Books Reviewed Roger Hancock

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Books Reviewed Roger Hancock Notre Dame Law School NDLScholarship Natural Law Forum 1-1-1961 Books Reviewed Roger Hancock Felice Battaglia Edgar Bodenheimer Thomas Broden Jr. Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarship.law.nd.edu/nd_naturallaw_forum Part of the Law Commons Recommended Citation Hancock, Roger; Battaglia, Felice; Bodenheimer, Edgar; and Broden, Thomas Jr., "Books Reviewed" (1961). Natural Law Forum. Paper 66. http://scholarship.law.nd.edu/nd_naturallaw_forum/66 This Book Review is brought to you for free and open access by NDLScholarship. It has been accepted for inclusion in Natural Law Forum by an authorized administrator of NDLScholarship. For more information, please contact [email protected]. BOOKS REVIEWED CAUSATION IN THE LAW. By H. L. A. Hart and A. M. Honor6. Oxford: The Clarendon Press, 1959. Pp. xxxii, 454. 55s. In this work Professor H. L. A. Hart, well known in Britain and America for his work in legal and moral philosophy, has collaborated with A. M. Honor6 in a careful and comprehensive study of causality in legal theory and practice. The authors have worked on the subject a number of years, earlier versions of some parts having appeared in joint articles in the Law Quarterly Review (1956). The authors have two main aims: (1) to explain our ordinary "common sense notions" of causality and show how these notions are widely used in law, and (2) to examine and criticize a "whole trend in legal thought" concerning causality, especially influential in the United States, which seeks to clarify and simplify the concept of causality. The two aims are closely related. In explaining ordinary notions of causality and showing their use in law the authors are (in part) trying to answer the objection that traditional ways of thinking about causality are hopelessly obscure or otherwise inadequate, and must be drastically revised. And in criticizing the modem theories the authors are trying to show that these theories blur or ignore important principles and distinctions embedded in our ordinary ways of thinking and recognized by courts. This is not to say that the authors completely reject the modem theories in favor of any tradi- tional theory of causality. They agree that much of the legal discussion of causality in the past has been "clouded over by metaphor." And in some ways they consider the modem theories a real advance. (In the following discussion I will try to show how far the authors go in admitting one basic clarification urged by the modem theorists, namely, the "bifurcation" of causal issues into factual and normative questions.) But in general spirit the work is conservative and cautionary, confident that common-sense notions (properly understood) can guide legal decisions, and suspicious of attempts to revise these notions radically in favor of allegedly scientific theories. In the following discussion I shall try, first, to summarize the argument of the book. Secondly, I shall consider some problems in the authors' analysis of ordinary causal concepts. And third, I shall comment on the criticism of the recent (American) theories of causality. Part I ("The Analysis of Causal Concepts") opens with a critical discussion of the analysis of causality in Hume and Mill (ch. 1), moves on to a dis- cussion of ordinary concepts of causality and responsibility (ch. 2 and 3), and NATURAL LAW FORUM discusses critically the modern theories. The central purpose of this Part is to analyze ordinary notions of causality; these are contrasted, on the one hand, with the philosophical theories of Hume and Mill, and on the other hand with the modern theories. The authors begin, in Ch. 1, by asking why lawyers have found the "phil- osophical discussion of causation" unhelpful. And the answer is, roughly stated, that philosophers traditionally have been concerned with causality in science, largely ignoring problems of causality in practical and moral contexts. To be sure, in examining philosophical theories of causality the authors consider only Hume and John Stuart Mill - in part, of course, because of their very great influence in modern philosophical discussions of causality, but also, perhaps, because the authors feel that a helpful philosophical discussion of causality is to be found, if at all, in empiricist philosophers such as Hume and Mill. One could argue, indeed, that if a philosophical theory of causality is to be helpful to lawyers it must be an empirical theory to this extent: it must define "causality" in such a way that statements asserting a causal relation can be supported or refuted by ordinary factual evidence. Presumably the problem of causality in the law is, in part, the problem of picking out the cause from among all the antecedents of an event: to be useful, a theory must