Quantum Entanglement (Albeit He Did Not Cite Any Names) but Proposed to Use It in Order to Simulate Quantum Physics with Computers [F82]
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
Load more
Recommended publications
-
Study of Quantum Spin Correlations of Relativistic Electron Pairs
Study of quantum spin correlations of relativistic electron pairs Project status Nov. 2015 Jacek Ciborowski Marta Włodarczyk, Michał Drągowski, Artem Poliszczuk (UW) Joachim Enders, Yuliya Fritsche (TU Darmstadt) Warszawa 20.XI.2015 Quantum spin correlations In this exp: e1,e2 – electrons under study a, b - directions of spin projections (+- ½) 4 combinations for e1 and e2: ++, --, +-, -+ Probabilities: P++ , P+- , P-+ , P- - (ΣP=1) Correlation function : C = P++ + P-- - P-+ - P-+ Historical perspective • Einstein Podolsky Rosen (EPR) paradox (1935): QM is not a complete local realistic theory • Bohm & Aharonov formulation involving spin correlations (1957) • Bell inequalities (1964) a local realistic theory must obey a class of inequalities • practical approach to Bell’s inequalities: counting aacoincidences to measure correlations The EPR paradox Boris Podolsky Nathan Rosen Albert Einstein (1896-1966) (1909-1995) (1979-1955) A. Afriat and F. Selleri, The Einstein, Podolsky and Rosen Paradox (Plenum Press, New York and London, 1999) Bohm’s version with the spin Two spin-1/2 fermions in a singlet state: E.g. if spin projection of 1 on Z axis is measured 1/2 spin projection of 2 must be -1/2 All projections should be elements of reality (QM predicts that only S2 and David Bohm (1917-1992) Sz can be determined) Hidden variables? ”Quantum Theory” (1951) Phys. Rev. 85(1952)166,180 The Bell inequalities J.S.Bell: Impossible to reconcile the concept of hidden variables with statistical predictions of QM If local realism quantum correlations -
Quantum Eraser
Quantum Eraser March 18, 2015 It was in 1935 that Albert Einstein, with his collaborators Boris Podolsky and Nathan Rosen, exploiting the bizarre property of quantum entanglement (not yet known under that name which was coined in Schrödinger (1935)), noted that QM demands that systems maintain a variety of ‘correlational properties’ amongst their parts no matter how far the parts might be sepa- rated from each other (see 1935, the source of what has become known as the EPR paradox). In itself there appears to be nothing strange in this; such cor- relational properties are common in classical physics no less than in ordinary experience. Consider two qualitatively identical billiard balls approaching each other with equal but opposite velocities. The total momentum is zero. After they collide and rebound, measurement of the velocity of one ball will naturally reveal the velocity of the other. But the EPR argument coupled this observation with the orthodox Copen- hagen interpretation of QM, which states that until a measurement of a par- ticular property is made on a system, that system cannot, in general, be said to possess any definite value of that property. It is easy to see that if dis- tant correlations are preserved through measurement processes that ‘bring into being’ the measured values there is a prima facie conflict between the Copenhagen interpretation and the relativistic stricture that no information can be transmitted faster than the speed of light. Suppose, for example, we have a system with some property which is anti-correlated (in real cases, this property could be spin). -
Required Readings
HPS/PHIL 93872 Spring 2006 Historical Foundations of the Quantum Theory Don Howard, Instructor Required Readings: Topic: Readings: Planck and black-body radiation. Martin Klein. “Planck, Entropy, and Quanta, 19011906.” The Natural Philosopher 1 (1963), 83-108. Martin Klein. “Einstein’s First Paper on Quanta.” The Natural Einstein and the photo-electric effect. Philosopher 2 (1963), 59-86. Max Jammer. “Regularities in Line Spectra”; “Bohr’s Theory The Bohr model of the atom and spectral of the Hydrogen Atom.” In The Conceptual Development of series. Quantum Mechanics. New York: McGraw-Hill, 1966, pp. 62- 88. The Bohr-Sommerfeld “old” quantum Max Jammer. “The Older Quantum Theory.” In The Conceptual theory; Einstein on transition Development of Quantum Mechanics. New York: McGraw-Hill, probabilities. 