Voices of Common Sense

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Voices of Common Sense VOICES OF COMMON SENSE Philosophical principle, a quality of the sociable man, a feature of language and communication. Sometimes degraded to political slogan. The understanding of common sense continues to stimulate debate, and remains relevant. We offer a selection of seventy books and manuscripts which convey some of the voices that, in one sense or another, have championed this idea. From Aristotle’s first intuition of the concept to Cicero’s, Horace’s and Seneca’s classical declension of a quality essential to humanity; to early-modern attempts to grapple with the notion of mind and its relationship with the external world; to the Scottish school of philosophy that, starting from a critical reading of Hume and Berkeley, turned common sense into a philosophical principle and, principally through the works of Thomas Reid, became extremely influential on American thought; to Kant, and pragmatism, and twentieth-century philosophers like Popper, Moore and Wittgenstein. Economists like Adam Smith or Dugald Stewart, sociologists like Adam Ferguson, essayists like Voltaire and Hazlitt, historians like Buchanan and statists like Tocqueville join in the conversation with the philosophers proper, as if to point to the far-reaching remits of a concept which has been, since inception, wider than a simple point of method. BERNARD QUARITCH ltd LIST 2016/4 [email protected] VOICES OF COMMON SENSE ENTER KOINE AISTHESIS 1. ARISTOTLE. [Scientific and psychological works, in Greek]. Aristotelous Physikēs akroaseōs biblia 8. Peri ouranou 4. Peri geneseōs kai phthoras 2. Meteōrologikōn 4. Peri kosmou 1. Peri phychēs 3 ... Aristotelis Physicae auscultationis lib. 8. De coelo 4. De gener. & corruptione 2. Meteorologicorum 4. De mundo 1. De anima 3. De sensu & sensibilibus, lib. 1. De memoria & reminiscentia 1. De somno & vigilia 1. De insomniis 1. De diuinatione per somnum 1. De iuuentute, senectute, vita & morte 1. De respiratione 1. De lōgitudine & breuitate vitae 1. Addita in tractatus cuiusq; fine varia locorum lectio, e libris tum impressis, tum manu scriptis. Adhaec index capitum; & rerum ac verborum notatu digniorum bina inuentaria, alterum graecum, alterum latinum. Frankfurt, Wechel, 1584 . 8vo, pp. 204, 108, 60, 132, 31, 78, 111, [1]; faint marginal stains to the last quires, but a very good, clean, generously-margined copy in dark impression, in a contemporary memorial binding of blind-stamped vellum over boards, sides with borders of foliage and cameos illustrating prominent humanists, rectangular centre-pieces of foliage and cartouches, the front dated 1584 (the same date as the publishing of the book) and enclosing a medallion with a memorial portrait of a German gentleman, his arms in the medallion on the rear; acquisition inscription dated June 1586 by Joseph Loeher from Sindelfingen (near Stuttgart) on the front free end-paper, early citation from Cicero’s De officiis on the front paste-down. £6500 First appearance of the authoritative Sylburg edition (‘beautiful, correct and scarce’, Dibdin) of Aristotle’s works on physics, cosmology and biology. A fine copy, in an attractive contemporary German memorial binding. It is in works on psychology, theory of perception and physiology such as De anima, De memoria et reminiscentia and De partibus animalium that Aristotle makes reference to koine aisthesis , that is sensus communis , ‘common sense’. Since Aristotle’s use of the term is rather sparse, interpretations of its meaning are not univocal; but there seems to be consensus on identifying common sense with a higher-order perceptual capacity of the mind which unites and monitors the five senses: a non-rational cognitive power comprising the perceptual and the imaginative capacities. It has been noted (Oehler) that it was Aristotle who first mooted the ‘argumentum e consensu omnium’, or public opinion, as a criterion for truth. ‘Great critical power and indefatigable industry’ (Britannica) immediately gave Sylburg’s impressive list of works edited for the publisher Wechel a mark of distinction and authority which set them apart in the sixteenth century and ever since. In the case of Aristotle, the renown and skills of the editor were matched by a renewed appetite for confronting the Philosopher’s insights on such issues as space, time, movement, speed, acceleration, by reading his thoughts in his own language and from sources as close to correctness as possible. Adams 1734. BRAIN AND THOUGHT INVESTIGATED 2. ABERCROMBIE, John. Inquiries concerning the intellectual powers and the investigation of truth. Edinburgh, Waugh and Innes, 1832. 