Great Thought Experiments of Modern Physics Kent A. Peacock

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Great Thought Experiments of Modern Physics Kent A. Peacock Happiest Thoughts: Great Thought Experiments of Modern Physics Kent A. Peacock Department of Philosophy University of Lethbridge 1. Introduction: Of Chickens and Physicists A physicist can be defined as a person for whom a chicken is a uniform sphere of mass M. The point of this joke (which this author first heard from a physics professor) is that physicists shamelessly omit a lot of detail when they attempt to model and predict the behaviour of complex physical systems; indeed, one of the important skills that physics students must learn is knowing what to leave out when setting up a problem. This penchant for simplification does not necessarily mean that physicists are hopelessly out of touch with reality, however; for one can learn a surprising amount about how real things behave by thinking about apparently simplistic models. A typical textbook example of a physical model might be the block sliding down an inclined plane. The plane is at a definite angle with respect to the force of gravitation; the block (a rectangular chunk of indefinite stuff) has a given mass, and there will be a certain coefficient of friction between the block and the plane. The assignment might be to calculate the coefficient of friction that would be sufficient to prevent the block from sliding down the plane, as a function of the angle of the plane. Now, no block of material in the world is perfectly uniform, no planar piece of material is perfectly flat and smooth, no actual coefficient of friction is known to arbitrary accuracy, and gravity is never exactly uniform in direction and magnitude. And yet, there are many physical systems in the real world which are sufficiently like idealized models such as this, to a definable degree of approximation, that their observable behavior can be predicted using such models. Models are therefore useful not only because they help us to picture how basic physical principles work in a concrete situation, but also as frameworks on which to hang a practical calculation. Even textbook problems couched in terms of simple models such as the inclined plane amount to thought experiments of a sort. Usually, though, we reserve the honorific Gedankenexperimente for idealized scenarios that give us new insights into the meaning or limitations of important physical concepts, usually by testing their implications in extreme or highly simplified settings. Suppose, for example, that I confusedly believe that all objects fall at a rate that is a function of their mass. Galileo has an elegant thought experiment that shows that To appear in James Robert Brown, Yiftach Fehige, and Michael T. Stuart (eds), The Routledge Companion to Thought Experiments. Preprint posted to philsci archive, August 6, 2016. Comments, corrections, and objections are welcome; contact the author at [email protected]. Happiest Thoughts Page 1 of 34 my notion is a mistake: all objects in a uniform gravitational field must fall with the same acceleration (ignoring air resistance), on pain of outright contradiction.1 Galileo’s thought experiment, like most typical textbook models, can be translated into experiments that can actually be performed. But sometimes one can learn a lot even from thought experiments that cannot be done, at least in the simple terms in which they are first described. Mach invited us to rotate the entire universe around Newton’s bucket of water. No granting agency will fund that feat, and yet Mach’s insights contributed (in a complicated way) to the construction of a theory (general relativity) that has testable consequences (Janssen, 2014). In this chapter I describe several thought experiments that are important in modern physics, by which I mean the physical theory and practice that developed explosively from the late 19th century onwards. I’m going to mostly skip thought experiments that merely illustrate a key feature of physics2 in favour of those that contributed to the advancement of physics. Some thought experiments (such as Galileo’s) provide the basis for rigorous arguments with clear conclusions; others seem to work simply by drawing attention to an important question that otherwise might not have been apparent. Many of the most interesting thought experiments have ramifications far beyond what their creators intended. I’ll pay special attention to one particular thought experiment, defined by Einstein and his collaborators Boris Podolsky and Nathan Rosen (1935). The Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen (EPR) thought experiment dominates investigations of the foundations of quantum mechanics and plays a defining role in quantum information theory; I will suggest that it may even help us understand one of the central problems of cosmology. In the form in which Einstein and his young colleagues first described it, the EPR experiment was another idealization that probably cannot be performed. Despite this, it has evolved into practicable technology. While the thought experiments to be discussed here are key turning points in the history of modern physical theory, in several cases (including the EPR experiment) their full implications remain to be plumbed. It is an extraordinary fact that most of the definitive thought experiments in twentieth century physics were born from the fertile imagination of one person, Albert Einstein. This forces us to ponder the importance of individual creativity in the advancement of science. Music would be very different, and much diminished, had Beethoven died young. If Einstein had not lived, would others have made equivalent discoveries? It seems likely that many of his advances would have been arrived at by other competent physicists sooner or later—except perhaps for general relativity, for the very conception of the possibility of, and need for, such a theory was due to the foresight and imagination of Einstein alone. 