C U R R I C U L U M V I T a E Tom L. Beauchamp Professor of Philosophy, Philosophy Department, and Senior Research Scholar At

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

C U R R I C U L U M V I T a E Tom L. Beauchamp Professor of Philosophy, Philosophy Department, and Senior Research Scholar At C U R R I C U L U M V I T A E Tom L. Beauchamp Professor of Philosophy, Philosophy Department, and Senior Research Scholar at the Kennedy Institute of Ethics Georgetown University Washington, D.C. 20057 Home Mailing Address: 3173 Porter St NW; Washington, DC 20008 DEGREES AND APPOINTMENTS: 1963 - B.A., M.A. Southern Methodist University 1966 - B.D., Yale University 1970 - Ph.D., The Johns Hopkins University (Philosophy) 1970 - Assistant Professor, Georgetown University 1975 - Associate Professor, Georgetown University 1979 - Professor, Georgetown University CURRENT PROFESSIONAL POSITIONS: General Editor, with David Fate Norton and M. A. Stewart The Critical Edition of the Works of David Hume, Clarendon Press, Oxford University Press. Editorial Board Member Journal of Medicine and Philosophy Hume Studies 2 PUBLICATIONS: Books Authored Principles of Biomedical Ethics (Oxford University Press, 1979; sixth Edition 2009), coauthor: James F. Childress. Japanese translation (Tokyo, 1994, of the third edition; Tokyo, 2009, of the fifth edition); Polish translation (Ksiaska i Wiedza, 1998); Spanish translation (Masson, 1999); Portuguese translation (Sao Paulo, 2002); French Edition (Paris 2008); German translation in preparation at Jena University. Standing on Principles (Oxford University Press, 2010). Hume and the Problem of Causation (Oxford University Press, 1981), coauthor: Alexander Rosenberg. Philosophical Ethics (McGraw-Hill, 1982; Second Edition, 1991; Third Edition, 2001). Medical Ethics (Prentice-Hall, 1984), coauthor: Laurence McCullough. Spanish translation (Barcelona, 1987); Japanese Translation (MDP, J. Munkata, 1992). A History and Theory of Informed Consent (Oxford University Press, 1986), coauthor: Ruth R. Faden. Japanese translation (Misuzu Shobo, 1992). The Virtuous Journalist (Oxford University Press, 1987), coauthor: Stephen Klaidman. Case Studies in Business, Society, and Ethics (Prentice-Hall, 1983; Fifth Edition, 2003). The Human Use of Animals (Oxford University Press, 1998; Second Edition, 2008), coauthors: F. Barbara Orlans, Rebecca Dresser, David B. Morton, and John P. Gluck. The Clarendon Hume and Oxford Philosophical Text Editions of Hume An Enquiry concerning the Principles of Morals (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1998) – in The Clarendon Edition of the Works of David Hume [New Paperback edn. published 2006]. (Partial German translation in progress, trans. 3 Dr. K. Hepfer). An Enquiry concerning Human Understanding (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2000) – in The Clarendon Edition of the Works of David Hume [New Paperback edn. published 2006]. (Partial Portuguese translation in progress, trans. Michael Wrigley). A Dissertation on the Passions and The Natural History of Religion (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2007) – in The Clarendon Edition of the Works of David Hume. An Enquiry concerning the Principles of Morals (Oxford: OUP, 1998) – The Oxford Philosophical Texts Edition for Students. An Enquiry concerning Human Understanding (Oxford: OUP, 