Absolute Relativism

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Absolute Relativism WELCOME TO THE STEFANICK NEW TYRANNY “IF IT FEELS GOOD, DO IT.” “THAT’S YOUR OPINION, AND THIS IS MINE.” “I DON’T WANT TO IMPOSE MY BELIEFS ON OTHERS. ” “WHAT’S TRUE FOR ONE PERSON MAY NOT BE TRUE FOR ANOTHER.” And thus the Dictator of Relativism speaks—as he has always spoken— to seduce humanity into a false sense of freedom. A In Absolute Relativism: The New Dictatorship and What to Do about It, BSOLUTE Chris Stefanick tackles all the tough questions about relativism by showing how bankrupt and impractical it is. Using a down-to-earth, easily accessible question-and-answer format, Absolute Relativism shows that far from being the answer to world peace— R or even personal peace of mind—relativism suffers from a self-destructive rot. ELATIVISM “In his 2010 book Light of the World, Benedict XVI stresses that ‘in the name of tolerance, tolerance is being abolished; this is the real threat we face.’ That threat to human dignity has a name—relativism—and Chris Stefanick explains and refutes it with energy, imagination, clarity, and force. Stefanick is one of the most engaging young defenders of the Christian faith on the scene today, and his booklet Absolute Relativism is an excellent resource for anyone seeking to understand the spirit of our times and the challenges we face in a world increasingly without a moral compass.” + Charles J. Chaput, O.F.M. Cap. Archbishop of Philadelphia Chris Stefanick speaks to over 50,000 teens, young adults, and parents every year. This 14-year youth ministry veteran P.O. Box 199000 served at a parish in the East L.A. area San Diego, CA 92159-9000 and as Director of Youth and Young Adult 619-387-7200 phone Ministry for the Archdiocese of Denver. 888-291-8000 orders Chris has authored or co-authored several books and is a regular in Catholic media. He is most proud of his wife and their six children. catholic.com 9 781933 919461 Absolute Relativism The New Dictatorship and What to Do about It Chris Stefanick Absolute Relativism Chris Stefanick © 2011 by Catholic Answers, Inc. 15 14 13 4 5 6 7 All rights reserved. Except for quotations, no part of this book may be reproduced or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording, uploading to the Internet, or by any information storage and retrieval system, without written permission from the publisher. Published by Catholic Answers, Inc. 2020 Gillespie Way El Cajon, California 92020 1-888-291-8000 orders 619-387-0042 fax catholic.com Cover by Devin Schadt Interior design by Russell Design ISBN 978-1-933919-46-1 For my wife, Natalie, whose life is a pursuit of Beauty and Truth. Without you I could do none of what I do and I’d be half the man I am. FOREWORD In his 2010 Christmas address to the College of Cardi- nals, the Roman Curia, and the Governorate of Vatican City State, Pope Benedict XVI spoke clearly and strong- ly about the profoundly disordered moral state in which our world nds itself. Speaking about the grave evils of our time—for example, the sexual abuse of minors by the clergy, the marketing of child pornography, sexual tourism, and the deadly abuse of drugs—he observed that they are all signs of “the tyranny of mammon which perverts mankind” and that they result from “a fatal misunderstanding of freedom which actually un- dermines man’s freedom and ultimately destroys it.”1 His words are redolent of the powerful pastoral concern that he expressed in his homily during the Mass for the Election of the Roman Ponti, celebrated before the conclave during which he was elected to the See of Peter. He spoke of how the “the thought of many Christians” has been tossed about, in our time, by various “ideological currents,” observing that we are witnesses to the “human deception and the trickery that strives to entice people into error,” about which St. Paul wrote in his Letter to the Ephesians.2 He noted that, in our time, those who live according to “a clear faith based on the Creed of the Church” are viewed as extremists, while relativism—that is, “letting oneself be ‘tossed here and there, carried about by every wind of doctrine’”—is extolled.3 Regarding the source of the grave moral evils of our time, he concluded: “We are building a dictatorship of relativism that does not rec- ognize anything as denitive and whose ultimate goal consists solely of one’s own ego and desires.”4 Reecting once again, in his 2010 Christmas ad- dress, on the grave evils that are destroying us as in- dividuals and as a society and have le us with a cul- ture