion to Boethius Edited by John Marenbon Index More information Index: References to Boethius’ works 341 THE CONSOLATION OF PHILOSOPHY (C): 1, I, Prose 4: 15, 18, 22, 24, 184, 206, 232, 3, 5–9, 19–20, 181–3, 207, 214, 235 235, 237, 240, 251, 253 and dialogue-form, 27, 230–1 I, Metrum 5: 193, 200, 203, 205, 233 author and persona, 237 I, Prose 5: 15, 183–5, 191–2, 194, 203, 206, parodied, 286 246, 249 poetry and prose in, 181–2, 232–4, 236 I, Metrum 6: 183 prosimetric form imitated, 286 I, Prose 6: 183–6, 188, 192–4, 197–8, 200, title perhaps not Boethius’ own, 24 205, 239, 253 unfinished?, 239–40 I, Metrum 7: 185, 194 see also literary form, philosophy in relation to Book 2 commentaries on 255–78 II, Prose 1: 181, 183–5, 200, 233, 248 and see Anonymous of St Gallen, II,Prose2: 29, 181, 185, 188, 200, Arend de Keysere 232, 248 Arnoul Greban II, Prose 3: 18, 183–4, 187, 248 Badius Ascenius II, Prose 4: 23, 184, 185–7, 189, 194, 196–7, Bernartius, Johannes 240, 242, 250, 252–3 Bertius, Petrus II, Prose 5: 183–4, 186–8, 194–5, 240, 250 Cally, Pierre II, Metrum 5: 187 Denys the Carthusian II, Prose 6: 24, 185, 187–9, 253 Dunstan, Giovanni Travesio II, Metrum 6: 187, 189, 194 Guglielmo da Cortemilia II,Prose7: 23–4, 187, 189, 204, 240, Murmellius, Joannes 250, 253 Nicholas Trevet II, Metrum 7: 187, 189, 241, 251 Pierre d’Ailly II, Metrum 8, 285, 292, 295 Pietro da Muglio pseudo-Thomas Aquinas Book 3 Remigius of Auxerre III, Prose 1: 183, 188, 194, 230, 240 Renier of St Truiden III, Metrum 1: 183, 188, 230 Sitzmannus, Theodorus III, Prose 2: 187–8, 190, 194, 196, 240 Vallinus III, Metrum 2: 204, 284 Vatican commentary III, Prose 3: 185, 187–8, 194, 196, 253, 285 William of Aragon III, Metrum 3: 187, 245 William of Conches III, Prose 4: 187–9, 196 William Wheteley III, Metrum 4:187, 189, 245 translations of, 7, 255 and see Alfred, III, Prose 5: 187–9, 196 King III, Metrum 5: 187, 189, 245 Chaucer, Geoffrey III, Prose 6: 187–9, 196 Jean de Meun III, Metrum 6: 187, 189, 245, 259 Livre de Boece de Consolacion III, Prose 7: 187–8, 196 Notker of St Gallen III, Metrum 7: 187, 240, 245 Von Rosenroth, Knorr III, Prose 8: 187–8, 190 III, Prose 9: 182, 188–9, 194, 205, 240 Book 1 III, Metrum 9 (‘Oquiperpetua’): 181, I, Metrum 1: 23, 25, 194, 229, 247 190–1, 194, 233, 237–9, 242, 247, I, Prose 1: 23, 25, 194, 231–3 251, 258–60 I, Metrum 2: 189, 194, 233 commentaries on, 259, 271–2, 297 I, Prose 2: 185–6, 192, 298 III, Prose 10: 182, 186–7, 194–7, 284 I,Prose3: 23, 25, 190, 193, 232, 240, III, Prose 11: 136, 182, 184, 188, 190–4, 246, 250 197–8, 249, 251, 284 © Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-87266-9 - The Cambridge Companion to Boethius Edited by John Marenbon Index More information 342 Index: References to Boethius’ works III,Metrum11: 190–2, 246, 252, 259, V, Prose 2: 185, 194, 225, 242, 273 271, 273 V, Metrum 2: 251 III,Prose12: 182, 184–5, 188, 193–5, V, Prose 3: 183, 194, 214–16, 218, 220, 197–8, 203, 206, 251 224–5, 251, 273, 292 III, Metrum 12: 247, 253, 260 V, Metrum 3: 183, 191, 204 V,Prose4: 154, 183, 140, 193–4, Book 4 207, 214–16, 218–19, 221, 223, IV, Prose 1: 25, 184, 192, 194, 199, 248 226–7, 268 IV, Metrum 1: 184, 190, 192–5, 248 V, Metrum 4: 190, 204, 259 IV, Prose 2: 185, 187–8, 195, 197–9, 205, 253 V, Prose 5: 50, 194, 214–17, 220–1, 226 IV, Metrum 2: 189, 206 V, Metrum 5: 204 IV, Prose 3: 186, 194–5, 198–9, 204, 240, V, Prose 6: 194, 203–4, 208, 214–21, 225, 250, 253 242, 251, 253 IV, Metrum 3: 247, 260 4 186 194–5 198–9 239 242 IV, Prose : , , , , LOST OR PLANNED WORKS IV, Prose 5: 194, 248 IV,Prose6: 181, 184–5, 191, 194–5, Breviarium of Aristotle’s On 199–200, 203–4, 225, 231, 