1999) – The Oxford Philosophical Texts Edition for Students. Books Edited Oxford Handbook of Business Ethics (Oxford University Press, 2009), coeditor: George Brenkert. Oxford Handbook of Animals and Ethics (Oxford University Press, 2011), coeditor: R. G. Frey. [forthcoming] Philosophical Problems of Causation (Dickenson/Wadsworth, 1974). Ethics and Public Policy (Prentice-Hall, 1975; Second Edition, 1982), coeditor: Terry Pinkard. Thomas Reid: Critical Interpretations (Philosophical Monographs, 1976), coeditor: Stephen F. Barker. Contemporary Issues in Bioethics (Wadsworth, 1978; Seventh Edition, 2008), coeditors: LeRoy Walters, Jeffrey Kahn, and Anna Mastroianni. Ethical Issues in Death and Dying (Prentice-Hall, 1978, coeditor: Seymour Perlin; Second Edition, 1996, coeditor: Robert M. Veatch). Ethical Theory and Business (Prentice-Hall, 1979; Eighth Edition, 2008), coeditors: Norman Bowie and Denis Arnold. 4 Philosophy and the Human Condition (Prentice-Hall, 1980; Second Edition, 1989), coeditors: Joel Feinberg and James Smith. Ethical Issues in Social Science Research (The Johns Hopkins University Press, 1982), coeditors: Ruth R. Faden, R. Jay Wallace, Jr., and LeRoy Walters. Ethics and Epidemiology (Oxford University Press, 1996; second edition, 2009), coeditors: Steven S. Coughlin and Douglas Weed. Intending Death: The Ethics of Assisted Suicide and Euthanasia (Prentice-Hall, 1996). Monograph and Special Journal Issue Special Issue of Journal of Clinical Epidemiology 44 (Suppl. I) (1991), issued in hardbound edition as Ethics and Epidemiology (Pergamon Press, 1991), coeditors: William Fayerweather, William Higginson. Electronic Edition HUMETEXT 1.0: a complete electronic edition of David Hume's philosophical, political, and literary works. Nine works were published in January 1990, another in January 1991. (Coeditor: David Fate Norton.) Articles [1] "On Causal Irregularity: A Reply to Dretske and Snyder," PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE 40 (1973): 285-87. [2] "Critique of Pure Anarchism," CANADIAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY 3 (1973): 533-39 (Joint author: K. Witkowski). [3] "No Fact-Value Gap for Hume?," JOURNAL OF VALUE INQUIRY 7 (1973): 52-59. [4] "Hume's Two Theories of Causation," ARCHIV FÜR GESCHICHTE DER PHILOSOPHIE 55 (1973): 281-300. [5] "Cosmic Epochs and the Scope of Scientific Laws," PROCESS STUDIES 2 (1972-73): 296-300. [6] "Hume on Causal Contiguity and Causal Succession," DIALOGUE 13 5 (1974): 271-82. [7] "Is Hume Really a Sceptic About Induction?," AMERICAN PHILOSOPHICAL QUARTERLY 12 (1975): 119-29 (Joint author: T. Mappes). [8] "On von Wright's Argument for Backward Causation," RATIO 17 (1975): 99-103 (Joint author: D. Robinson). [9] "Singular Causal Statements: A Reconsideration," PHILOSOPHICAL FORUM 5 (1975): 611-18 (Joint author: A. Rosenberg). [10] "On Justifications for Coercive Genetic Intervention," in R. Almeder and J. Humber, eds., Biomedical Ethics and the Law (New York: Plenum Press, 1976): 361-73. [11] "An Analysis of Hume's Essay 'On Suicide'," THE REVIEW OF METAPHYSICS 30 (1976): 73-95. [12] "The Justification of Reverse Discrimination," in W. Blackstone and R. Heslep, eds., Social Justice and Preferential Treatment (Athens, GA: University of Georgia Press, 1977): 84-110. (Reprinted in several anthologies.) [13] "Paternalism and Bio-behavioral