marked by violence and death, the Holy Father reminded us that, if we, with the help of God’s grace, are to overcome these grave evils, “we must turn our attention to their ideological foundations.”5 He then identied directly and unequivocally the ideology that fosters these evils: a perversion of ethos, the norm of life or moral norm, which has even entered into the thinking of some theologians in the Church. Referring to one of the more shocking manifestations of the ideology—namely, the so-called moral position that the sexual abuse of children by adults is actually good for the children and for the adults—he declared: It was maintained—even within the realm of Catholic theology—that there is no such thing as evil in itself or good in itself. ere is only a “better than” and a “worse than.” Nothing is good or bad in itself. Everything depends on the circumstances and on the end in view. Anything can be good or also bad, depending upon purposes and circum- stances. Morality is replaced by a calculus of consequences, and in the process it ceases to exist.6 Pope Benedict XVI describes a moral relativ- ism—called proportionalism or consequentialism in contemporary moral theology—that has generated profound confusion and outright error regarding the most fundamental truths of the moral law. 7 It has led to a situation in which morality itself “ceases to exist.” One thinks, for instance, of the plague of procured abortion in our society, which justies the wholesale murder of the unborn in the womb as the exercise of the so-called right of the mother to choose whether to bring to term the baby she has conceived; of the arti- cial generation of human life and its destruction at the embryonic stage of development, which are justied as the means to nd cures for crippling or deadly diseas- es; and of the so-called “mercy killing” of those who have the rst title to our care—our brothers and sisters who have grown weak through advanced years, grave illness, or special needs—which is justied as care for the quality of their lives. One also thinks of the ever-advancing agenda of those who want to redene marriage to include the unnatural sexual union of two persons of the same sex, which is justied as tolerance of so-called alternative forms of human sexuality, as if there were a true form of human sexuality other than that intended by God, our Creator and Redeemer. To confront the ideology, Pope Benedict XVI has urged us to study anew the teaching of his predeces- sor, the Venerable (soon to be Blessed) Pope John Paul II, in his encyclical letter Veritatis Splendor, “On the Fundamentals of the Church’s Moral Teaching,” in which he, in the words of Pope Benedict XVI, “indi- cated with prophetic force, in the great rational tradi- tion of Christian ethos, the essential and permanent foundations of moral action.”8 Reminding us of the need to form our consciences in accord with the moral teaching of the Church, our Holy Father also reminds us of “our responsibility to make these criteria audible and intelligible once more for people today as paths of true humanity, in the context of our paramount con- cern for mankind.”9 In the exhortation of Pope Bene- dict XVI, we see the expression of the deepest pastoral charity of the Vicar of Christ on earth: charity, which like that of the Christ the Good Shepherd, knows no boundary and is unceasing. e book that you now hold in your hands is pre- cisely a tool by which to respond to Pope Benedict XVI’s exhortation that we must address the ideology that underlies so many and grave evils in our time. rough his writing, Christopher Stefanick—draw- ing upon his studies of the Church’s moral teaching and his many years of working with the pastors of the Church, especially in their care of youth—helps us to reect more deeply on “the concept of ethos,” the mor- al norm, and its relationship to the unchanging truth about God, ourselves, and our world. Our author leads us to an ever deeper reection upon our own moral thinking and its coherence with the moral truth that our Lord Jesus Christ teaches us in the Church. In a particular and most important way, he helps us to ad- dress a false notion of tolerance, which is nothing less than an expression of the “dictatorship of relativism,” which threatens to destroy us and our society and through which morality “ceases to exist.” In the end, as our author reminds us, we discover the truth, the true concept of ethos, in Jesus Christ in a personal relationship with him as he comes to meet us and to make us ever more one with him in his Mystical Body, the Church.