1966, pp. 89-156. The Bohr-Kramers-Slater theory. Max Jammer. “The Transition to Quantum Mechanics.” In The Conceptual Development of Quantum Mechanics. New York: McGraw-Hill, 1966, pp. 157-195. Bose-Einstein statistics. Don Howard. “‘Nicht sein kann was nicht sein darf,’ or the Prehistory of EPR, 1909-1935: Einstein’s Early Worries about the Quantum Mechanics of Composite Systems.” In Sixty-Two Years of Uncertainty: Historical, Philosophical, and Physical Inquiries into the Foundations of Quantum Mechanics. Arthur Miller, ed. New York: Plenum, 1990, pp. 61-111. Max Jammer. “The Formation of Quantum Mechanics.” In The Schrödinger and wave mechanics; Conceptual Development of Quantum Mechanics. New York: Heisenberg and matrix mechanics. McGraw-Hill, 1966, pp. 196-280. James T. Cushing. “Early Attempts at Causal Theories: A De Broglie and the origins of pilot-wave Stillborn Program.” In Quantum Mechanics: Historical theory. -
A WORLD WITHOUT CAUSE and EFFECT Logic-Defying Experiments Into Quantum Causality Scramble the Notion of Time Itself
A WORLD WITHOUT CAUSE AND EFFECT Logic-defying experiments into quantum causality scramble the notion of time itself. BY PHILIP BALL lbert Einstein is heading out for his This finding1 in 2015 made the quantum the constraints of a predefined causal structure daily stroll and has to pass through world seem even stranger than scientists had might solve some problems faster than con- Atwo doorways. First he walks through thought. Walther’s experiments mash up cau- ventional quantum computers,” says quantum the green door, and then through the red one. sality: the idea that one thing leads to another. theorist Giulio Chiribella of the University of Or wait — did he go through the red first and It is as if the physicists have scrambled the con- Hong Kong. then the green? It must have been one or the cept of time itself, so that it seems to run in two What’s more, thinking about the ‘causal struc- other. The events had have to happened in a directions at once. ture’ of quantum mechanics — which events EDGAR BĄK BY ILLUSTRATION sequence, right? In everyday language, that sounds nonsen- precede or succeed others — might prove to be Not if Einstein were riding on one of the sical. But within the mathematical formalism more productive, and ultimately more intuitive, photons ricocheting through Philip Walther’s of quantum theory, ambiguity about causation than couching it in the typical mind-bending lab at the University of Vienna. Walther’s group emerges in a perfectly logical and consistent language that describes photons as being both has shown that it is impossible to say in which way. -
Can Quantum-Mechanical Description of Physical Reality Be Considered
Can quantum-mechanical description of physical reality be considered incomplete? Gilles Brassard Andr´eAllan M´ethot D´epartement d’informatique et de recherche op´erationnelle Universit´ede Montr´eal, C.P. 6128, Succ. Centre-Ville Montr´eal (QC), H3C 3J7 Canada {brassard, methotan}@iro.umontreal.ca 13 June 2005 Abstract In loving memory of Asher Peres, we discuss a most important and influential paper written in 1935 by his thesis supervisor and men- tor Nathan Rosen, together with Albert Einstein and Boris Podolsky. In that paper, the trio known as EPR questioned the completeness of quantum mechanics. The authors argued that the then-new theory should not be considered final because they believed it incapable of describing physical reality. The epic battle between Einstein and Bohr arXiv:quant-ph/0701001v1 30 Dec 2006 intensified following the latter’s response later the same year. Three decades elapsed before John S. Bell gave a devastating proof that the EPR argument was fatally flawed. The modest purpose of our paper is to give a critical analysis of the original EPR paper and point out its logical shortcomings in a way that could have been done 70 years ago, with no need to wait for Bell’s theorem. We also present an overview of Bohr’s response in the interest of showing how it failed to address the gist of the EPR argument. Dedicated to the memory of Asher Peres 1 Introduction In 1935, Albert Einstein, Boris Podolsky and Nathan Rosen published a paper that sent shock waves in the physics community [5], especially in Copenhagen. -