2. Sorting Molecules: A Thought Experiment in Thermodynamics We’ll start with Maxwell’s Demon, a thought experiment that bridges 19th and 20th century physics. 1 For a nice analysis of Galileo’s thought experiment, see (Arthur, 1999). 2 Such as the double-slit experiment. For a lucid exposition, see (Feynman, Leighton, & Sands, 1965 Ch. 1). Happiest Thoughts Page 2 of 34 James Clerk Maxwell (1831–79) is best known for his eponymous equations for the electromagnetic field. He also made important contributions to statistical mechanics; in particular, he was the first to write the Maxwell-Boltzmann probability distribution which describes the statistics of particles in a Newtonian gas. Although Maxwell did not originate the concept of entropy (which was due to Rudolf Clausius, 1822–88) he was well aware of the Second Law of Thermodynamics, which, in the form relevant to our discussion here, states that no process can create a temperature difference without doing work. Maxwell fancifully imagined a box containing a gas at equilibrium, with its temperature and pressure uniform throughout apart from small, random fluctuations (Norton (2013a)). A barrier is inserted in the middle of the box, and there is a door in the barrier. A very small graduate student with unusually good eyesight is given the task of tracking the individual gas molecules and opening or closing the door so as to sort the faster molecules into (say) the left side, and the slower molecules into the right. Apparently, then, a temperature difference can be created between the two sides by means of a negligible expenditure of energy. The problem is to say precisely why such a violation of the Second Law of Thermodynamics would not be possible. There is a large literature on Maxwell’s demon, which we can’t hope to do justice to here. (For entry points, see (Maroney, 2009; Norton, 2013a).) It is well understood that there is a sense in which statistical mechanics would, in principle, allow us to beat the Second Law— albeit, in general, only for extremely brief periods of time. The easiest way to create a temperature difference between the two boxes is simply to leave the door open for a very, very long time. Eventually enough fast molecules will, by pure chance, wander into one side and enough slow molecules, again by pure chance, will wander into another, to create a measurable temperature difference between the gasses in the two boxes, at least until another fluctuation erases the gains made by the first. Now imagine that the hole has a spring-loaded door which could snap shut as soon as a specified difference in temperature Δ푇 was detected between the two partitions. The thermometer and door mechanism will have some definite energy requirement, but this can be made independent of Δ푇. If we want Δ푇 to be large enough that it implies an energy transfer greater than the energy requirements of the door mechanism, all we have to do is wait long enough and eventually a large enough fluctuation will probably (not certainly) come along—although the larger we want it to be, the longer we (again, probably) have to wait. (Let’s call this process “fishing for fluctuations”; like ordinary fishing the result can never be guaranteed.) As soon as the desired temperature difference is detected, the door snaps shut and we would have “trapped a fluctuation” in a way that apparently violates the Second Law. This example underscores the point made by Ludwig Boltzmann (and apparently well understood by Maxwell), which is that the Second Law is a statistical statement. Violations of the Law by pure chance are possible. In trying to exorcise Maxwell’s demonic assistant we are dealing with a question of what is overwhelmingly probable, not what is certain in a law-like way. The question is not whether energetically-free sorting against entropic gradients (such as temperature or concentration) could be done at all, but whether it can be done reliably, repeatedly, and in a time span shorter than the life of the observable universe.
Recommended publications
  • Kaluza-Klein Gravity, Concentrating on the General Rel- Ativity, Rather Than Particle Physics Side of the Subject
    Kaluza-Klein Gravity J. M. Overduin Department of Physics and Astronomy, University of Victoria, P.O. Box 3055, Victoria, British Columbia, Canada, V8W 3P6 and P. S. Wesson Department of Physics, University of Waterloo, Ontario, Canada N2L 3G1 and Gravity Probe-B, Hansen Physics Laboratories, Stanford University, Stanford, California, U.S.A. 94305 Abstract We review higher-dimensional unified theories from the general relativity, rather than the particle physics side. Three distinct approaches to the subject are identi- fied and contrasted: compactified, projective and noncompactified. We discuss the cosmological and astrophysical implications of extra dimensions, and conclude that none of the three approaches can be ruled out on observational grounds at the present time. arXiv:gr-qc/9805018v1 7 May 1998 Preprint submitted to Elsevier Preprint 3 February 2008 1 Introduction Kaluza’s [1] achievement was to show that five-dimensional general relativity contains both Einstein’s four-dimensional theory of gravity and Maxwell’s the- ory of electromagnetism. He however imposed a somewhat artificial restriction (the cylinder condition) on the coordinates, essentially barring the fifth one a priori from making a direct appearance in the laws of physics. Klein’s [2] con- tribution was to make this restriction less artificial by suggesting a plausible physical basis for it in compactification of the fifth dimension. This idea was enthusiastically received by unified-field theorists, and when the time came to include the strong and weak forces by extending Kaluza’s mechanism to higher dimensions, it was assumed that these too would be compact. This line of thinking has led through eleven-dimensional supergravity theories in the 1980s to the current favorite contenders for a possible “theory of everything,” ten-dimensional superstrings.