8vo, pp. xvi, 441, [1 blank]; a very good copy in contemporary polished half calf, panelled spine with half-raised bands, decorated in gilt with a red morocco lettering-piece, marbled boards; joints cracked but holding. £140 Third edition, ‘ various new facts have been added ’ (preface to this edition), of a pioneering neurocognitive work by a Fellow of the Royal College of Physicians in Edinburgh. Abercrombie examines sensation and perception, reasoning, memory, dreams, somnambulism and other phenomena of the mind, attempting definitions of insanity. The first edition had appeared in Edinburgh by Waugh and Innes in 1830. This third, expanded edition was published in the same year as the first America edition, which appeared as part of J. and J. Harper’s Family Library. Charles Darwin owned a copy of a slightly later edition (1838), and annotated it with thoughts about the relationship between brain and thought, embracing Abercrombie’s agnosticism regarding this subject. Jessop p. 81. SENSES THE BASIS OF ALL MENTAL PROCESSES 3. BAIN, Alexander . Autograph Letter, Signed, to Edward Livingston Youmans. Aberdeen, 27 th November 1875. [Inserted in:] BAIN, Alexander. The emotions and the will. London, Longmans, Green, 1865. 8vo, pp. xxxii, 616 + 24 (publisher’s advertisements); occasional, light foxing, but a very good copy, uncut and partly unopened in the original publisher’s brown cloth, sides panelled in blind, flat spine lettered in gilt; spine ends a little worn; autograph letter by the author inserted in the books, pp. [4], 12 lines to a page, brown ink; remarkably fresh, well-preserved and thoroughly legible. £500 Second edition, with ‘extensive emendations… the chapter on Emotions in general has been wholly recast […] and all that regards the connexions of mind with physical processes has undergone careful revision’ (author’s preface to this edition). A handsome association copy belonging to Edward Livingston Youmans, the recipient of the letter tipped inside the book. Youmans was the author of the preface to the American edition of this work by the Aberdeen Professor, advocate of British empiricism, founder of the influential journal ‘Mind’ in 1876, and Mill’s assistant in the preparation of his Logic. Bain maintained that all mental processes must be based on physical sensations. He strove to identify the link between the mind and the body, focusing on the physiological correlations between mental and behavioural phenomena. A strong influence on Bain was Darwin, whose masterpiece ‘was published the same year as The Emotions and the Will (1859). Bain never became an evolutionist, though he received Darwin’s work with critical admiration. Darwin refers to Bain’s psychology of emotions in his Expression of the emotions in Man and Animals (1872), and Bain responds to this reference in later editions of his psychological treatises’ (G. Hamner, American pragmatism , note 4 to Chapter 5). The autograph letter recommends a forthcoming textbook on Roman Law by Bain’s former pupil, the Scottish jurist William Alexander Hunter, as very remarkable and eminently suited for advertising and distribution in America. Indeed, Hunter’s Introduction to Roman Law , which saw the light first in 1880, was to become a standard textbook both sides of the Atlantic. Jessop,p.85. IDEAS ARE NOT INNATE 4. BARBIERI, Lodovico. Trattato di psicologia nel quale si ragiona della natura dell’anime umane, e degli altri spiriti, della loro excellenza sopra i corpi, della intelligenza, della volonta, della immortalita ... Venice, Pietro Valvasense, 1756. 