give guidance to this pro- cess. It goes without saying that theories such as that of Leibniz, who held that "in metaphysical rigor" there are no causes at all but only concomitants, or F. H. Bradley's theory that the notion of causality is self-contradictory, are ir- relevant to law. A more interesting case is Kant's theory of causality. For Kant, causality is strictly a scientific concept, applicable exclusively to physical pro- cesses. Hence, as the authors point out in a later section, German legal theorists attempting to use the Kantian theory are forced into a curious position, name- ly, that "in considering whether a human actor has caused harm only the actor's physical movements may be regarded as relevant, not his state of mind: once it is found that such movements were the cause of harm the question whether the act was deliberate, mistaken, or accidental is relevant only to the question of fault or mens rea."l But even as applied to physical processes, Kant's theory does little to guide particular causal investigations. The authors praise Hume and Mill for having "swept away much lumber" traditionally encumbering the notion of causality, such as the notion of "un- observable forces or powers," and for having noticed that there is an intimate connection between particular causal judgments and generalizations asserting an invariable sequence. And Mill, in particular, is commended for noticing the ordinary distinction between the cause and other factors which are merely "neces- sary conditions." Mill's analysis is given a sympathetic treatment but criticized on several counts. The two most important objections are the following. (1) Mill (following Hume) was justified in stressing the rtle of generalizations asserting regular sequence; in many cases when we say that A caused B, part of our meaning is that events like A have invariably been followed by events like B. When we say that the sun warmed the stone - that this is a case of propter hoc and not simply post hoc - part of our meaning is that invariably in our ex- 1. HART and HONORi, CAUSATION IN THE LAW 385 (1959). ROGER HANCOCK perience bodies exposed to heat become warmer. But Mill overstated the case; there is a type of causation where generalizations do not play this r6le. These are cases of "interpersonal transactions" as the authors call them, cases where we say that a person caused another to act in a certain way by persuasion, threat, inducement, etc. Suppose A threatens to shoot B unless B gives over his money, which B then does. We should say that A made B give over his money, but in saying this we do not mean that in similar cases B, or anyone else, in- variably gives up his money. (2) Mill (again following Hume and the tradi- tional philosophical discussion of causality) concentrates on "explanatory con- texts" where, given an event, our search for the cause is a search for some un- known factor. But this ignores the "attributive inquiries" frequent in law - contexts where we know all the factors and in a sense clearly understand how an event happened, but are puzzled as to whether this or that factor is the cause. (This distinction prefigures the authors' later discussion of the "bifurca- tion" of causal questions.) In Ch. 2 the authors attempt a kind of reversal in the analysis of causality by treating everyday human actions as the starting point; the "central" or "basic" meaning of causality is found not in the language of science or in the demands of metaphysical rigor, but in the everyday language in which people are said to "push, pull, bend, twist, break, injure" things and other persons. From this basic meaning others are derived by analogy or metaphor. Two of these de- rived meanings are especially relevant to law: (1) "causing" in the sense of inducing, persuading, threatening, etc., someone to act, and (2) "causing" in the sense of providing or failing to provide an opportunity, as in causing a loss by carelessly leaving the door unlocked and thus allowing a theft to occur, or caus- ing loss to a manufacturer by failing to deliver the machinery as promised. In Ch. 3 the authors embark on a discussion of responsibility and raise the im- portant question of how we set limits to the consequences of an act, limits be- yond which we no longer consider the agent as the cause and hence as responsible. Chapter 4 introduces the modem theory, held in the most radical form by Leon Green. As the authors describe it this theory asserts that the question "Did A cause B?" means (if it is clear) two things: (1) would B have hap- pened if A had not acted as he did? (the sine qua non test) and (2) should A be held responsible or liable for B? The first question is considered to be a straightforward factual question, while the second is considered to be a "policy" question to be decided by appeal to legal policy, justice, or expediency.