Required Readings
HPS/PHIL 687 Fall 2003 Historical Foundations of the Quantum Theory Required Readings: Topic: Readings: Planck and black-body radiation. Martin Klein. “Planck, Entropy, and Quanta, 1901- 1906.” The Natural Philosopher 1 (1963), 83-108. Einstein and the photo-electric effect. Martin Klein. “Einstein’s First Paper on Quanta.” The Natural Philosopher 2 (1963), 59-86. The Bohr model of the atom and spectral series. Max Jammer. “Regularities in Line Spectra”; “Bohr’s Theory of the Hydrogen Atom.” In The Conceptual Development of Quantum Mechanics. New York: McGraw-Hill, 1966, pp. 62-88. The Bohr-Sommerfeld “old” quantum theory; Max Jammer. “The Older Quantum Theory.” In Einstein on transition probabilities. The Conceptual Development of Quantum Mechanics. New York: McGraw-Hill, 1966, pp. 89-156. The Bohr-Kramers-Slater theory. Max Jammer. “The Transition to Quantum Mechanics.” In The Conceptual Development of Quantum Mechanics. New York: McGraw-Hill, 1966, pp. 157-195. Bose-Einstein statistics. Don Howard. “‘Nicht sein kann was nicht sein darf,’ or the Prehistory of EPR, 1909-1935: Einstein’s Early Worries about the Quantum Mechanics of Composite Systems.” In Sixty-Two Years of Uncertainty: Historical, Philosophical, and Physical Inquiries into the Foundations of Quantum Mechanics. Arthur Miller, ed. New York: Plenum, 1990, pp. 61-111. Schrödinger and wave mechanics; Heisenberg and Max Jammer. “The Formation of Quantum matrix mechanics. Mechanics.” In The Conceptual Development of Quantum Mechanics. New York: McGraw-Hill, 1966, pp. 196-280. De Broglie and the origins of pilot-wave theory. James T. Cushing. “Early Attempts at Causal Theories: A Stillborn Program.” In Quantum Mechanics: Historical Contingency and the Copenhagen Hegemony. -
The Dancing Wu Li Masters an Overview of the New Physics Gary Zukav
The Dancing Wu Li Masters An Overview of the New Physics Gary Zukav A BANTAM NEW AGE BOOK BANTAM BOOKS NEW YORK • TORONTO • LONDON • SYDNEY • AUCKLAND This book is dedicated to you, who are drawn to read it. Acknowledgments My gratitude to the following people cannot be adequately expressed. I discovered, in the course of writing this book, that physicists, from graduate students to Nobel Laureates, are a gracious group of people; accessible, helpful, and engaging. This discovery shattered my long-held stereo- type of the cold, "objective" scientific personality. For this, above all, I am grateful to the people listed here. Jack Sarfatti, Ph.D., Director of the Physics/Consciousness Research Group, is the catalyst without whom the following people and I would not have met. Al Chung-liang Huang, The T'ai Chi Master, provided the perfect metaphor of Wu Li, inspiration, and the beautiful calligraphy. David Finkelstein, Ph.D., Director of the School of Physics, Georgia Institute of Technology, was my first tutor. These men are the godfathers of this book. In addition to Sarfatti and Finkelstein, Brian Josephson, Professor of Physics, Cambridge University, and Max Jammer, Professor of Physics, Bar-Ilan University, Ramat- Gan, Israel, read and commented upon the entire manu- script. I am especially indebted to these men (but I do not wish to imply that any one of them, or any other of the individualistic and creative thinkers who helped me with this book, would approve of it, page for page, as it is written, nor that the responsibility for any errors or mis- interpretations belongs to anyone but me). -
Dirac's Quantum Electrodynamics