233, 243, Interpretation, 44 248, 250 Bucolic Verse (Carmen bucolicum), 230 IV, Prose 7: 181, 184–5, 200 Commentary on Aristotle’s Categories, IV, Metrum 7: 245, 253, 260 secunda editio, 36–7, 41–2, 95–6, 103 Commentary on Aristotle’s Physics, 35–6 Book 5 Commentary on Aristotle’s Posterior V, Prose 1: 194, 200, 239 Analytics, 38 V, Metrum 1: 185, 194 Commentary on Aristotle’s Topics, 38, 78 © Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-87266-9 - The Cambridge Companion to Boethius Edited by John Marenbon Index More information general index Where an endnote simply gives a reference to what is mentioned in the text, the entry refers to the page of the text; where an endnote introduces fresh references or material, its own page is given. Medieval authors are listed under their Christian names (e.g. Thomas Aquinas), though not where they are usually known by surnames (for instance, Chaucer). Abaelard, see Peter Abelard Alexander of Aphrodisias, 3, 43, 45, 52, Abelard, see Peter Abelard 94, 102, 126, 128, 213, 216 abstraction, 59–60, 94–5, 99, 262 commentary on Aristotle’s Prior Acacian schism, 17 Analytics, 305 accidents, 58–9, 109, 134, 137–8 On Fate, 224–5 accidental change, 135 Alexandria, 29, 236 individual, 153 Alfred, King, translation of Consolation, inseparable, 59–60, 69, 77, 79, 139–44, 257, 277, 280, 308 148–50 Amalasuintha (daughter of Theoderic), Acilius Severus, 254 28–9 ACN, see modality, absolute and Ambrose of Milan, 14, 127 conditional necessity Ambrosiaster, 127 Acta Pauli et Theclae, 235 Ammonius, 3, 29, 43, 250 Adam, 299–300; and see language, relationship with Boethius’ Adamic origin of commentaries, 211 Aelfric, Homilies, 280 commentary on Aristotle’s Categories, akrateia, see will, weakness of 27, 46, 48, 101, 143 Alan of Lille, The Lament of Nature, 283, commentary on Aristotle’s On 286–90, 296 Interpretation, 55, 92, 100, 211, Theological Rules, 163 216–17, 220, 222–7 Alberic of Paris, 81–2 commentary on Aristotle’s Prior Albert the Great, De bono, 175 Analytics, 305 Albertism in the fifteenth commentary on Porphyry’s Isagoge, 52 century, 268 Anaxagoras, 21 Albinus (Senator), 19 Andronicus, 46–7 Alcuin, 157, 257 Anecdoton Holderi, 105, 116, 125, 197, De vera philosophia (preface to De 230, 241, 307, 310 grammatica), 279 angels, 194 ‘O mea cella’, 279 good and bad, 266 343 © Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-87266-9 - The Cambridge Companion to Boethius Edited by John Marenbon Index More information 344 General index Anonymous of St Gallen, Commentary Arrigo da Settimello, Elegy, 286 on the Consolation, 257, 259 ars vetus/nova, see logic, logica vetus/ Anonymus Valesianus, 32, 237 nova Anscombe, Elizabeth (G.E.M.), 210 artefacts, 135–6, 148 Anselm of Canterbury, 169 Aspasius, 46–7 aphorismenos, can mean ‘separately’ or Asterius (consul in 494), 13, 15 ‘indefinitely’, 211 Asztalos, Monika, 52, 103, 309 Apuleius, 235 Athens, 29 Aquinas, see Thomas Aquinas Augustine, 8, 109, 117–18, 122, 125, 230, Archytas of Tarentum, 41 249, 269, 273, 297, 307 Arend de Keysere, 268 and Aristotle’s Categories, 26–7, 109–11, arguments, types of, see topical 113, 164 argumentation; syllogistic at Cassiciacum, 243, 245 Arianism, 17, 20, 155, 173, 249 pseudo-Augustine, see Categoriae Aristotle, 26, 34–5, 40–1, 101–10, 126, Decem 129, 171, 184 City of God, 22–3, 33, 126–7, 225–6 harmony with Plato, 3–4, 6, 10, 25–6, Confessions, 25–7, 204, 232, 252 34–5, 46, 310 Enchiridion, 128 idea of science, 162–3 On the Psalms, 252 Categories, 26, 40, 155, 159, 223 On the Trinity, 126 Categories commentaries, 27 and see Soliloquy, 231 Ammonius, Boethius, Porphyry, To Simplicianus, 226 Simplicius Augustus, 14