Recommended publications
  • Duke University Dissertation Template
    A Sea of Debt: Histories of Commerce and Obligation in the Indian Ocean, c. 1850-1940 by Fahad Ahmad Bishara Department of History Duke University Date:_______________________ Approved: ___________________________ Edward J. Balleisen, Co-supervisor ___________________________ Engseng Ho, Co-supervisor ___________________________ Janet J. Ewald ___________________________ Timur Kuran ___________________________ Bruce S. Hall ___________________________ Jonathan K. Ocko Dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Department of History in the Graduate School of Duke University 2012 i v ABSTRACT A Sea of Debt: Histories of Commerce and Obligation in the Indian Ocean, c. 1850-1940 by Fahad Ahmad Bishara Department of History Duke University Date:_______________________ Approved: ___________________________ Edward J. Balleisen, Co-supervisor ___________________________ Engseng Ho, Co-supervisor ___________________________ Janet J. Ewald ___________________________ Timur Kuran ___________________________ Bruce S. Hall ___________________________ Jonathan K. Ocko An abstract of a dissertation submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Department of History in the Graduate School of Duke University 2012 Copyright by Fahad Ahmad Bishara 2012 ABSTRACT This dissertation is a legal history of debt and economic life in the Indian Ocean during the nineteenth and early-twentieth century. It draws on materials from Bahrain, Muscat, Bombay, Zanzibar and London to examine how members of an ocean-wide commercial society constructed relationships of economic mutualism with one another by mobilizing debt and credit. It further explores how they expressed their debt relationships through legal idioms, and how they mobilized commercial and legal instruments to adapt to the emergence of modern capitalism in the region.
    [Show full text]
  • Defending the Formal Federal Civil Rulemaking Process: Why the Court Should Not Amend Procedural Rules Through Judicial Interpretation
    SELLERS.CORRECTED.PAGES_331-32.342.362.370.373.386-87.389.DOC 12/15/2010 10:34:04 AM Note Defending the Formal Federal Civil Rulemaking Process: Why the Court Should Not Amend Procedural Rules Through Judicial Interpretation Nathan R. Sellers* I. INTRODUCTION The Federal Rules of Civil Procedure (“Rules”)1 govern procedure in the federal courts from the moment a lawsuit is filed until its final disposition, and they affect every stage of the litigation process.2 The Rules govern pleading,3 discovery,4 depositions,5 summary judgment,6 * Loyola University Chicago School of Law, Juris Doctor expected May 2011. I would like to thank the members of the Volume 42 Executive Board for publishing my article and for their insightful comments and criticisms. I also want to thank my parents, my brothers, and Kendahl for all of their love, support, and encouragement. 1. Where this Note refers to other types of rules promulgated by the Supreme Court, it will do so by explicit reference. 2.See FED. R. CIV. P. 1 (“These rules govern the procedure in all civil actions and proceedings in the United States district courts . .”). 3. Rule 8 establishes the general requirements for pleading. FED. R. CIV. P. 8. In this Note, “pleading” refers to the initial written filing submitted to a court by a plaintiff to initiate a civil case, setting forth the plaintiff’s claims and allegations. BLACK’S LAW DICTIONARY 1191 (8th ed. 2004) [hereinafter BLACK’S LAW] (citing FED. R. CIV. P. 8(a)). Generally speaking, pleadings have two functions. First, they permit the elimination from consideration of contentions that have no legal significance.