Control," THE MONIST 60 (1977): 62-80. [14] "Rachels on the Distinction between Active and Passive Euthanasia," in T. Mappes and J. Zembaty, eds., Social Ethics (New York: McGraw-Hill, 1977): 67-75. Reprinted in several anthologies. Translated into German, in Medizin und Ethik, ed. Dietrich Klose. Published in Japanese. [15] "Cracks in The Cement of the Universe," CANADIAN JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY 7 (1977): 371-404. (Essay review of John Mackie's The Cement of the Universe, coauthored with Alex Rosenberg.) [16] "Distributive Justice," Appendix A to The Belmont Report: Ethical Guidelines for the Protection of Human Subjects of Research. DHEW Publication No. (OS) 78-0013 (1978), National Commission for the Protection of Human Subjects, Washington, D.C., 1976. [17] "The Definition of Euthanasia," JOURNAL OF MEDICINE AND PHILOSOPHY 4 (1979) (coauthored with Arnold Davidson), and reprinted in S. Gorovitz, et al., eds., Moral Problems in Medicine, 2nd ed. (Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall, 1983). 6 [18] "Paternalism," in Warren T. Reich, ed., Encyclopedia of Bioethics (New York: Free Press, 1978; third edition, 1995): 1194-1201. [19] "Should Recombinant DNA Research be Regulated?," in John Richards, ed., Science, Ethics, and Politics (New York: Academic Press, 1978): 225-40. [20] "Personal Identity: Reid's Answer to Hume," THE MONIST 61 (1978): 326-39 (coauthored with D. Robinson). [21] "The Regulation of Hazards and Hazardous Behaviors," HEALTH EDUCATION MONOGRAPHS 6 (1978): 242-57 (coauthored with Ruth Faden). [22] "What is Suicide?," in Ethical Issues in Death and Dying (above): 97-102. [23] "Morality and the Social Control of Biomedical Technology," in H. Tristram Engelhardt, Jr. and Stuart F. Spicker, eds., The Moral Use of New Knowledge in the Biomedical Sciences, Philosophy and Medicine Series (Boston: Reidel Publishing Co., 1979). [24] "The Right to Health and the Right to Health Care," JOURNAL OF MEDICINE AND PHILOSOPHY 4 (1979): 118-31 (coauthored with Ruth R. Faden). [25] "Self Inconsistency or Mere Self Perplexity?: Hume on Personal Identity," HUME STUDIES 5 (1979): 37-44. [26] "Medical, Moral, and Legal Aspects of Renal Replacement Theory," Parts I and II, in PROCEEDINGS OF THE CLINICAL DIALYSIS AND TRANSPLANT FORUM, Vols. VII, VIII (November 1977 and November 1978) (Joint authors: Arnold Siemsen and John Robertson). [27] "Decision-Making and Informed Consent: A Study of the Impact of Disclosed Information," SOCIAL INDICATORS RESEARCH 7 (1980): 313-36 (coauthored with Ruth R. Faden). [28] "The Foundations of Ethics and the Foundations of Science," in H. Tristram Engelhardt, Jr. and Daniel Callahan, eds., Volume IV, The Foundations of Ethics and Its Relationship to Science Series (Hastings-on-Hudson, N.Y.: The Hastings Center, 1979): 260-68. [29] "Utilitarianism and Cost/Benefit Analysis," in Ethical Theory and Business, lst ed.: 276-82. 7 [30] "Distributive Justice and the Difference Principle," in H. Gene Blocker and Elizabeth Smith, eds., John Rawls' Theory of Social Justice: An Introduction (Athens, Ohio: Ohio University Press, 1980): 132-61. [31] "Blackstone and the Problem of Reverse Discrimination," SOCIAL THEORY AND PRACTICE 5 (1979): 227-38. [32] "The Right to Food," in Burton Leiser, ed., Values in
Recommended publications
  • The Impossibility of Informed Consent?