Recommended publications
  • Moral Relativism and Human Rights
    Buffalo Human Rights Law Review Volume 13 Article 6 9-1-2007 Moral Relativism and Human Rights Torben Spaak Uppsala University Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalcommons.law.buffalo.edu/bhrlr Part of the Comparative and Foreign Law Commons, and the Human Rights Law Commons Recommended Citation Torben Spaak, Moral Relativism and Human Rights, 13 Buff. Hum. Rts. L. Rev. 73 (2007). Available at: https://digitalcommons.law.buffalo.edu/bhrlr/vol13/iss1/6 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Law Journals at Digital Commons @ University at Buffalo School of Law. It has been accepted for inclusion in Buffalo Human Rights Law Review by an authorized editor of Digital Commons @ University at Buffalo School of Law. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Moral Relativism and Human Rights Torben Spaak* 1. INTRODUCTION Politicians, human rights activists, scholars, and others disagree about whether human rights are universally true or valid or only true or valid relative to a given culture.1 Jack Donnelly, for example, defends (what he refers to as) the moral universality of human rights: If human rights are the rights one has simply because one is a human being, as they are usually thought to be, then they are held "universally," by all human beings. They also hold "universally" against all other persons and institutions. As the highest moral rights, they regulate the fundamental structures and practices of political life, and in ordinary cir- cumstances they take priority over other moral, legal, and political claims. These distinctions encompass what I call 2 the moral universality of human rights.
    [Show full text]
  • Moral Relativism
    City University of New York (CUNY) CUNY Academic Works Publications and Research New York City College of Technology 2020 The Incoherence of Moral Relativism Carlo Alvaro CUNY New York City College of Technology How does access to this work benefit ou?y Let us know! More information about this work at: https://academicworks.cuny.edu/ny_pubs/583 Discover additional works at: https://academicworks.cuny.edu This work is made publicly available by the City University of New York (CUNY). Contact: [email protected] 1 The Incoherence of Moral Relativism Abstract This paper is a response to Park Seungbae’s article, “Defence of Cultural Relativism”. Some of the typical criticisms of moral relativism are the following: moral relativism is erroneously committed to the principle of tolerance, which is a universal principle; there are a number of objective moral rules; a moral relativist must admit that Hitler was right, which is absurd; a moral relativist must deny, in the face of evidence, that moral progress is possible; and, since every individual belongs to multiple cultures at once, the concept of moral relativism is vague. Park argues that such contentions do not affect moral relativism and that the moral relativist may respond that the value of tolerance, Hitler’s actions, and the concept of culture are themselves relative. In what follows, I show that Park’s adroit strategy is unsuccessful. Consequently, moral relativism is incoherent. Keywords: Moral relativism; moral absolutism; objectivity; tolerance; moral progress 2 The Incoherence of Moral Relativism Moral relativism is a meta-ethical theory according to which moral values and duties are relative to a culture and do not exist independently of a culture.
    [Show full text]
  • Moral Relativism and Chinese Philosophy
    1 Introduction Yong Huang and Yang Xiao It is only quite recently that moral relativism has become a central topic among moral philosophers. About thirty years ago, in 1979, Philippa Foot had the following to say: Because moral relativism is “one of those natural philosophical thoughts . one might therefore expect that mor- al relativism would be a central topic among those discussed in classes and in the journals. Surprisingly, however, the truth has for long been quite otherwise. Many recent books on moral philosophy ignore the problem or give it perfunctory treatment, and it is only in the last two or three years that strong, interesting articles have begun to appear in print” (Foot 2002, 20). In 1984, David Wong’s Moral Relativity, the first book-length study of moral relativism appeared (Wong 1984). Since then, there have been many books and journal articles on the topic.1 It is a significant fact that, in contrast to most of the people who have aimed at establishing its falsity, Wong is among a handful of contemporary philosophers in the English-speaking world who are willing to defend certain forms of relativism.2 In his second book on moral relativism, Natural Moralities: A Defense of Pluralistic Relativism (Wong 2006), which is the focus of this edited volume, Wong gives new arguments for an ambitious, sophisti- cated, and original version of moral relativism, which was first sketched out in his 1984 book. As one of the reviewers remarks, Wong’s new book is “the most systematic and persuasive defense of moral relativism that has yet been written” (Gowans 2007).