    [Show full text]
  • Jurisprudence: Readings and Cases
    The Catholic Lawyer Volume 13 Number 2 Volume 13, Spring 1967, Number 2 Article 9 Jurisprudence: Readings and Cases Dr. Miriam Theresa Rooney Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarship.law.stjohns.edu/tcl Part of the Jurisprudence Commons, and the Natural Law Commons This Book Review is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at St. John's Law Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in The Catholic Lawyer by an authorized editor of St. John's Law Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. BOOK REVIEW JURISPRUDENCE: READINGS AND CASES by Mark R. MacGuigan University of Toronto Press, Toronto, Ontario, Canada, 1966. Pp. 666. $20.00 Reviewed by DR. MIRIAM THERESA ROONEY * This is a worthwhile book. It is or- an Appendix, reviewing the present ganized in less than 700 pages, and is trends and prospects for Jurisprudence in therefore compact enough for basic class- Canada, where Common Law and Civil room use. Within such a limited space Law co-exist under one Constitution, it is amazingly comprehensive. Further- complete the presentation. more, it concentrates upon the problems Although the compiler includes ex- of Jurisprudence of the 1960's, without tensive excerpts from many of the books omitting indications of the more impor- which have become classics in Anglo- tant historical antecedents. American juridical thought, and consist- All the materials, which are highly ently presents them in a respectful and relevant, are skillfully edited, and ar- judicious manner, which ensures the use- ranged in a sequential order of cogency fulness of the book no matter what view- upon points currently at issue.
    [Show full text]
  • The Role of Textualism in the Progressive Toolbox
    TRACZ (DO NOT DELETE) 4/27/2021 11:15 PM WORDS AND THEIR MEANINGS: THE ROLE OF TEXTUALISM IN THE PROGRESSIVE TOOLBOX BY ELIOT T. TRACZ* I.INTRODUCTION ................................................................................................... 353 II.TEXTUALISM ........................................................................................................ 355 A. Textualism ............................................................................................. 355 i. Legislative intent ......................................................................... 355 ii. Textualism ...................................................................................... 358 B. Words and Their Meanings ............................................................ 359 C. Canons of Construction- What happens when the text is vague? ..................................................................................................... 361 D. Some Criticisms ................................................................................... 364 III.TEXTUALISM AS BIG “C” OR LITTLE “C” CONSERVATIVE ............ 365 IV.TEXTUALISM AS A PROGRESSIVE TOOL ............................................... 369 A. Past Examples of Textualism Helping a Progressive Agenda 370 B. Future Areas Where Textualism Can Support Progressive 371 i. Commonsense Gun Reform ..................................................... 371 ii. Qualified Immunity ..................................................................... 374 V. CONCLUSION .......................................................................................................
    [Show full text]
  • Download (2MB)
    Cunningham, Graeme James (2018) Law, rhetoric, and science: historical narratives in Roman law. PhD thesis. https://theses.gla.ac.uk/41030/ Copyright and moral rights for this work are retained by the author A copy can be downloaded for personal non-commercial research or study, without prior permission or charge This work cannot be reproduced or quoted extensively from without first obtaining permission in writing from the author The content must not be changed in any way or sold commercially in any format or medium without the formal permission of the author When referring to this work, full bibliographic details including the author, title, awarding institution and date of the thesis must be given Enlighten: Theses https://theses.gla.ac.uk/ [email protected] Law, Rhetoric, and Science: Historical Narratives in Roman Law. Graeme James Cunningham LL.B. (Hons.), LL.M., M.Litt. Submitted in fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy. School of Law, College of Social Sciences, University of Glasgow. September 2018 Abstract. The consensus of scholarship has upheld the view that Roman law is an autonomous science. A legal system, which, due to its systematic, doctrinal principles, was able to maintain an inherent and isolated logic within the confines of its own disciplinary boundaries, excluding extra-legal influence. The establishment of legal science supposedly took place in the late second to early first century BC, when the famed Roman jurist, Quintus Mucius Scaevola pontifex, is supposed to have first treated law in a scientific way under the guidance of Greek categorical thought.