    [Show full text]
  • Conformal Symmetry in Field Theory and in Quantum Gravity
    universe Review Conformal Symmetry in Field Theory and in Quantum Gravity Lesław Rachwał Instituto de Física, Universidade de Brasília, Brasília DF 70910-900, Brazil; [email protected] Received: 29 August 2018; Accepted: 9 November 2018; Published: 15 November 2018 Abstract: Conformal symmetry always played an important role in field theory (both quantum and classical) and in gravity. We present construction of quantum conformal gravity and discuss its features regarding scattering amplitudes and quantum effective action. First, the long and complicated story of UV-divergences is recalled. With the development of UV-finite higher derivative (or non-local) gravitational theory, all problems with infinities and spacetime singularities might be completely solved. Moreover, the non-local quantum conformal theory reveals itself to be ghost-free, so the unitarity of the theory should be safe. After the construction of UV-finite theory, we focused on making it manifestly conformally invariant using the dilaton trick. We also argue that in this class of theories conformal anomaly can be taken to vanish by fine-tuning the couplings. As applications of this theory, the constraints of the conformal symmetry on the form of the effective action and on the scattering amplitudes are shown. We also remark about the preservation of the unitarity bound for scattering. Finally, the old model of conformal supergravity by Fradkin and Tseytlin is briefly presented. Keywords: quantum gravity; conformal gravity; quantum field theory; non-local gravity; super- renormalizable gravity; UV-finite gravity; conformal anomaly; scattering amplitudes; conformal symmetry; conformal supergravity 1. Introduction From the beginning of research on theories enjoying invariance under local spacetime-dependent transformations, conformal symmetry played a pivotal role—first introduced by Weyl related changes of meters to measure distances (and also due to relativity changes of periods of clocks to measure time intervals).
    [Show full text]
  • Gravity, Inertia, and Quantum Vacuum Zero Point Fields
    Foundations of Physics, Vol.31,No. 5, 2001 Gravity, Inertia, and Quantum Vacuum Zero Point Fields James F. Woodward1 Received July 27, 2000 Over the past several years Haisch, Rueda, and others have made the claim that the origin of inertial reaction forces can be explained as the interaction of electri- cally charged elementary particles with the vacuum electromagnetic zero-point field expected on the basis of quantum field theory. After pointing out that this claim, in light of the fact that the inertial masses of the hadrons reside in the electrically chargeless, photon-like gluons that bind their constituent quarks, is untenable, the question of the role of quantum zero-point fields generally in the origin of inertia is explored. It is shown that, although non-gravitational zero-point fields might be the cause of the gravitational properties of normal matter, the action of non-gravitational zero-point fields cannot be the cause of inertial reac- tion forces. The gravitational origin of inertial reaction forces is then briefly revisited. Recent claims critical of the gravitational origin of inertial reaction forces by Haisch and his collaborators are then shown to be without merit. 1. INTRODUCTION Several years ago Haisch, Rueda, and Puthoff (1) (hereafter, HRP) pub- lished a lengthy paper in which they claimed that a substantial part, indeed perhaps all of normal inertial reaction forces could be understood as the action of the electromagnetic zero-point field (EZPF), expected on the basis of quantum field theory, on electric charges of normal matter. In several subsequent papers Haisch and Rueda particularly have pressed this claim, making various modifications to the fundamental argument to try to deflect several criticisms.