Recommended publications
  • Iconoclasm: a Christian Dilemma
    ICONOCLASM: A CHRISTIAN DILEMMA - A BYZANTINE CONTROVERSY By STEPHEN CHARLES STEACY •• Bachelor of Arts Oklahoma State University Stillwater, Oklahoma 1969 Submitted to the Faculty of the Graduate College of the Oklahoma State University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Degree of MASTER OF ARTS December, 1978 ICONOCLASM: A CHRISTIAN DILEMMA - A BYZANTINE CONTROVERSY Thesis Approved: '. ~- Dean of the Graduate College 1019541 ii P~F~E This thesis is concerned with Iconoclasm, the religious upheaval which troubled the Byzantine conscience for over a century. There have been numerous theories adduced by his­ torians to account for this phenomenon. It is the purpose of this study to view the varying interpretations, analyze their shortcomings, and to put forth a different view of the controversy, one that more adequately expresses the deeply rooted religious nature of the movement, a movement not only of the eighth and ninth centuries but an idea which was nurtured in fertile soil of the Old Testament and Apostolic Christianity. The author wishes to express heartfelt appreciation to his thesis adviser, Dr. George Jewsbury, whose unflagging solicitude, support, and inspiration were instrumental in the preparation of this work. A note of thanks is given to Mrs. Karen Hoyer, whose typing expertise, in the final analysis, made the difference between success and failure. iii TABLE OF CONTENTS Chapter Page I. INTRODUCTION AND HISTORIOGRAPHICAL ESSAY 1 II. THEOLOGICAL AND PHILOSOPHICAL COURSES OF THE CONTROVERSY. • • . • . • • . • . 13 Genesis of the Cult of Icons .•.• 13 The Scriptures as the Foundation of Iconoclasm. 26 Precursors of ·the Iconoclast Movement . 30 Origen . 31 Eusebius .
    [Show full text]
  • THE SENTENCES of SEXTUS Wisdom Literature from the Ancient World
    THE SENTENCES OF SEXTUS Wisdom Literature from the Ancient World Leo G. Perdue, General Editor Reinhard Gregor Kratz, Associate Editor Area Editors Bendt Alster Pancratius C. Beentjes Katharine Dell Edward L. Greenstein Victor Hurowitz John Kloppenborg Michael Kolarcik Manfred Oeming Bernd U. Schipper Günter Stemberger Loren T. Stuckenbruck Number 1 THE SENTENCES OF SEXTUS THE SENTENCES OF SEXTUS By Walter T. Wilson Society of Biblical Literature Atlanta THE SENTENCES OF SEXTUS Copyright © 2012 by the Society of Biblical Literature All rights reserved. No part of this work may be reproduced or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying and recording, or by means of any information storage or retrieval system, except as may be expressly permit- ted by the 1976 Copyright Act or in writing from the publisher. Requests for permission should be addressed in writing to the Rights and Permissions O! ce, Society of Biblical Literature, 825 Houston Mill Road, Atlanta, GA 30329 USA. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Sentences of Sextus. The sentences of Sextus / Walter T. Wilson. p. cm. — (Wisdom literature from the ancient world ; number 1) ISBN 978-1-58983-719-5 (paper binding : alk. paper) — ISBN 978-1-58983-720-1 (electronic format) — ISBN 978-1-58983-727-0 (hardcover binding : alk. paper) 1. Christian life—Early works to 1800. 2. Sentences of Sextus. I. Sextus, Pythagoreus. II. Wilson, Walter T. III. Sentences of Sextus. English. 2012. IV. Sentences of Sextus. Greek. 2012. V. Title. VI. Series: Wisdom literature from the ancient world ; no. 1. BV4500.S4913 2012 248.4—dc23 2012041820 Printed on acid-free, recycled paper conforming to ANSI/NISO Z39.48-1992 (R1997) and ISO 9706:1994 standards for paper permanence.