8vo, xxxi, [1], 340 (the last page with list of books printed by Valvasense); woodcut title- page vignette, initials, head- and tailpieces; a little light foxing, some very faint damp staining towards the end; a very good copy in contemporary stiff vellum, gilt lettering and inked roman numerals to spine, red edges; a few marks; circular blue ink stamp to title-page, contemporary ownership inscription of F. Philippus of Poggio Mirteto to foot of title-page and his book label to facing flyleaf. £500 First edition, very rare, of the polymath Barbieri’s treatise in which he argues that the soul is an ‘active power’. Barbieri’s text tackles the interrelation of the body and soul, the nature of space, will and freedom, arguing against the theory of innate ideas, and attempts to provide proof of the soul’s immortality. In the course of his discussion, Barbieri confronts Leibniz’s ‘monads’ and doctrine of pre-established harmony, and sets himself in opposition to Locke and, in particular, to Antonio Genovesi. Rare: 4 copies only in the UK/US: British Library, Chicago, New York Public Library, and Yale. TAKING ISSUE WITH BERKELEY’S ‘ABSENCE OF MATTER’ 5. BAXTER, Andrew. An Enquiry into the Nature of the human Soul; wherein the Immateriality of the Soul is evinced from the Principles of Reason and Philosophy. London, printed by James Bettenham, for the Author; and sold by G. Strahan
Recommended publications
  • Thomas Reid on Consciousness and Attention 165 Volume 39, Number 2, June 2009, Pp
    CANADIAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHYThomas Reid on Consciousness and Attention 165 Volume 39, Number 2, June 2009, pp. 165-194 Thomas Reid on Consciousness and Attention GIDEON YAFFE University of Southern California Los Angeles, CA 90089 USA I Introduction It was common enough in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries to fi nd philosophers holding the position that for something to be ‘in the mind’ and for that mind to be conscious of it are one and the same thing. The thought is that consciousness is a relation between a mind and a mental entity playing the same role as the relation of inherence found between a substance and qualities belonging to it. What it is, on this view, for something to ‘inhere’ in the mind is for that mind to be conscious of it. Locke was explicit in his acceptance of such a claim, writing, for instance, [T]o be in the Mind, and, never to be perceived, is all one, as to say, any thing is, and is not, in the Mind.1 The implication here is that it is a fl at contradiction to assert that some- thing is in the mind and ‘unperceived’ where a mind ‘perceives’ some- 1 John Locke, An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, Nidditch, P. H. (ed.), Ox- ford: Clarendon Press, 1975, I.ii.5. 166 Gideon Yaffe thing, in this context, just in case it is conscious of it. On this issue, as on many others, Locke’s position was accepted almost verbatim by the most infl uential Anglophone philosophers of the century that followed, including even those, such as Thomas Reid, who opposed many of the tenets of Locke’s philosophy of mind.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophies of Common Sense
    Philosophies of Common Sense Fall 2009 - Winter 2010 This course will focus on a series of philosophers whose work can be loosely characterized as philosophy of common sense, namely, Hume, Reid, Moore, Austin, and among contemporaries, Mark Wilson. Our goal will be to trace a number of inter-related meta- philosophical themes: naturalism, the nature and viability of conceptual analysis, and the role of ordinary language. (The ‘naturalism’ in question will often be the specific form I call ‘Second Philosophy’, so some grasp of that approach, as in Maddy [2007] or [200?], would be useful as background.) Skepticism, and particularly the Argument from Illusion, will feature as a recurring case study for comparing and contrasting these various approaches to philosophical inquiry. The default requirement for those taking the course for a grade (other than S/U) is three short papers (750-1250 words) due at the beginning of class in the 4th week, 7th week, and 10th week. Each paper should isolate one localized point in the readings and offer some analysis and/or critique. Other options are open to negotiation. I assume everyone has access to copies of: J. L. Austin, Sense and Sensibilia. Mark Wilson, Wandering Significance. All other assigned materials are available to enrolled students at the links below. Copies of these books will be available in Brian Rogers’s office (795 SST): Austin, Philosophical Papers. Baldwin, G. E. Moore. 2 Cuneo and Woudenberg, Cambridge Companion to Thomas Reid. Fratantaro, The Methodology of G. E. Moore. Moore, Philosophical Papers. Philosophical Studies. Some Main Problems of Philosophy. Reid, An Inquiry into the Human Mind on the Principles of Common Sense.