    [Show full text]
  • (3 Credit Hours) Course Description: a Study of the Moral Principl
    PHILIOSOPHY 320 ETHICS BULLETIN INFORMATION PHIL 320 - Ethics (3 credit hours) Course Description: A study of the moral principles of conduct and the basic concepts underlying these principles, such as good, evil, right, wrong, justice, value, duty, and obligation. The ethical works of influential philosophers are analyzed in terms of these concepts. SAMPLE COURSE OVERVIEW We will discuss central questions in the study of ethics. These questions include: What ought we to do? What is of value in our lives? What kind of person should I be? Are there moral facts, and if so, what are they and how do we know about them? If not, what else might ground ethical or moral thinking? To help us with these questions, we will analyze competing moral theories. Along the way we will grapple with some examples of their application, both as thought-experiments and to real-world issues. ITEMIZED LEARNING OUTCOMES Upon successful completion of Philosophy 320, students will be able to: 1. Think carefully and systematically about questions of right and wrong action 2. Identify values, the role they have in our lives and in moral theory, and their possible sources 3. Demonstrate an understanding of the importance of values, ethics, and social Responsibility for the self and for contemporary society 4. Reflect on how values shape personal and community ethics and decision-making 5. Present arguments in support of moral claims, both orally and in writing SAMPLE REQUIRED TEXTS/SUGGESTED READINGS/MATERIALS 1. Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals by Immanuel Kant (Pub: Hackett. ISBN: 0-87220-166-X) 2.
    [Show full text]
  • Responding to Relativism with Logic and Love by Edward Sri Discussion Guide
    Who Am I To Judge: Responding to Relativism with Logic and Love by Edward Sri Discussion Guide Part One The Challenge Relativism is the idea that there is no truth, that each individual decides for himself what is true and what is right and wrong. Pope Benedict states that “Having a clear faith based on the Creed of the Church is often labeled as fundamentalism.” He further states, “We are building a dictatorship of relativism that does not recognize anything as definitive…” 1. Have you ever felt afraid to bring up a moral topic or talk about a moral issue with your friends or family? Clashing World views Relativism thrives because Christians have not done a good job of explaining the Christian moral vision. We have left people with the impression that morality is just about random rules. 2. Why is it illogical for relativists to say there is no truth? Part Two A New Vision The Greek philosophers believed that practically every moment is an ethical moment because ethics is fundamentally about a person’s character. In other words, our individual choices really do matter; they lead us in one direction or another. 3. Using the funeral example mentioned in this chapter, which qualities do you want to be remembered for most? What does this tell us about what’s most important in life and the kind of life you want to live? Friendship & Virtue Catholicism defines virtue as “a habitual and firm disposition to do good.” The virtuous person does good easily, consistently, and joyfully. When we fail to be the best we can be, we have a negative impact on the people God has placed in our lives.
    [Show full text]
  • Just War? Moral Soldiers?
    SUBSCRIBE NOW AND RECEIVE CRISIS AND LEVIATHAN* FREE! “The Independent Review does not accept “The Independent Review is pronouncements of government officials nor the excellent.” conventional wisdom at face value.” —GARY BECKER, Noble Laureate —JOHN R. MACARTHUR, Publisher, Harper’s in Economic Sciences Subscribe to The Independent Review and receive a free book of your choice* such as the 25th Anniversary Edition of Crisis and Leviathan: Critical Episodes in the Growth of American Government, by Founding Editor Robert Higgs. This quarterly journal, guided by co-editors Christopher J. Coyne, and Michael C. Munger, and Robert M. Whaples offers leading-edge insights on today’s most critical issues in economics, healthcare, education, law, history, political science, philosophy, and sociology. Thought-provoking and educational, The Independent Review is blazing the way toward informed debate! Student? Educator? Journalist? Business or civic leader? Engaged citizen? This journal is for YOU! *Order today for more FREE book options Perfect for students or anyone on the go! The Independent Review is available on mobile devices or tablets: iOS devices, Amazon Kindle Fire, or Android through Magzter. INDEPENDENT INSTITUTE, 100 SWAN WAY, OAKLAND, CA 94621 • 800-927-8733 • [email protected] PROMO CODE IRA1703 Just War? Moral Soldiers? —————— ✦ —————— LAURIE CALHOUN Moral reasoning within the just war tradition is far more like a skilled musi- cal conductor interpreting a symphonic score than it is like an engineer reading a blueprint. The conductor has notes and other instructions on his score. But the beauty (or dissonance) of the music he or she makes is a func- tion, not simply of the notes, but of the application of the conductor’s imagination, intelligence, and discipline.