    [Show full text]
  • Epicurus on Socrates in Love, According to Maximus of Tyre Ágora
    Ágora. Estudos Clássicos em debate ISSN: 0874-5498 [email protected] Universidade de Aveiro Portugal CAMPOS DAROCA, F. JAVIER Nothing to be learnt from Socrates? Epicurus on Socrates in love, according to Maximus of Tyre Ágora. Estudos Clássicos em debate, núm. 18, 2016, pp. 99-119 Universidade de Aveiro Aveiro, Portugal Available in: http://www.redalyc.org/articulo.oa?id=321046070005 How to cite Complete issue Scientific Information System More information about this article Network of Scientific Journals from Latin America, the Caribbean, Spain and Portugal Journal's homepage in redalyc.org Non-profit academic project, developed under the open access initiative Nothing to be learnt from Socrates? Epicurus on Socrates in love, according to Maximus of Tyre Não há nada a aprender com Sócrates? Epicuro e os amores de Sócrates, segundo Máximo de Tiro F. JAVIER CAMPOS DAROCA (University of Almería — Spain) 1 Abstract: In the 32nd Oration “On Pleasure”, by Maximus of Tyre, a defence of hedonism is presented in which Epicurus himself comes out in person to speak in favour of pleasure. In this defence, Socrates’ love affairs are recalled as an instance of virtuous behaviour allied with pleasure. In this paper we will explore this rather strange Epicurean portrayal of Socrates as a positive example. We contend that in order to understand this depiction of Socrates as a virtuous lover, some previous trends in Platonism should be taken into account, chiefly those which kept the relationship with the Hellenistic Academia alive. Special mention is made of Favorinus of Arelate, not as the source of the contents in the oration, but as the author closest to Maximus both for his interest in Socrates and his rhetorical (as well as dialectical) ways in philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • La Prière Dans La Tradition Platonicienne
    446 Recensiones La prière dans la tradition platonicienne TIMOTIN, ANDREI (2017). La prière dans la tradition platonicienne, de Platon à Proclus. RRR 22. Turnhout: Brepols. 296 pp., 80,00€ [ISBN 978-2-5035- 5748-20]. GARY M. GURTLER, S. J. Boston College [email protected] This book provides a marvellous retrieval of Greek philosophical reflection on the nature of prayer in the wider context of Greek culture and its evolving un- derstanding of the relation of the human and the divine. It thus joins a remarkable project overcoming the scholarly assumptions of the last two centuries. This project is international and multilingual, as Andrei Timotin (AT) makes clear in his notes and bibliography here and his collaboration with John Dillon in Platonic Theories of Prayer (2016). The bibliography, spanning 20 pages, has references in English, French, German, and Italian. Where the religious dimension of ancient thought had been relegated to the fringes, it has now become a central topic. Where the prayers in Platonic dialogues had been passed over in silence, they are now examined with all the resources of modern scholarly method. AT’s approach is both chronological, from Plato to Proclus, and thematic, examining philosophy, religion, and rhetoric. https://doi.org/10.20318/arys.2019.5005 - Arys, 17, 2019 [446-449] issn 1575-166x Recensiones 447 Beginning with Plato, AT divides his attention between the discussion in the Laws and the Republic, with the relation of prayer to the religious tradition and the role of civic cult, and the examination of Homer and religious poetry. In both in- stances, AT shows that Plato sees his task as defining the proper prayer for indi- viduals and cities and critiquing those expressions of prayer that fall outside what is proper, whether in the writings of the poets or the attempts of the immoral to influ- ence the gods.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy in the Roman Empire: Ethics, Politics and Society: Ethics
    PHILOSOPHY IN THE ROMAN EMPIRE Drawing on unusually broad range of sources for this study of Imperial period philosophical thought, Michael Trapp examines the central issues of personal morality, political theory, and social organization: philosophy as the pursuit of self- improvement and happiness; the conceptualization and management of emotion; attitudes and obligations to others; ideas of the self and personhood; constitutional theory and the ruler; the constituents and working of the good community. Texts and thinkers discussed range from Alexander of Aphrodisias, Aspasius and Alcinous, via Hierocles, Seneca, Musonius, Epictetus, Plutarch and Diogenes of Oenoanda, to Dio Chrysostom, Apuleius, Lucian, Maximus of Tyre, Pythagorean pseudepigrapha, and the Tablet of Cebes. The distinctive doctrines of the individual philosophical