    [Show full text]
  • History of the Human Sciences
    History of the Human Sciences http://hhs.sagepub.com Herder: culture, anthropology and the Enlightenment David Denby History of the Human Sciences 2005; 18; 55 DOI: 10.1177/0952695105051126 The online version of this article can be found at: http://hhs.sagepub.com/cgi/content/abstract/18/1/55 Published by: http://www.sagepublications.com Additional services and information for History of the Human Sciences can be found at: Email Alerts: http://hhs.sagepub.com/cgi/alerts Subscriptions: http://hhs.sagepub.com/subscriptions Reprints: http://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.nav Permissions: http://www.sagepub.co.uk/journalsPermissions.nav Citations http://hhs.sagepub.com/cgi/content/refs/18/1/55 Downloaded from http://hhs.sagepub.com at CAPES on December 11, 2009 03HHS18-1 Denby (ds) 8/3/05 8:47 am Page 55 HISTORY OF THE HUMAN SCIENCES Vol. 18 No. 1 © 2005 SAGE Publications (London, Thousand Oaks, CA and New Delhi) pp. 55–76 [18:1;55–76; DOI: 10.1177/0952695105051126] Herder: culture, anthropology and the Enlightenment DAVID DENBY ABSTRACT The anthropological sensibility has often been seen as growing out of opposition to Enlightenment universalism. Johann Gottfried Herder (1744–1803) is often cited as an ancestor of modern cultural relativism, in which cultures exist in the plural. This article argues that Herder’s anthropology, and anthropology generally, are more closely related to Enlightenment thought than is generally considered. Herder certainly attacks Enlightenment abstraction, the arrogance of its Eurocentric historical teleology, and argues the case for a proto-hermeneutical approach which emphasizes embeddedness, horizon, the usefulness of prejudice. His suspicion of the ideology of progress and of associated theories of stadial development leads to a critique of cosmopolitanism and, particularly, of colonialism.
    [Show full text]
  • Doç. Dr. Hacı Mustafa AÇIKÖZ a BRIEF OVERVIEW of REID's
    DİCLE ÜNİVERSİTESİ SOSYAL BİLİMLER ENSTİTÜSÜ DERGİSİ ISSN: 1308-6219 Ekim 2020 YIL-12 Sayı 25 Araştırma Makalesi / Research Article Yayın Geliş Tarihi / Article Arrival Date Yayınlanma Tarihi / The Publication Date 07.06.2020 19.10.2020 Doç. Dr. Hacı Mustafa AÇIKÖZ Muş Alparslan Üniversitesi Fen-Edebiyat Fakültesi Felsefe Bölümü [email protected] A BRIEF OVERVIEW OF REID’S PHILOSOPHY AND ITS HISTORICAL IMPACTS AT HIS 310TH BIRTH ANNIVERSARY Abstract Without referring to common sense it is impossible to act and talk both individually and socially, whether we are aware of it or not. Both action itself and act of speech brought about at the conventional realms necessarily require rational processes excluding some unhealty irational cases so that without applying common sense none can talk of rational process in any action of an agent. Thus common sense equated or matched with huge, live and matured sides of a shared, general, sound and valid conventional reason. Initially, common sense seems an inevitable accidential mode of theoretical and applicable functions of the mind. For Reid common sense in large is equated to reasion or mind as to its content, function and importance so that it is a multi functional safe heaven of human rationality. Although common sense philosophy, founded and codified by Reid, has been obvious historical impact over the philosophers of Scotland, France and America, it unfortunatelly ignored. Because notion and phenemon of common sense deliberately and unjustly negativated, for instance, Kant, as a Scotish Germanian Humeist, has an absurd and unjust role in this process. Herein we shall briefly introduce Thomas Reid’s common sense philosophy and its global influences over philosophers at 310th anniversary of his birth (i.e.