    JME40: Good medical ethics J Med Ethics: first published as 10.1136/medethics-2014-102308 on 16 December 2014. Downloaded from PAPER The impossibility of informed consent? Kenneth Boyd Correspondence to ABSTRACT medical ethics’ over the 40 years of the Journal’s Professor Kenneth Boyd, The problematic nature of informed consent to medical publication. Biomedical Teaching Organisation, Edinburgh treatment and research, and its relation to autonomy, trust and clinical practice, has been addressed on many University, Edinburgh, Scotland Surveying the scene: the law and ethics of EH89AG, UK; occasions and from a variety of ethical perspectives in informed consent to treatment and research [email protected] the pages of the Journal of Medical Ethics. This paper Two early and wide-ranging contributions on medi- gives an account of how discussion of these issues has Received 1 September 2014 colegal and ethical aspects of informed consent developed and changed, by describing a number of Revised 26 September 2014 were made in papers by judge Kirby3 of Australia Accepted 23 October 2014 significant contributions to these debates which provide in 1983 and paediatrician Silverman4 of the USA in examples of ‘doing good medical ethics’ over the 1989. Both agreed that a paternalist or beneficence- 40 years of the Journal’s publication. based approach, in which the doctor recommends a course of treatment to which the patient either con- sents or refuses, had properly been superseded by THE IMPOSSIBILITY OF INFORMED CONSENT? an approach based on respect for the autonomy or Awareness that informed consent is problematic, in right to self-determination of the individual theory and in practice, was already evident in the patient.
    [Show full text]
  • Whose Life Is It Anyway? a Study in Respect for Autonomy
    Journal ofmedical ethics 1995; 21: 179-183 J Med Ethics: first published as 10.1136/jme.21.3.179 on 1 June 1995. Downloaded from Medicine and literature Whose Life Is It Anyway? A study in respect for autonomy Margaret Norden Marymount University, Arlington, Virginia, USA Abstract Precis of the story Brian Clark's drama, Whose Life Is It Anyway? (1), Whose Life Is It Anyway? opens with the explores the difficulties ofapplying the principle of hospitalization of Ken Harrison who was critically respect for autonomy to real-life circumstances. In the injured in an automobile accident four months play a permanently disabled patient, who wishes to be earlier and permanently paralyzed from the neck allowed to die, raises moral questions about the down. Although Ken arrived in critical condition, he adequacy of the autonomous agent, respect for the has since been stabilized, informed by his doctors autonomy ofothers, the authority of the law, the that his paralysis is permanent, and advised that he allocation ofsociety's resources, and the intrinsic value will be transferred to a long-term care facility. Facing ofhuman life. After a brief review of the story and the prospect of such an existence, Ken chooses not definition of respect for autonomy, this paper cites to live. He realizes that he could not survive outside passages from the play that dramatize the tension of an institution, and therefore, requests a discharge. between respect for autonomy and these other moral Although a psychiatrist confirms Ken's mental copyright. concerns. There follows a review of relevant competence, the hospital doctors refuse to discharge commentary from the classicists Kant and Mill and the him.
    [Show full text]
  • Haben Tiere Rechte? Eine Untersuchung Der Argumente Pro Und Contra Unter Besonderer Berücksichtigung Der Theorie Von Tom Regan