schools are outlined, but also the range of choice that collectively they presented to the potential philosophical ‘convert’, and the contexts in which that choice was encountered. Finally Trapp turns his attention to the status of philosophy itself as an element of the elite culture of the period, and to the ways in which philosophical values may have posed a threat to other prevalent schemes of value; Trapp argues that the idea of ‘philosophical opposition’, though useful, needs to be substantially modified and extended. To NGD, SWBT and NWBT Philosophy in the Roman Empire Ethics, Politics and Society MICHAEL TRAPP Kings College London, UK First published 2007 by Ashgate Publishing Published 2016 by Routledge 2 Park Square, Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon OX14 4RN 711 Third Avenue, New York, NY 10017, USA Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group, an informa business Copyright © 2007 Michael Trapp Michael Trapp has asserted his moral right under the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act, 1988, to be identified as the author of this work.
    [Show full text]
  • Manetti's Socrates and the Socrateses of Antiquity
    Manetti's Socrates and the Socrateses of Antiquity The Harvard community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters Citation Hankins, James. 2008. Manetti’s Socrates and the Socrateses of antiquity. In Dignitas et excellentia hominis: Atti del convegno internazionale di studi su Giannozzo Manetti, Ed. Stefano U. Baldassarri, 203-219. Florence: Le Lettere. Citable link http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:2961810 Terms of Use This article was downloaded from Harvard University’s DASH repository, and is made available under the terms and conditions applicable to Other Posted Material, as set forth at http:// nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:dash.current.terms-of- use#LAA Manetti’s Socrates and the Socrateses of Antiquity Towards the middle of his Life of Socrates (c.1440), the first biography of the great philosopher written since antiquity, Giannozzo Manetti roundly states that the opinions attributed to Socrates in the books of Plato were genuine, and that furthermore they were shared by Plato too: Nullum igitur doctrinae [Socratis] apud nos monumentum extat, nisi si quis forte Platonis libros Socratis, magistri sui, monumenta appellare vellet. In quibus fere omnibus, cum Socrates loquens exprimatur, eas Socratis sententias fuisse vere simul atque eleganter dici potest quae in Platonis dialogis illius verbis efferuntur; et versa vice eas Platonis opiniones extitisse dicemus, quae ex ore Socratis pronuntiantur.1 The remark is one that a modern classical scholar could not but regard as staggeringly naïve, given the shelves full of books that have been written over the last two centuries attempting to recover the historical Socrates and, in particular, to distinguish his teaching from that of Plato.
    [Show full text]
  • Maximus of Tyre What God Is According to Plato
    Maximus of Tyre What God is According to Plato Translated by Thomas Taylor the “Platonist” in The Dissertations of Maximus Tyrius (1805). Taylor’s notes have been omitted, and there have been some changes to the wording and punctuation to make the reading somewhat easier. This document is in the public domain. platonic-philosophy.org In disputing concerning dæmons, I can bear the opposition of arguments, I can endure the contention, and do not think that the conduct of him who doubts with himself, or with another, concerning the existence, essence, and magnitude of a dæmoniacal nature, is in any respect dire, erroneous, and absurd. For here indeed the name is uncertain; the essence of that which is investigated is unapparent, and its power is the subject of doubt. But now, in speaking of divinity, how shall I act? By what beauty of words, by what light from the clearest appellations, or by what harmony of composition, shall I be able to exhibit to myself and others that which is now investigated? For if Plato, who was the most eloquent of all men, even though compared with Homer himself, is not, in what he says respecting divinity, sufficiently understood by every one, and indeed there are those who enquire of others what the opinion of Plato was on this subject – if this be the case, he who is endued but with a small portion of intellect, will scarcely dare to engage in this investigation; unless we wish to imitate the conduct of him who should procure necessary drink for one thirsty, not from a pure and abundant fountain though present – a fountain to the sight most pleasant, to the taste most sweet, and for nutrition most prolific – but from a fountain debile and in no respect to be compared with the former.