    [Show full text]
  • Thomas Reid's Common-Sense Philosophy in the Development Of
    Thomas Reid’s Common-Sense Philosophy in the Development of Nineteenth-Century French Spiritualism by James Crombie Université Sainte-Anne 1695 Route 1, Pointe-de-l’Église Nova Scotia, Canada james.crombie <at> usainteanne.ca Conference 19th-Century French Philosophy: The 'Spiritualist' Tradition and its Critics, 14-15 September 2017, Manchester Metropolitan University, Manchester, UK This presentation calls attention to the surprising level of influence which the Scottish philosopher Thomas Reid (1710-1796) had on nineteenth-century French philosophy – especially among professional teachers of philosophy in French universities – in particular among those identified as belonging to the so-called ‘spiritualist’ tradition. Some of the political, social, personal – and even philosophical – reasons for this phenomenon will be adumbrated. There were many figures who could be considered to be influential Reidians during the nineteenth-century in France. This presentation will focus on the major players: firstly, Royer-Collard; secondly, Cousin, Damiron and Jouffroy. Some attention will be paid, thirdly, to some of the members of the third generation: Adolphe Garnier, Amédée Jacques, Émile Saisset, Jules Simon, Adolphe Bertereau and Adolphe Franck. Pierre Maine de Biran and Joseph- Marie Degérando (aka de Gérando) are mentioned but not Pierre Prévost who, in Geneva, was publishing on the subject of Reid before he was discovered in Paris by Royer-Collard. Thomas Reid This portrait is reputed to be the only surviving visual likeness of Thomas Reid. It was painted by Sir Henry Raeburn in 1796, upon the urging of James Gregory, on the occasion of a visit by Reid, in the year in which Reid died, at the age of 86.
    [Show full text]
  • A Theological Account of John Henry Newman's
    “READING CUSTOM AS ILLATIVE SENSE” A THEOLOGICAL ACCOUNT OF JOHN HENRY NEWMAN’S APPROPRIATION OF A REALIST INTERPRETATION OF DAVID HUME Thesis Submitted to The College of Arts and Sciences of the UNIVERSITY OF DAYTON In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for The Degree of Master of Arts in Theological Studies By Sean Swain Martin UNIVERSITY OF DAYTON Dayton, Ohio August, 2015 “READING CUSTOM AS ILLATIVE SENSE” A THEOLOGICAL ACCOUNT OF JOHN HENRY NEWMAN’S APPROPRIATION OF A REALIST INTERPRETATION OF DAVID HUME Name: Martin, Sean Swain APPROVED BY: ______________________________ William L. Portier, Ph.D. Faculty Advisor ______________________________ Sandra A. Yocum, Ph.D. Committee Member ______________________________ Dennis M. Doyle, Ph.D. Committee Member ii ABSTRACT “READING CUSTOM AS ILLATIVE SENSE” A THEOLOGICAL ACCOUNT OF JOHN HENRY NEWMAN’S APPROPRIATION OF A REALIST INTERPRETATION OF DAVID HUME Name: Martin, Sean Swain University of Dayton Advisor: Dr. William Portier This thesis explores the notion that John Henry Newman offered an epistemological system that in some way mirrors the image of the non-skeptical, realist reading of Hume that we have only seen become popular over the last few decades and that understanding this commonality to Newman’s system is extremely helpful in making sense of the complicated notion he names the illative sense and the function it is to play in the practice of the Christian faith. I first formulate the historically accepted skeptical epistemology associated with Hume, with specific attention given to his discussion of the problems surrounding the idea of causation. I contrast this traditionally rendered Hume with the model provided by his contemporary, Thomas Reid, which includes explicit interaction with this understanding of Hume’s philosophy.