Dirac’s Quantum Electrodynamics Alexei Kojevnikov Dirac’s relationship with quantum electrodynamics was not an easy one. On the one hand, the theory owes to him much more than to anybody else, especially if one considers the years crucial for its emergence, the late 1920s and early 1930s, when practically all its main concepts, except for that of renormalization, were developed. After this period Dirac also wrote a number of important papers, specifically, on indefinite metrics and quantum dynamics with constraints. On the other hand, since the early 1930s he was an active critic of the theory and tried to develop alternative schemes. He did not become satisfied with the later method of re- normalization and regarded it as a mathematical trick rather than a fundamental solution, and died unreconciled with what, to a large extent, was his own brainchild.1 In the present paper I examine Dirac’s contribution to quantum electrodynamics during the years 1926 to 1933, paying attention to the importance and the specificity of his approach and also tracing the roots of his dissatisfaction with the theory, which goes back to the same time and which, as I see it, in many ways influenced his attitude to its subsequent development. Some of Dirac’s crucial accomplishments of that period, in particular his theory of the relativistic electron, have already been studied by historians in much detail. I will describe them more briefly, placing them in the context of Dirac’s other works and of the general situation in quantum theory and leaving more room for other, less studied works, such as the 1932 Dirac–Fock–Podolsky theory. -
On Aerts' Overlooked Solution to the EPR Paradox
On Aerts' overlooked solution to the EPR paradox Massimiliano Sassoli de Bianchi Center Leo Apostel for Interdisciplinary Studies, Brussels Free University, Brussels, Belgium∗ (Dated: May 9, 2018) The Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen (EPR) paradox was enunciated in 1935 and since then it has made a lot of ink flow. Being a subtle result, it has also been largely misun- derstood. Indeed, if questioned about its solution, many physicists will still affirm today that the paradox has been solved by the Bell-test experimental results, which have shown that entangled states are real. However, this remains a wrong view, as the validity of the EPR ex-absurdum reasoning is independent from the Bell-test experiments, and the possible structural shortcomings it evidenced cannot be elim- inated. These were correctly identified by the Belgian physicist Diederik Aerts, in the eighties of last century, and are about the inability of the quantum formalism to describe separate physical systems. The purpose of the present article is to bring Aerts' overlooked result to the attention again of the physics' community, explaining its content and implications. I. INTRODUCTION In 1935, Albert Einstein and his two collaborators, Boris Podolsky and Nathan Rosen (abbreviated as EPR), devised a very subtle thought experiment to highlight possible inade- quacies of the quantum mechanical formalism in the description of the physical reality, today arXiv:1805.02869v1 [quant-ph] 8 May 2018 known as the EPR paradox.1 The reason for the \paradox" qualifier is that the predictions of quantum theory, regarding the outcome of their proposed experiment, differed from those obtained by means of a reasoning using a very general reality criterion. -
0707.0401.Pdf
J.S. Bell’s Concept of Local Causality Travis Norsen Marlboro College, Marlboro, VT 05344∗ (Dated: March 3, 2011) John Stewart Bell’s famous 1964 theorem is widely regarded as one of the most important devel- opments in the foundations of physics. It has even been described as “the most profound discovery of science.” Yet even as we approach the 50th anniversary of Bell’s discovery, its meaning and impli- cations remain controversial. Many textbooks and commentators report that Bell’s theorem refutes the possibility (suggested especially by Einstein, Podolsky, and Rosen in 1935) of supplementing or- dinary quantum theory with additional (“hidden”) variables that might restore determinism and/or some notion of an observer-independent reality. On this view, Bell’s theorem supports the orthodox Copenhagen interpretation. Bell’s own view of his theorem, however, was quite different. He in- stead took the theorem as establishing an “essential conflict” between the now well-tested empirical predictions of quantum theory and relativistic local causality. The