    [Show full text]
  • Moral Relativism Explained
    Moral Relativism Explained Gilbert Harman 1 What Is Moral Relativism? According to moral relativism, there is not a single true morality. There are a variety of possible moralities or moral frames of reference, and whether something is morally right or wrong, good or bad, just or unjust, etc. is a relative matter—relative to one or another morality or moral frame of reference. Something can be morally right relative to one moral frame of reference and 1 morally wrong relative to another. It is useful to compare moral relativism to other kinds of 2 relativism. One possible comparison is with motion relativism. There is no such thing as absolute motion or absolute rest. Whether something is moving or at rest is relative to a spatio- temporal frame of reference. Something may be at rest in one such frame of reference and moving in another. There is no such thing as absolute motion and absolute rest, but we can make do with relative motion and rest. Similarly, moral relativism is the view that, although there is no such thing as absolute right and wrong, we can make do with relative right and wrong. 3 Paul Boghossian suggests a different comparison. When people decided that there were no witches and no such thing as witchcraft, they did not become relativists about witches; they gave up their beliefs about witches. It would have been a mistake for them to conclude that witchcraft is a relative matter, so that someone could be a witch in relation to one witch framework but not in relation to another.
    [Show full text]
  • Consequentialism David Cummiskey
    1 Consequentialism David Cummiskey According to consequentialists, the overall goodness of results is the most basic moral consideration. For instance, if actions are the primary focal point of moral evaluation, the consequences of the actions will determine whether the action is right or wrong. If one is evaluating rules or social institutions, the evaluation will depend on the consequences of adopting the rules or institutions. Whatever the object of evaluation, the value of outcomes will provide the justification (Kagan 1998). If morality involves promoting good consequences, we need a theory of the good. What makes one outcome better than another? There are three major theories of the good that correspond to different forms of consequentialism. The classical utilitarianism of Jeremy Bentham and John Stuart Mill represents wbiee178 the best‐known form of consequentialism (see utilitarianism; bentham, jeremy; wbiee594 mill, john stuart). Classical utilitarians are consequentialist with a particular the- wbiee610 ory of the good: the good is happiness, where happiness is simply the experience of pleasure and the absence of pain. This theory of the good, which identifies happi- wbiee780 ness with pleasure, is called hedonism (see hedonism). Of course, unlike egoists, utilitarians aim to maximize the happiness of all people (or all beings capable of feeling pleasure or pain). Thus, for utilitarians, the goal of life is happiness and max- imizing the happiness of all provides the standard for morality. Other utilitarians, wbiee741 like R. M. Hare (see hare, r. m.), have defended alternative conceptions of the wbiee522 good – for example, the good as the satisfaction of desires or preferences (see desire wbiee927 theories of the good; subjective theories of well‐being).
    [Show full text]
  • 'Moral Relativism,' There Are Three Plausible Versions
    GILBERT HARMAN WHAT IS MORAL RELATIVISM? Of the various views that have been called 'moral relativism,' there are three plausible versions, which I will label 'normative moral relativism,' 'moral judgment relativism,' and 'meta-ethical relativism.' The first of these views is a thesis about moral agents; the second, a thesis about the form of meaning of moral judgments; the third, a thesis about the truth conditions or justifi­ cation of moral judgments. Nonnative moral relativism is the view roughly that different people, as agents, can be subject to different ultimate moral demands. Moral judgment relativism holds that moral judgments make implicit reference to the speaker or some other person or to some group or to one or another set of moral standards, etc. Meta-ethical relativism says that conflicting moral judgments about a particular case can both be right. 1. NORMATIVE MORAL RELATIVISM According to our rough statement of normative moral relativism, different people, as agents, can be subject to different ultimate moral demands. Only ultimate differences are supposed to be relevant, since even the nonrelativist will agree that different agents are subject to some different moral demands because of differences in situation. Jack is morally obligated to pay George ten dollars, Mary is not. That is not yet normative moral relativism. Maybe Jack has borrowed ten dollars from George and Mary has not. In that case Mary and Jack might still be subject to the same ultimate moral demands, including for example that one should pay one's debts. Differences in situation can include differences in custom. In England (in 1977) Jack ought to drive on the left side of the road.