    [Show full text]
  • The Questions of Abū Hanīfa Ebû Hanîfe'nin Sorulari
    Araştırma makalesi / HANIF, S. “The Questions of Abū Hanīfa” Diyanet İlmî Dergi 56 (2020): 1349-1404 Resarch article THE QUESTIONS OF ABŪ HANĪFA ABSTRACT This article assesses EBÛ HANÎFE’NİN SORULARI the contribution of Abū Ḥanīfa (d. 150/767) to the Geliş Tarihi: 16.09.2020 Kabul Tarihi: 17.12.2020 development of Islamic law through a study of SOHAIL HANIF the ‘legal question’, or DR. masʾala. The first section CAMBRIDGE MUSLIM COLLEGE presents anecdotal accounts [email protected] to illustrate the nature and reception of Abū Ḥanīfa’s questions. It also studies the spread of Abū Ḥanīfa’s questions through the writings of his students, particularly Muḥammad ibn al-Ḥasan al-Shaybānī (d. 189/805). The second section presents investigations into the development of legal questions addressing the topic of wiping over khuffs (leather socks) in ritual ablutions, assessing (1) the development of legal questions in the first two-and-a-half centuries of Islam, (2) the nature of ÖZ questions addressed by key second- and third-century Bu makale, Ebû Hanîfe’nin (ö. 150/767) İslâm hukukunun texts of the legal schools, gelişimine katkısını ‘hukukî soru’ veya ‘mesele’ and (3) the questions that çalışmasıyla değerlendirmektedir. İlk bölüm, Ebû constituted core school Hanîfe’nin sorularının doğasını ve kabulünü göstermek için doctrine in classical-era anekdot niteliğinde açıklamalar sunmaktadır. Ayrıca, Ebû mukhtaṣars (legal digests) Hanîfe’nin sorularının öğrencilerinin, özellikle Muhammed of the schools of law. bin Hasan eş-Şeybânî’nin
    [Show full text]
  • Yale Law School 2014–2015
    BULLETIN OF YALE UNIVERSITY BULLETIN OF YALE BULLETIN OF YALE UNIVERSITY Periodicals postage paid New Haven ct 06520-8227 New Haven, Connecticut Yale Law School 2014–2015 Yale Law School Yale 2014–2015 BULLETIN OF YALE UNIVERSITY Series 110 Number 10 August 10, 2014 BULLETIN OF YALE UNIVERSITY Series 110 Number 10 August 10, 2014 (USPS 078-500) The University is committed to basing judgments concerning the admission, education, is published seventeen times a year (one time in May and October; three times in June and employment of individuals upon their qualifications and abilities and a∞rmatively and September; four times in July; five times in August) by Yale University, 2 Whitney seeks to attract to its faculty, sta≠, and student body qualified persons of diverse back- Avenue, New Haven CT 0651o. Periodicals postage paid at New Haven, Connecticut. grounds. In accordance with this policy and as delineated by federal and Connecticut law, Yale does not discriminate in admissions, educational programs, or employment against Postmaster: Send address changes to Bulletin of Yale University, any individual on account of that individual’s sex, race, color, religion, age, disability, PO Box 208227, New Haven CT 06520-8227 status as a protected veteran, or national or ethnic origin; nor does Yale discriminate on the basis of sexual orientation or gender identity or expression. Managing Editor: Kimberly M. Go≠-Crews University policy is committed to a∞rmative action under law in employment of Editor: Lesley K. Baier women, minority group members, individuals with disabilities, and protected veterans. PO Box 208230, New Haven CT 06520-8230 Inquiries concerning these policies may be referred to Valarie Stanley, Director of the O∞ce for Equal Opportunity Programs, 221 Whitney Avenue, 3rd Floor, 203.432.0849.