goal of the present paper is, in general, to make Bell’s own views more widely known and, in particular, to explain in detail Bell’s little-known mathematical formulation of the concept of relativistic local causality on which his theorem rests. We thus collect and organize many of Bell’s crucial statements on these topics, which are scattered throughout his writings, into a self-contained, pedagogical discussion including elaborations of the concepts “beable”, “completeness”, and “causality” which figure in the formula- tion. We also show how local causality (as formulated by Bell) can be used to derive an empirically testable Bell-type inequality, and how it can be used to recapitulate the EPR argument. -
Paul Dirac and Igor Tamm Correspondence; 1, 1928-1933
M PL I la 53 -270 Seo 1) Lv og MPI—Ph / 93 — 80 October, 1993 Paul Dirac and Igor Tamm Correspondence Part 1: 1928 — 1933 Commented by Alexei B. Kojevnikov 1 Max—Planck-Institut fur Physik Werner—Heisenberg-Institut Postfach 40 12 12, Fohringer Ring 6 D — 80805 Miinchen Germany Abstract These letters between two famous theoretical physicists and Nobel prize winners, Paul Dirac (1902 — 1984) of Britain and Igor Tamm (1895 — 1971) of the Soviet Union, contain important information on the development of the relativistic theory of electrons and positrons and on the beginnings of nuclear physics, as well as on the life of physicists in Europe and the Soviet Union during 1930s. Willininilalixiinilrnuiuilm eenzsema 1Alexander von Humboldt Fellow. On leave from the Institute for History of Science and Technology. Staropansky per. 1/5. Moscow, 103012. Russia. email addresses, permanent: [email protected] ; present: [email protected] OCR Output OCR Output1. Introduction to the Publication Brief Description This paper publishes the correspondence between two famous theoretical physicists of this century. Paul Adrien Maurice Dirac is known as one of the key creators of quantum mechanics and quantum electrodynamics, the author of Dirac equation and of The Principles of Quantum [Mechanics. To lay audiences Dirac is usually presented as the one who predicted anti-matter, or, more precisely, the first anti-particle — the positron. ln 1933 he shared the Nobel prize with Erwin Schrodinger "for the discovery of new productive forms of atomic theory”. Igor Evgen’evich Tamm worked on both particle theory and solid state theory, but received his Nobel prize in 1958 for the theoretical explanation of a non-quantum effect — Cherenkov radiation. -
Bell's Theorem
Bell's Theorem Bachelor thesis Mathematics and Physics Sven Etienne Supervisor: Klaas Landsman John Stewart Bell, 1982 [18]. Radboud University April 2019 Contents 1 Introduction 2 2 The question of completeness 4 2.1 Determinism . .4 2.2 Realism . .4 2.3 Hidden variables . .5 3 The Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen argument 6 3.1 Entanglement . .6 3.2 Locality . .7 4 Bell's theorem 10 4.1 The gist of Bell's theorem . 10 4.2 Many assumptions . 13 4.3 A formal statement of Bell's theorem . 16 4.4 The relation between Locality and SRT . 17 4.5 Bell's second theorem . 19 5 Are Locality and Independence equivalent? 22 5.1 The surmise . 22 5.2 A counterexample? . 22 6 Conclusion and discussion 26 A Spin 27 B Special relativity & causality 30 Bibliography 33 1 1 Introduction Quantum mechanics is strange. But it works, scientifically as well as in practice. This appears, for example, from the correct predictions regarding atomic spectra and the omnipresent transis- tor. Perhaps quantum mechanics is right, but just not complete and maybe the missing pieces of the theory would make everything fall into place and would make quantum mechanics a bit less strange. This, in a nutshell, is what led to the idea of `hidden variables'. A hidden variable is supposed to give us a more precise description of the physical state of particles than quantum mechanics currently does. In 1964, John Bell published an article in which he showed that certain types of hidden variables would lead to a contradiction. This result is known as Bell's theorem and this is the central topic of this bachelor's thesis.