    Haben Tiere Rechte? Eine Untersuchung der Argumente pro und contra unter besonderer Berücksichtigung der Theorie von Tom Regan Dissertation zur Erlangung des philosophischen Doktorgrades an der Philosophischen Fakultät der Georg-August-Universität Göttingen vorgelegt von Wen-Yen Huang aus Chia-Yih, Taiwan Göttingen 2013 Erster Gutachter: Prof. Dr. Ulrich Majer Zweiter Gutachter: Prof. Dr. Holmer Steinfath Tag der mündlichen Prüfung: 11.12.2013 Inhaltsverzeichnis 1. Einleitung ………………………………………………………………………… 1 2. Betrachtung der Begriffe des Tiers und der Tierrechte ...…………………….. 2 2.1 Der Begriff des Tiers …………………………………………………….. 2 2.2 Der Begriff der Tierrechte ……………………………………………….. 5 3. Kurzer Abriss der Entwicklung der philosophischen Gedanken über Tiere in den westlichen Ländern …………………………………………………………... 24 4. Eine Auseinandersetzung mit vier Positionen, die Tieren keine Rechte zuschreiben ………………………………………………………………………... 33 4.1 Die Lehre der Tierautomaten von Descartes …………………………… 34 4.2 Eine kritische Auseinandersetzung mit der Lehre der Tierautomaten von Descartes ……………………………………………………………….. 38 4.3 Kants Lehre der indirekten Pflichten gegenüber Tieren ………………... 53 4.4 Eine kritische Auseinandersetzung mit der Lehre der indirekten Pflichten von Kant ……………………………………………………………….. 60 4.5 Der Kontraktualismus von John Rawls ………………………………… 70 4.6 Eine kritische Auseinandersetzung mit dem Kontraktualismus von Rawls ………………………………………………………………………….. 75 4.6.1 Eine Kritik an dem Kontraktualismus von Rawls ……………. 75 4.6.2 Die Idee der Gerechtigkeit bei Aristoteles ……………………. 95 4.7 Der Präferenz-Utilitarismus von Peter Singer ………………………… 103 4.8 Eine kritische Auseinandersetzung mit dem Präferenz-Utilitarismus von Singer …………………………………………………………………. 109 5. Über die Theorie der Tierrechte von Tom Regan …………………………... 116 5.1 Die Theorie der Tierrechte von Regan ……………………………...… 116 5.2 Eine Kritik an der Theorie der Tierrechte von Regan ……….……...… 129 6. Über die Begründung der Tierrechte ……………………………………..….
    [Show full text]
  • American Psychiatric Association the Principles of Medical Ethics
    American Psychiatric Association The Principles of Medical Ethics With Annotations Especially Applicable to Psychiatry 2013 Edition Copyright © 2010 American Psychiatric Association ALL RIGHTS RESERVED Manufactured in the United States of America 08 07 06 3 2 1 The Principles of Medical Ethics 2013 Edition (Previous editions 1973, 1978, 1981, 1984, 1985, 1989, 1992, 1993, 1995, 1995 Revised, 1998, 2001, 2001 Revised, 2006, 2008, 2009. 2009 Revised, and 2010 American Psychiatric Association 1000 Wilson Boulevard #1825 Arlington, VA 22209 THE PRINCIPLES OF MEDICAL ETHICS With Annotations Especially Applicable to Psychiatry 2013 Edition In 1973, the American Psychiatric Association (APA) published the first edition of The Principles of Medical Ethics with Annotations Especially Applicable to Psychiatry. Subsequently, revisions were published as the APA Board of Trustees and the APA Assembly approved additional annotations. In July of 1980, the American Medical Association (AMA) approved a new version of the Principles of Medical Ethics (the first revision since 1957), and the APA Ethics Committee1 incorporated many of its annotations into the new Principles, which resulted in the 1981 edition and subsequent revisions. This version includes changes to the Principles approved by the AMA in 2001. Foreword ALL PHYSICIANS should practice in accordance with the medical code of ethics set forth in the Principles of Medical Ethics of the American Medical Association. An up-to-date expression and elaboration of these statements is found in the Opinions and Reports of the Council on Ethical and Judicial Affairs of the American Medical Association.2 Psychiatrists are strongly advised to 3 be familiar with these documents. However, these general guidelines have sometimes been difficult to interpret for psychiatry, so further annotations to the basic principles are offered in this document.