    [Show full text]
  • “ „Knowing As We Are Known‟ in Confessions 10 and Other
    “ „Knowing as we are Known‟ in Confessions 10 and Other Philosophical, Augustinian and Christian Obedience to the Delphic Gnothi Seauton from Socrates to Modernity”1 Augustinian Studies 34:1 (2003) 23-48. Wayne J. Hankey A. THE OBEDIENCE OF MODERN AND MEDIAEVAL AUGUSTINIANS TO THE ORACLE “Our wisdom, in so far as it ought to be deemed true and solid wisdom, consists almost entirely of two parts: the knowledge of God and of ourselves. But as these are connected together by many ties, it is not easy to determine which of the two precedes and gives birth to the other. ... [I]t is evident that man never attains to a true self-knowledge until he have previously contemplated the face of God, and come down after such contemplation to look into himself.” On this basis, Jean Calvin, from the beginning of whose Institutes of the Christian Religion I have been quoting, fixes the order of the Institutes. For Calvin, as for Eriugena, Aquinas, and other mediaeval theologians, the unity of epistemology and ontology, though differently balanced between them, determines that system treats first of God, then of the human.2 The Geneva Reformer wrote these words about 1536. One hundred years later, another French Augustinian, equally as important for the making of modernity, carried out another investigation of the connection between self-knowledge and knowledge of God. In his Meditations on the First Philosophy, René Descartes wrote to the same effect as Calvin had: ... I see that there is manifestly more reality in infinite substance than in finite, and therefore that in some way I have in me the notion of the infinite earlier than the finite to wit, the notion of God before that of myself.
    [Show full text]
  • Julian, Paideia and Education
    The Culture and Political World of the Fourth Century AD: Julian, paideia and Education Victoria Elizabeth Hughes Submitted in partial fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy School of History, Classics and Archaeology April 2018 Abstract This thesis examines the role of education and paideia in the political and cultural landscape of the mid-fourth century, focusing on the Greek East and the reign of Julian, particularly his educational measures. Julian’s edict and rescript on education are often understood (not least in light of the invectives of Gregory of Nazianzus) as marking an attempt on his part to ban Christians from teaching and, by extension, from engaging in elite public life. They have been used by some scholars as evidence to support the hypothesis that Julian, a committed pagan, implemented an anti-Christian persecution. This thesis reconsiders that hypothesis: it re-evaluates the reign of Julian and his educational measures, and considers the political role of paideia as the culmination and public expression of rhetorical education. Chapter one introduces the topic and provides a brief ‘literature review’ of the key items for a study of Julian and education in the fourth century. Chapter two addresses rhetorical education in the fourth century: it offers a survey of its methods and content, and explores the idea of a ‘typical’ student in contrast with ‘culture heroes’. Chapter three investigates the long-standing Christian debate on the compatibility of a traditional Greek education with Christian belief, and considers the role of Julian in this connection. Chapter four discusses the enhanced status of Latin and of law studies in light of the enlarged imperial administration in the fourth century, and considers the extent to which this development worked to the detriment of rhetorical studies.
    [Show full text]
  • Ancient Narrative Volume 7
    J.R. MORGAN, M. JONES (eds.), Philosophical Presences in the Ancient Novel Ancient Narrative Supplements 10 Pp. 282. Groningen: Barkhuis & Groningen University Library, 2007. Hard- back. €84.80 ISBN 9-789077-922378 Review by Ilaria L. E. Ramelli, Catholic University of Milan, [email protected] This fine collection of essays originated from a conference panel organized by the KYKNOS Research Centre for Ancient Narrative Literature (Swan- sea, Lampeter, and Exeter Universities). It is devoted to an assessment of the presence of philosophy, in various forms, in the Greek novels. First of all, for an investigation of this sort to be fruitful and methodol- ogically careful, it is necessary to determine what exactly “philosophy” means in the cultural context in which the Greek novels arose. This clarifica- tion is duly provided by the first essay: Michael Trapp, “What is This Phi- losophia Anyway?” (pp. 1–22). He explains how philosophy was understood in the Hellenistic and Roman periods,1 and includes in his discussion defini- tions of “philosophy” taken from Alcinoous’ Didaskalikos, Seneca, Lucian, Plutarch, and Maximus of Tyre, all belonging to the first two centuries of the Imperial era. In addition to these, however, texts such as the Cebetis Tabula, with its ethical allegories, are taken into consideration, and particular atten- tion is paid to Plutarch’s essays on moral progress, a notion that was val- orised – I should remark – in Roman Stoicism as well.2 The theoretical side of philosophy was especially stressed by Platonism (at least in Middle- Platonism and in Neoplatonism); the practical side was privileged by Roman ————— 1 A good survey, not cited here, is J.