    [Show full text]
  • The Paquete Habana: a Case History in the Development of International Law
    University of Baltimore Law Review Volume 15 Article 2 Issue 1 Fall 1985 1985 The aP quete Habana: A Case History in the Development of International Law Scott .W Stucky Federal Judge, U.S. Court of Appeals for the Armed Forces Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarworks.law.ubalt.edu/ublr Part of the International Law Commons Recommended Citation Stucky, Scott .W (1985) "The aP quete Habana: A Case History in the Development of International Law," University of Baltimore Law Review: Vol. 15: Iss. 1, Article 2. Available at: http://scholarworks.law.ubalt.edu/ublr/vol15/iss1/2 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by ScholarWorks@University of Baltimore School of Law. It has been accepted for inclusion in University of Baltimore Law Review by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks@University of Baltimore School of Law. For more information, please contact [email protected]. UNIVERSITY OF BALTIMORE LAW REVIEW Copyright © 1985 by The University of Baltimore Law Review. All rights reserved. Volume Fifteen Fall 1985 Number One THE PAQUETE HABANA: A CASE HISTORY IN THE DEVELOPMENT OF INTERNATIONAL LAW Scott w. Stuckyt In The Paquete Habana, decided in 1900, the United States Supreme Court adopted the doctrine that coastal fishing vessels are exempt from capture as prize of war. The Court held that the exemption was an estab­ lished custom of international law, which-in the absence of a controlling executive or judicial decision-should be incorporated into the corpus of our common law. The Paquete Habana influenced the development of positive rules of international law that expanded the class of civilian vessels that are exempt from capture.
    [Show full text]
  • Mats, P. 18–19, 26–28
    18 CONSTITUTIONAL HISTORY AND SOURCES OF LAW Sec. 1 47. After him of greatest authority were ATEIUS CAPITO, who followed Ofilius, and ANTISTLUS LABEO, who listened to all these, but was instructed by Trebatius. Of these Ateius was consul; Labeo, when the consulate was offered to him by Augustus, by which he would have become interim consul (suffectus), refused to take the office but gave his attention in the main to his studies. And he so divided the whole year that he was at Rome six months, six months away, and gave his attention to writing books. Accordingly, he left four hundred volumes, many of which are employed constantly. These two founded, as it were, respective schools; for Ateius Capito continued in those things which had been handed down to him; Labeo, by the quality of his originality and the faith of his own learning, having paid attention to other branches of knowledge, endeavored to innovate many things. 48. And so MASSURIUS SABINUS succeeded Ateius Capito, NERVA Labeo, who then increased these dissensions. This Nerva was very intimate with the emperor. Massurius Sabinus was in the equestrian order and was the first to respond publicly; afterwards, this privilege began to be given, which, however, had been granted to him by Tiberius Caesar. 49. And as we may observe in passing, before the time of Augustus the right of responding publicly (ius respondendi publice) was not given by the emperors, but he who had confidence in his studies responded to his consultants; nor were responsa always given under seal, but often they themselves wrote to the iudices (judge jurors) or were testified to by those who consulted them.
    [Show full text]
  • A New History of Colonial Lawyering: Likhovski and Legal Identities in the British Empire
    Law & Social Inquiry Volume 32, Issue 4, 1059–1094, Fall 2007 A Oxford,LSILaw0897-6546©XXXOriginalLAWBlackwell 2007New & & SocialHistory AmericanUKSOCIALArticles Publishing Inquiry of ColonialINQUIRY Bar Ltd NewFoundation. Lawyering History of Colonial Lawyering: Likhovski and Legal Identities in the British Empire Mitra Sharafi LIKHOVSKI, ASSAF. 2006. Law and Identity in Mandate Palestine. Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press. Pp. xi + 312. $49.95 cloth. The history of the legal profession has been dominated by Richard Abel’s monopolization thesis, and by Terence C. Halliday and Lucien Karpik’s political model of lawyers as maintainers of liberal polities. By contrast, Assaf Likhovski’s legal history of mandate Palestine treats lawyers and judges as cultural intermediaries who shaped the legal identity of Jewish and Arab communities. This article situates Likhovski’s book within a growing body of scholarship on non-European lawyering in the British Empire. It links Likhovski’s case studies to legal figures from colonial India, West Africa, and Malaya, all of whom acted as cultural translators and ethnographic intermediaries in the formation of colonial identities. INTRODUCTION Until recently, the history of the legal profession fell more under the spell of the sociology of the professions than under the influence of historians. Led by Richard Abel, the sociological literature focused almost exclusively Mitra Sharafi is Assistant Professor of Law and History, University of Wisconsin-Madison (sharafi@wisc.edu). Parts of this article were presented in earlier versions at the Hurst Legal History Institute at the University of Wisconsin-Madison (June 29, 2005); and in India at: the University College of Law in Dharwad (December 18, 2006), the Critical Legal Conference at the National Academy for Legal Study and Research (NALSAR) in Hyderabad (September 1, 2006), and Delhi University’s Department of History (February 1, 2007).