    [Show full text]
  • Clinician Conscience Objection and Ethical Care of Patients
    1 VERMONT MEDICAL SOCIETY RESOLUTION 2 3 Clinician Conscience Objection and Ethical Care of Patients 4 5 As adopted at the VMS Annual Meeting on November 2, 2019 6 7 RESOLVED, that the VMS Policy on Physician Conscience be amended to read: The 8 Vermont Medical Society recognizes that the provision of certain types of medical care 9 or treatment can come in conflict with members’ cultural values, ethics or religious 10 beliefs. The Vermont Medical Society commits to protecting its members’ (physicians, 11 physician assistants, medical students) freedom to follow their own conscience in 12 deciding whether to participate in providing care or treatment, consistent with the 13 ethical norms of their professions, stated for physicians in AMA Code of Ethics Section 14 1.1.7, found in its entirety below, including fidelity to patients, respect for patient self- 15 determination, non-discrimination and informing the patient about all relevant options 16 for treatment, including options to which the physician morally objects, and information 17 regarding how to access such services. 18 19 AMA Code of Medical Ethics Opinion 1.1.7 20 Physicians are expected to uphold the ethical norms of their profession, including fidelity 21 to patients and respect for patient self-determination. Yet physicians are not defined 22 solely by their profession. They are moral agents in their own right and, like their 23 patients, are informed by and committed to diverse cultural, religious, and philosophical 24 traditions and beliefs. For some physicians, their professional calling is imbued with their 25 foundational beliefs as persons, and at times the expectation that physicians will put 26 patients’ needs and preferences first may be in tension with the need to sustain moral 27 integrity and continuity across both personal and professional life.
    [Show full text]
  • The Hippocratic Oath and Principles of Medical Ethics
    MEDICINE AND PUBLIC POLICY The Hippocratic Oath and Principles of Medical Ethics Gilbert Berdine MD The Hippocratic Oath is associated with the morally right. This tradition remains in the modern practice of medicine, but over time fewer medical era. “As God is my witness I hereby pledge to …” can graduates have taken any form of the Hippocratic be found in modern rituals to stress the seriousness Oath. As of 2006, the State University of New York of purpose. Courts in the U.S. require prospective Upstate Medical School in Syracuse was the only witnesses to pledge their truthfulness: “Do you sol- U.S. medical school that administered the classic emnly swear or affirm that you will tell the truth, the version of the Hippocratic Oath to its graduates. The whole truth, and nothing but the truth, so help you Hippocratic Oath has been revised to make it more God?” This pledge becomes a source of contention in acceptable to modern schools, but the medical pro- a multi-cultural society as some members believe in fession no longer has a common set of promises that other deities. guide it. This article will look at the classic version of the Hippocratic Oath to see why it has been aban- Anyone who takes his or her religion seriously doned. Modern medical students wish to graduate would not pledge to a pagan god as this would be a into an ancient order of physicians, so they long for form of idolatry. This pledge is probably the main rea- a solemn ceremony, but it is difficult to craft a solemn son that the Oath has been abandoned in the modern ceremony that remains agreeable to a diverse group era, but what can take its place as a symbol of seri- of students.
    [Show full text]
  • Glossary of Medical Ethics and Hospice Care
    Center for Bioethics and Health Policy Glossary of Medical Ethics and Hospice Care Before defining the terms commonly used in medical ethics and hospice care, it might be reasonable to ask: What is medical ethics and how does ethics differ from morals? Morals relates to the principles of right and wrong behavior, i.e., a specific act is right or it is wrong, end of question: to murder is wrong. Ethics, on the other hand, is a system of moral principles that apply values and judgments to accepted professional standards of conduct. Medical ethics evolve/devolve, i.e., what may have been considered ethical behavior in the 19th century may not be considered ethical in the 21st century and vice versa, e.g., eugenics was accepted as ethical behavior in the early 20th century. The Tuskegee study was accepted from its inception in the mid 1930s until it was abruptly discontinued in 1972. Advanced Health Care Directive (Living Will) - a document in which a person gives advanced directions about medical care, or designates who should make medical decisions for the person if they should lose their decision making capacity, or both. There are two types: treatment directive (Living Will), and proxy/surrogate directives (Healthcare Power of Attorney). Allow Natural Death (Allow to Die) – involves the withholding or withdrawing of life- sustaining treatment that is judged by the patient or proxy to be excessively burdensome and/or of little or no benefit. It involves a decision to no longer prevent the underlying disease process or pathology to run its course. Assent – a concept that applies to minors and refers to their right to have their own perspective represented in all decision making about their health care.