    [Show full text]
  • Bbm:978-94-015-8181-3/1.Pdf
    INDEXES INDEX OF NAMES Abaris 344 320,471 Abel 70, 104, 248, 447, 450 Alcinous (pseudo-), see Albinus of Smyrna Abelard, Peter 244, 375, 402, 405, 424, 425, Alcmaeon of Croton 189, 269 431 Alcuin of York 402 Abraham 70, 78, 96, 104, 105, 108, III, Il3, Alderotti, Taddeo (physician) 80 Il4, Il8, 121, 126 217, 227, 242, 249, 305, Aldo di Asolo (printer) 86 n 310, 447, 455 Aldobrandini, Pietro (Cardinal) 156, 157 Aceti, G. 442 Aldobrandini, Tommaso 156, 157, 158 Adam (Adamus), Melchior 70, 74, 97, 113, Alessandro di Sangro, Bishop of Bene- 128 vento 46 Adam xxiii, 52, 69, 70, 77, 91, 96, 100, 101, Alexander of Aphrodisias 43, 102, Il7, 216, 104, 107, 114, 115, 126, 215, 217, 238, 247, 230, 443, 467 251, 307, 310, 349, 446, 454, 466 Alexander of Hales 56, 456 Adrian VI, Pope (Adrian of Utrecht) 385 Alexander the Great 109, 131, 139, 166 Aegidius Romanus 27, 80, 102 Alexandre de Villedieu (Alexander de Aelian (Claudius Aelianus) 150 Villa Dei) 80 Aeschines Socraticus 180 Alfarabi, see al-Farabi Aeschylus 172, 173 Alfonso X (the Wise), King of Castile and Aesculapius 105, 109, 110 Leon 75,80 Aesop 73, 105 Algasel, see al-Ghazzali Aetius of Antioch 458 Allacci (Allatius), Leone 17B, 194 Agenor, King of the Phoenicians 108, Il2 Allen, M.]. B. 61 Aglaophemus 16, 24, Il2, Il7, 297 Allut, P. 63 Agricola, Rudolph 143, 242, 385 Amabile, L. xviii Agrippa von Nettesheim, Heinrich Cor- Amalric (Amaury) of Bene, 432 nelius 49, 51 n, 64, 447 Ammonius Alexandrinus (Eclectic philo- Aguzzi Barbagli, D.
    [Show full text]
  • Truth to Power: the Politics of Theological Free Speech in the Cappadocian Fathers and Augustine of Hippo by Jennifer Lynn Bene
    Truth to Power: The Politics of Theological Free Speech in the Cappadocian Fathers and Augustine of Hippo by Jennifer Lynn Benedict Graduate Program in Religion Duke University Date:_______________________ Approved: ___________________________ James Smith, Supervisor ___________________________ Stanley Hauerwas ___________________________ Meredith Riedel ___________________________ C. Kavin Rowe Dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate Program in Religion in the Graduate School of Duke University 2018 ABSTRACT Truth to Power: The Politics of Theological Free Speech in the Cappadocian Fathers and Augustine of Hippo by Jennifer Lynn Benedict Graduate Program in Religion Duke University Date:_______________________ Approved: ___________________________ James Smith, Supervisor ___________________________ Stanley Hauerwas ___________________________ Meredith Riedel ___________________________ C. Kavin Rowe An abstract of a dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate Program in Religion in the Graduate School of Duke University 2018 Copyright by Jennifer Lynn Benedict 2018 Abstract This dissertation investigates the political grammars of truth-telling employed by two sets of early Christian authors, the Cappadocian Fathers (Basil of Caesarea, Gregory of Nazianzus, and Gregory of Nyssa), who wrote in Greek, and Augustine of Hippo, who wrote in Latin. My aim is to describe the rules that these thinkers take to order relations implicated in the Christian’s acts of parrhêsia and confessio before other human persons and before the LORD. To this end, I employ methodology derived from ordinary language philosophy (OLP), which understands the meaning of a word to be constituted by its use within the form of life of a particular community.
    [Show full text]