    [Show full text]
  • Virtue Theory, Relativism and Survival
    International Journal of Social Science and Humanity, Vol. 3, No. 4, July 2013 Virtue Theory, Relativism and Survival Joseph Grcic there can be no objective or universal knowledge in any Abstract—Virtue theory claims that moral virtues define the human endeavor including ethics. moral person. Moral relativism claims there are no necessary Metaethical relativism is the claim that moral concepts universal moral values-this theory is not rationally sustainable have meaning only within a given cultural framework. Any as a theory of ethics. The necessary functions of social order two different normative systems are incommensurable and and existence require certain moral virtues. There are six main universal moral virtues: wisdom, courage, justice, humanity, one cannot be rationally judged to be superior to the other. temperance, and transcendence. Societies cannot function Relativism in the extreme form conflicts with the fact that efficiently without these core virtues. there are similarities in moral virtues found across all stable cultures. These virtues and values are a function of the Index terms—Moral relativism, social structure, virtue universality of human nature, human needs and the common theory. problems societies must solve to survive. The differences that do exist in moral norms are limited and arise due to different social and historical contexts, ideologies and belief I. INTRODUCTION systems which shape moral norms to some degree. But The realm of ethics seems to be one of the most these differences are secondary when compared to the larger conflicted and uncertain in philosophy and in human history. common foundation of core values based on the common This conflict would be tolerable if it did not have practical problems which must be solved for communities to survive.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy 12 Existentialism 3 Units; 3 Hours Lecture Recommended Preparation: Eligibility for English 1A Credit, Degree Applicable Transfer CSU
    Philosophy 12 Existentialism 3 units; 3 hours lecture Recommended Preparation: eligibility for English 1A Credit, degree applicable Transfer CSU This course will examine the philosophical thought of the two strands of existentialist writers: the religious existentialist such as Kierkegaard, Dostoevsky, and Heidegger, and the atheistic existentialists such as Nietzsche, Camus, and Sartre. Issues that will be examined include authenticity; free will; responsibility for one’s character and actions; the essence, possibilities and limits of human beings; and the meaning of life. Course Objectives: 1. Identify the common questions, ideas and themes of Existentialism. 2. Describe the earlier historical/philosophical movements and philosophers to which Existentialism responds. 3. Differentiate the two major strands of Existentialism, Religious and Atheistic Existentialism, and identify the philosophers associated with each type. 4. Examine and analyze what it is to be an authentic person. 5. Describe and examine the dangers of following the herd or society, and explain the challenges of questioning society's ideas and values while still being a part of that society. 6. Assess and analyze the significance of living authentically in a world with others. 7. Describe and analyze the concepts of perspectivism, objective truth and subjective truth, and moral relativism. 8. Examine and discuss the dangers of reliance on inflexible rules and restrictions. 9. Assess the importance of one's non-rational or irrational sides, including one's emotions, appetites and instincts, and their relevance to authenticity. 10. Discuss and differentiate Existentialist philosophers' criticisms of religion in general and Christianity in particular. 11. Assess the impact of free will and choice on one's actions, ideas, character, and life, focusing on the degree of responsibility one has for what one does and who one is.
    [Show full text]
  • Qualifying Hume's Sentimentalist Defense Against Moral Relativism
    Qualifying Hume’s Sentimentalist Defense Against Moral Relativism A Senior Essay presented to The Colorado College Department of Philosophy Paxton Hyde Advisor Rick Furtak April, 2019 ii On my honor, I have given nor received unauthorized aid in the production of this Senior Essay. – P.B.H. iii Abstract : This essay revisits David Hume’s argument for moral sentimentalism and qualifies his solution to moral relativism. Agreeing with Hume’s empirical thesis that emotional judgments are contextually-determined, I trace his argument showing it is impossible to ground moral judgment in pure reason because reason is impartial and thus cannot choose moral values. Moral judgment therefore must be grounded in emotion. It follows that moral truth is relative to one’s subjective position because the partiality of moral judgment that enables the preference of certain moral values simultaneously makes it impossible for those judgments to be impartial and universal. Hume and other sentimentalists defend against this relativism by arguing that people who have been exposed to a diversity of thought and maintain an open-minded and empathic attitude are able to make superior moral judgments. I support this defense on the grounds that it champions freedom of expression and provides a viable framework for resolving moral disputes. At the same time, I argue that the moral relativism implied by Hume’s sentimentalism is too strong for him to claim that open-mindedness and empathy are absolute moral standards. Keywords : ethics, Hume, moral relativism, sentimentalism, moral philosophy, empathy 1 0. Introduction Through Hume’s moral psychology this essay addresses his argument that moral judgments are motivated by emotion and what this implies for how moral disputes might be resolved without absolute moral authority.
    [Show full text]