    [Show full text]
  • An Inquiry Into the Human Mind
    An Inquiry into the Human Mind Thomas Reid Copyright © Jonathan Bennett 2017. All rights reserved [Brackets] enclose editorial explanations. Small ·dots· enclose material that has been added, but can be read as though it were part of the original text. Occasional •bullets, and also indenting of passages that are not quotations, are meant as aids to grasping the structure of a sentence or a thought. Every four-point ellipsis . indicates the omission of a short passage that seems to present more difficulty than it is worth. Longer omissions are reported beween square brackets in normal-sized type. First launched: September 2005 Last amended: July 2007 Contents Chapter 1: Introduction 1 1. The subject’s importance, and how to study it..........................................1 2. Obstacles to our knowledge of the human mind........................................2 3. The present state of this part of philosophy: Descartes, Malebranche and Locke......................4 4. In defence of those philosophers.................................................6 5. Bishop Berkeley. ·Hume’s· Treatise of Human Nature. Scepticism..............................7 6. The Treatise of Human Nature ..................................................9 7. The system of all these authors is the same, and it leads to scepticism..........................9 8. We ought not to despair of finding a better system...................................... 10 Chapter 2: Smelling 11 1. The order in which I shall take things. The medium of smelling and the organ of smell.................. 11 2. The sensation ·of smell· considered abstractly......................................... 12 3. Sensation and memory: natural producers of belief...................................... 13 Inquiry into the Human Mind Thomas Reid 4. Sometimes judgment and belief precede simple apprehension................................ 14 5. Two theories of the nature of belief refuted.
    [Show full text]
  • Reid on the Priority of Natural Language*
    Reid on the priority of natural language* JOHN TURRI [email protected] Abstract: Thomas Reid distinguished between natural and artificial language and argued that natural language has a very specific sort of priority over artificial language. This paper critically interprets Reid’s discussion, extracts a Reidian explanatory argument for the priority of natural language, and places Reid’s thought in the broad tradition of Cartesian linguistics. 1. Introduction Noam Chomsky’s work on human language reignited a dormant tradition of studying language as a way of revealing something im­ portant about human nature (Chomsky 1957). Chomsky traces the roots of his approach back through Wilhelm von Humboldt and Rene Descartes (Chomsky 1966). This tradition — what Chomsky calls Cartesian linguistics — treats the creative human use of lan­ guage as especially noteworthy, in two senses. On the one hand, the available evidence seems woefully inadequate to account for the lin­ guistic competence humans acquire. On the other hand, humans * This is the penultimate version (2013­08­10) of a paper forthcoming in Ca­ nadian Journal of Philosophy. Please cite the final, published version if possible. 1 John Turri | 2 routinely invent novel ways of expressing themselves, which other humans have little difficulty understanding, despite the novelty. Thomas Reid fits comfortably into this tradition. Reid thought that language ought to be studied because doing so promises “to lay open some of the first principles of human nature” and in particular the human mind (Reid 1764: 51). One purpose of this paper is to demonstrate, through a careful analysis of Reid’s central argument in this area, how naturally Reid fits into the Cartesian linguistic tra­ dition.
    [Show full text]
  • Reid on the Real Foundation of the Primary/Secondary Quality Distinction
    Forthcoming in Primary and Secondary Qualities: The Historical and Ongoing Debate, edited by Larry Nolan (Oxford: Oxford University Press). Reid on the Real Foundation of the Primary/Secondary Quality Distinction James Van Cleve The distinction betwixt primary and secondary qualities hath had several revolutions. Democritus and Epicurus, and their followers, maintained it. Aristotle and the Peripatetics abolished it. Des Cartes, Malebranche, and Locke, revived it, and were thought to have put it in a very clear light. But Bishop Berkeley again discarded this distinction, by such proofs as must be convincing to those that hold the received doctrine of ideas. Yet, after all, there appears to be a real foundation for it in the principles of our nature. Thomas Reid1 Every student of philosophy knows how to draw up the lists of primary and secondary qualities. On the left go extension, size, shape or figure, solidity, motion or rest, and number; on the right go color, sound, scent, taste, heat and cold. But what is the principle of the distinction? Does it have to do with objective versus subjective? Categorical versus dispositional? Intrinsic versus extrinsic? Or something else? And does the distinction stand up to the criticisms that various philosophers have made of it? In this chapter, I expound the answers to these questions given or made possible by Thomas Reid. 1. Reid’s relation to Locke and Berkeley 1 Thomas Reid, An Inquiry into the Human Mind on the Principles of Common Sense, edited by Derek R. Brookes (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 1997; first published in 1764), Chapter 5, Section 4, p.