    [Show full text]
  • Law-Making and the Roman Jurists by Pnof ..J
    320 THE LAW JOURNAL Law-Making and the Roman Jurists By PnoF ..J. -AQUILINA, B.A., LJ.J._D., PH.D. (LoND_.) HE ''Law Journal'' published by the Student~' Law Society T bears on it8 cover the very 8'ignificant motto Legum servi sunnis ut l-iberi esse pussnnus. rrhe motto is very significant. It n1ay be considered as iihe -historical synthesis of Man's efforts to establish the very basis of personal freed01n within an organised community regulated by a set of laws, whi-ch guarantee him such freedom at the price of &i partial restriction ·of his own liberty of action within the sa1ne society. '.The wQrd lex, derives probably from the same root _licet, because laws to be effective ·must be binding upon. us all, and for this rea s~n1 the infringement of a law carries with it, a.s an inevitable consequence, a more_or less serious pu~ nishment. And yet, as :the Latin quotation says, in spite of the restriction of action that is inherent in every law, we are the willing servants of the Ze:.r . We willingly accept the comtnand o~ the law-giver, the oblig.ation imposed thereby upon us, and the sanction that is incurred in the event of disobedience. We accept the yoke of the law because survival without it is impossible, because where there is no law there is what is known as ''anar­ chy", a Greek word meaning "without ruler". This blind hatred of a ruler who lays down the law restricting absolu.te freedom whether in the ·name of social security or morality, has found a poetical exponent in that great visionary Percy Bysshe Shelley, whom Matthew Arnold has aptly described ·as "an ineffec~ual' angel beating in the votd his luminous wings in vain".
    [Show full text]
  • Introductory Concepts on Sociological Jurisprudence: Jhering, Durkheim, Ehrlich
    NOTES CORNER OTS CORNER INTRODUCTORY CONCEPTS ON SOCIOLOGICAL JURISPRUDENCE: JHERING, DURKHEIM, EHRLICH Elise Nalbandian♣ Introduction In his concept of Law, Hart describes his enterprise as being a study in “descriptive sociology” all the while explaining the rules according to which people in a society act and react. While undeniably a positivist theory of Law by his own admission, Hart’s theory tends to lean on and allude to concepts of sociological theory whose main and pervasive message is that “law is a social phenomenon”. To further clarify this concept, sociological jurists tend to focus on studying how law comes into existence and the manner of its operation and its impact on those to whom it applies. In so doing this school of thought goes beyond simply looking at the nature of law in legal terms but rather closely examines the workings of society in general by relying heavily on social sciences such as sociology, history, political science and economics to build a fuller picture of the workings and nature of law. Sociological Jurisprudence has a long and distinguished history and can be traced as far back as the writings of Hume who in “A Treatise on Human Nature” argued that law’s origin did not lie in a peculiar common conception of human nature at all. According to Hume, law owes its origins to social conventions and was in itself a developing social institution. In addition to Hume’s start on describing law as a social phenomenon, Montesquieu put forward the idea that law originated out of social custom and good laws therefore had to be in accordance with the spirit of the society.
    [Show full text]