    [Show full text]
  • Downloadable%20File/New Published Maps and Institutional Affiliations
    Swazo et al. Philosophy, Ethics, and Humanities in Medicine (2020) 15:7 https://doi.org/10.1186/s13010-020-00091-6 RESEARCH Open Access A Duty to treat? A Right to refrain? Bangladeshi physicians in moral dilemma during COVID-19 Norman K. Swazo1*, Md. Munir Hossain Talukder2 and Mohammad Kamrul Ahsan2 Abstract Background: Normally, physicians understand they have a duty to treat patients, and they perform accordingly consistent with codes of medical practice, standards of care, and inner moral motivation. In the case of COVID-19 pandemic in a developing country such as Bangladesh, however, the fact is that some physicians decline either to report for duty or to treat patients presenting with COVID-19 symptoms. At issue ethically is whether such medical practitioners are to be automatically disciplined for dereliction of duty and gross negligence; or, on the contrary, such physicians may legitimately claim a professional right of autonomous judgment, on the basis of which professional right they may justifiably decline to treat patients. Methods: This ethical issue is examined with a view to providing some guidance and recommendations, insofar as the conditions of medical practice in an under-resourced country such as Bangladesh are vastly different from medical practice in an industrialized nation such as the USA. The concept of moral dilemma as discussed by philosopher Michael Shaw Perry and philosopher Immanuel Kant’s views on moral appeal to “emergency” are considered pertinent to sorting through the moral conundrum of medical care during pandemic. Results: Our analysis allows for conditional physician discretion in the decision to treat COVID-19 patients, i.e., in the absence of personal protective equipment (PPE) combined with claim of duty to family.
    [Show full text]
  • Ethics & Behavior Opposing Views on Animal Experimentation
    This article was downloaded by: [Vienna University Library] On: 25 February 2011 Access details: Access Details: [subscription number 931547535] Publisher Routledge Informa Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office: Mortimer House, 37- 41 Mortimer Street, London W1T 3JH, UK Ethics & Behavior Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information: http://www.informaworld.com/smpp/title~content=t782890670 Opposing Views on Animal Experimentation: Do Animals Have Rights? Tom L. Beauchamp Online publication date: 08 January 2010 To cite this Article Beauchamp, Tom L.(1997) 'Opposing Views on Animal Experimentation: Do Animals Have Rights?', Ethics & Behavior, 7: 2, 113 — 121 To link to this Article: DOI: 10.1207/s15327019eb0702_3 URL: http://dx.doi.org/10.1207/s15327019eb0702_3 PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE Full terms and conditions of use: http://www.informaworld.com/terms-and-conditions-of-access.pdf This article may be used for research, teaching and private study purposes. Any substantial or systematic reproduction, re-distribution, re-selling, loan or sub-licensing, systematic supply or distribution in any form to anyone is expressly forbidden. The publisher does not give any warranty express or implied or make any representation that the contents will be complete or accurate or up to date. The accuracy of any instructions, formulae and drug doses should be independently verified with primary sources. The publisher shall not be liable for any loss, actions, claims, proceedings, demand or costs or damages whatsoever or howsoever caused arising directly or indirectly in connection with or arising out of the use of this material. ETHICS & BEHAVIOR, 7(2), 113-121 Copyright O 1997, Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, Inc.