    [Show full text]
  • The University of Western Ontario Department of Philosophy Graduate Course Outline 2018-19
    THE UNIVERSITY OF WESTERN ONTARIO DEPARTMENT OF PHILOSOPHY GRADUATE COURSE OUTLINE 2018-19 Philoso 9xxxA: Survey of Early Modern Western Philosophy of Language Fall Term 2018 Benjamin Hill M 11:30-2:30 StvH 3140, StvH 1145 Mon 9:30-10:30 Wed 10:30-11:30 by appointment [email protected] Description This is a graduate level survey course. The early modern era was a time of revolutionary philosophical developments and profound conceptual changes. Among many others, it produced significant changes in Western Philosophy’s conceptions of mind and language. Indeed, the core of the contemporary Western conceptions of mind and language were formed during this era. More importantly, these changes are not unrelated. This graduate level survey course will explore what those changes were, how they emerged, and why they happened. The change was from a largely formalistic conception of language that considered language an inessential “gift from God,” reflective of human thought and by and large continuous with natural expressions and animal communication and toward a more activity-based conception of language that emphasized it was distinctly human, spontaneously emerging from human nature, constitutive of human thought and cognition, and radically non-natural. Figures to be studied will include Lorenzo Valla, Michel de Montaigne, Antoine Arnauld and PierreDraft Nicole, Geraud Cordemoy, John Locke, John Wilkins, Gottfried Leibniz, Etienne Bonnot de Condillac, Thomas Reid, Adam Smith, Denis Diderot, Johann Gottfried von Herder, and Wilhelm von Humboldt.
    [Show full text]
  • Instinct and Explanation in Thomas Reid's Theory of Action
    RUCH FILOZOFICZNY LXXIV 2018 3 Chris Lindsay University of Glasgow, Scotland ORCID: 0000-0003-1693-4943 e-mail: [email protected] Instinct and Explanation in Thomas Reid’s Theory of Action http://dx.doi.org/10.12775/RF.2018.027 Introduction In his account of what he calls the ‘mechanical principles’ of action, Thomas Reid distinguishes between deliberate, willed actions and those caused by instincts or habits. He holds that that agents can only be held morally responsible with respect to willed actions, as it is only in such cases that the agent acts freely on his libertarian model of agency. Nev- ertheless, in his later writings Reid seems to suggest that instinctual be- haviour is both prior to and a precondition for the performance of free action. In this brief paper, I want to first introduce Reid’s theory of ac- tion and then expand upon this account in order to show that it goes some way to mitigate the criticisms raised by Louis Loeb and others against Reid, namely that Reid is content to rest with an account that rejects any attempt to explain the origin of beliefs that arise from human nature. Loeb portrays Hume as the superior philosopher due in part to his willingness to open up the black box of the mind for scientific inspec- tion. I want to claim that Loeb misses the mark here; despite the fact that Hume does attempt to give us a psychological account of the origins of certain beliefs, it is crippled by the implausible restrictions Hume places on his system.
    [Show full text]
  • Thomas Reid on Character and Freedom
    Thomas Reid on Character and Freedom Kenneth L. Pearce University of Southern California 159 Recent challenges notwithstanding,1 it is widely held that a necessary con- dition of freedom is the power or ability to do otherwise. It is also widely held that the power to do something entails the possibility of doing it: that is, if S has the power to φ, then, possibly, S φs. This condition is, however, hardly sufficient. It is possible that I should walk through walls, but I do not have the power to walk through walls, because this possibility is distant and, indeed, outlandish. A common way of ruling out these sorts of cases is to insist that in order for me to have the power to perform some action, there must be a possible world sufficiently similar to the actual world in which I perform that action. Incompatiblists understand this ‘sufficient similarity' condition as requiring that, in order for me to have the power to perform some action, my performing that action must be consistent with all the actual facts about the past and the laws of nature: I do not have the power to perform any action that the past and the laws of nature together entail that I do not perform. Thomas Reid is often held up as a classic exemplar of this view.2 Reid holds that in order for me to have the power to perform some action, all the necessary conditions for my performing that action must either already obtain or be within my power to bring about.
    [Show full text]