    [Show full text]
  • WMA Medical Ethics Manual
    3rd edition 2015 2 1 WORLD MEDICAL ASSOCIATION Medical Ethics Manual World Medical Association Medical Ethics Medical Ethics Manual – Principal Features of Manual 3rd edition 2015 Medical student holding a newborn © Roger Ball/CORBIS 2 1 © 2015 by The World Medical Association, Inc. TABLE OF CONTENTS All rights reserved. Up to 10 copies of this document may be made for your non-commercial personal use, provided that Acknowledgments ...................................................................................4 credit is given to the original source. You must have prior written Foreword ........................................................................................................5 permission for any other reproduction, storage in a retrieval system or transmission, in any form or by any means. Requests Introduction ..................................................................................................7 for permission should be directed to The World Medical · What is medical ethics? Association, B.P. 63, 01212 Ferney-Voltaire Cedex, France; · Why study medical ethics? email: [email protected], fax (+33) 450 40 59 37. · Medical ethics, medical professionalism, human rights and of Contents Table Medical Ethics Manual – law This Manual is a publication of the World Medical Association. · Conclusion It was written by John R. Williams, Director of Ethics, ...14 WMA (2003-2006) Chapter One – Principal Features of Medical Ethics Medical Ethics Manual – Principal Features of · Objectives Cover, design and concept by Tuuli Sauren, · What’s special about medicine? INSPIRIT International Communications, Belgium. · What’s special about medical ethics? Production and concept by · Who decides what is ethical? World Health Communication Associates, UK. · Does medical ethics change? Pictures by Van Parys Media/CORBIS · Does medical ethics differ from one country to another? · The role of the WMA Cataloguing-in-Publication Data · How does the WMA decide what is ethical? Williams, John R.
    [Show full text]
  • Table 1. a Short Description of Subfields As an Indicator. Table 2. A
    Appendix tables Table 1. A short description of subfields as an indicator. Subfield Description General General bioethics covers topics relevant to the history, development, bioethics methods and overview of the bioethics or its subfields. Clinical ethics Clinical or medical ethics covers general issues of bioethics, including health care systems, provider payment systems, health equity and justice, death and disability. Research ethics Research ethics covers everything relevant with research, including researchers’ integrity, methods and biobanks. Biotech ethics Biotech ethics covers advanced technologies in medicine and health, including nanotechnology, genetics and artificial intelligence. Public health Public health ethics covers topics relevant with public health, including public ethics participation, advertising, community health, smoke control, organ distribution and organ transplantation. Neuroethics Neuroethics covers topics relevant with mental health and psychiatry, including neurocognitive mechanisms of morality and ethics. Professional Professional ethics covers professional ethics, moral distress and education. ethics Religious Religious bioethics covers topics relevant with faith and religion. bioethics Law and Law and bioethics covers every topic relevant with regulations, laws and legal bioethics systems. Environmental Environmental ethics covers ethical issues relevant to local and global ethics environments, climate change and ecosystems. Table 2. A short description of selected topics Topic Description End of life issues Issues such as withdrawing/withholding treatment, brain death, advance directives, terminal care, etc. Patient decision Issues such as patient autonomy, informed consent, and issues relevant making to patient making decision in clinical and research settings. Reproduction issues Issues such as abortion, eugenics, surrogacy, cesarean, and IVF, etc. Enhancement Issues relevant to physical and cognitive enhancement, moral enhance, etc.
    [Show full text]
  • Informed Consent
    AMA | JAMA Network | AMA Store Informed Consent Informed consent is more than simply getting a patient to sign a written consent form. It is a process of communication between a patient and physician that results in the patient's authorization or agreement to undergo a specific medical intervention. In the communications process, you, as the physician providing or performing the treatment and/or procedure (not a delegated representative), should disclose and discuss with your patient: The patient's diagnosis, if known; The nature and purpose of a proposed treatment or procedure; The risks and benefits of a proposed treatment or procedure; Alternatives (regardless of their cost or the extent to which the treatment options are covered by health insurance); The risks and benefits of the alternative treatment or procedure; and The risks and benefits of not receiving or undergoing a treatment or procedure. In turn, your patient should have an opportunity to ask questions to elicit a better understanding of the treatment or procedure, so that he or she can make an informed decision to proceed or to refuse a particular course of medical intervention. This communications process, or a variation thereof, is both an ethical obligation and a legal requirement spelled out in statutes and case law in all 50 states. Patient autonomy is the overarching ethical consideration that forms the core of informed consent. The AMA’s Code of Medical Ethics states that physicians must provide relevant information to their patients. The full disclosure of relevant information to patients is intended to protect each patient’s right to self-determination, bodily integrity, and to protect his or her voluntariness in the healthcare decisionmaking process.
    [Show full text]