    [Show full text]
  • Loop Quantum Cosmology, Modified Gravity and Extra Dimensions
    universe Review Loop Quantum Cosmology, Modified Gravity and Extra Dimensions Xiangdong Zhang Department of Physics, South China University of Technology, Guangzhou 510641, China; [email protected] Academic Editor: Jaume Haro Received: 24 May 2016; Accepted: 2 August 2016; Published: 10 August 2016 Abstract: Loop quantum cosmology (LQC) is a framework of quantum cosmology based on the quantization of symmetry reduced models following the quantization techniques of loop quantum gravity (LQG). This paper is devoted to reviewing LQC as well as its various extensions including modified gravity and higher dimensions. For simplicity considerations, we mainly focus on the effective theory, which captures main quantum corrections at the cosmological level. We set up the basic structure of Brans–Dicke (BD) and higher dimensional LQC. The effective dynamical equations of these theories are also obtained, which lay a foundation for the future phenomenological investigations to probe possible quantum gravity effects in cosmology. Some outlooks and future extensions are also discussed. Keywords: loop quantum cosmology; singularity resolution; effective equation 1. Introduction Loop quantum gravity (LQG) is a quantum gravity scheme that tries to quantize general relativity (GR) with the nonperturbative techniques consistently [1–4]. Many issues of LQG have been carried out in the past thirty years. In particular, among these issues, loop quantum cosmology (LQC), which is the cosmological sector of LQG has received increasing interest and has become one of the most thriving and fruitful directions of LQG [5–9]. It is well known that GR suffers singularity problems and this, in turn, implies that our universe also has an infinitely dense singularity point that is highly unphysical.
    [Show full text]
  • Study of Quantum Spin Correlations of Relativistic Electron Pairs
    Study of quantum spin correlations of relativistic electron pairs Project status Nov. 2015 Jacek Ciborowski Marta Włodarczyk, Michał Drągowski, Artem Poliszczuk (UW) Joachim Enders, Yuliya Fritsche (TU Darmstadt) Warszawa 20.XI.2015 Quantum spin correlations In this exp: e1,e2 – electrons under study a, b - directions of spin projections (+- ½) 4 combinations for e1 and e2: ++, --, +-, -+ Probabilities: P++ , P+- , P-+ , P- - (ΣP=1) Correlation function : C = P++ + P-- - P-+ - P-+ Historical perspective • Einstein Podolsky Rosen (EPR) paradox (1935): QM is not a complete local realistic theory • Bohm & Aharonov formulation involving spin correlations (1957) • Bell inequalities (1964) a local realistic theory must obey a class of inequalities • practical approach to Bell’s inequalities: counting aacoincidences to measure correlations The EPR paradox Boris Podolsky Nathan Rosen Albert Einstein (1896-1966) (1909-1995) (1979-1955) A. Afriat and F. Selleri, The Einstein, Podolsky and Rosen Paradox (Plenum Press, New York and London, 1999) Bohm’s version with the spin Two spin-1/2 fermions in a singlet state: E.g. if spin projection of 1 on Z axis is measured 1/2 spin projection of 2 must be -1/2 All projections should be elements of reality (QM predicts that only S2 and David Bohm (1917-1992) Sz can be determined) Hidden variables? ”Quantum Theory” (1951) Phys. Rev. 85(1952)166,180 The Bell inequalities J.S.Bell: Impossible to reconcile the concept of hidden variables with statistical predictions of QM If local realism quantum correlations
    [Show full text]
  • Gravitational Interaction to One Loop in Effective Quantum Gravity A
    IT9700281 LABORATORI NAZIONALI Dl FRASCATI SIS - Pubblicazioni LNF-96/0S8 (P) ITHf 00 Z%i 31 ottobre 1996 gr-qc/9611018 Gravitational Interaction to one Loop in Effective Quantum Gravity A. Akhundov" S. Bellucci6 A. Shiekhcl "Universitat-Gesamthochschule Siegen, D-57076 Siegen, Germany, and Institute of Physics, Azerbaijan Academy of Sciences, pr. Azizbekova 33, AZ-370143 Baku, Azerbaijan 6INFN-Laboratori Nazionali di Frascati, P.O. Box 13, 00044 Frascati, Italy ^International Centre for Theoretical Physics, Strada Costiera 11, P.O. Box 586, 34014 Trieste, Italy Abstract We carry out the first step of a program conceived, in order to build a realistic model, having the particle spectrum of the standard model and renormalized masses, interaction terms and couplings, etc. which include the class of quantum gravity corrections, obtained by handling gravity as an effective theory. This provides an adequate picture at low energies, i.e. much less than the scale of strong gravity (the Planck mass). Hence our results are valid, irrespectively of any proposal for the full quantum gravity as a fundamental theory. We consider only non-analytic contributions to the one-loop scattering matrix elements, which provide the dominant quantum effect at long distance. These contributions are finite and independent from the finite value of the renormalization counter terms of the effective lagrangian. We calculate the interaction of two heavy scalar particles, i.e. close to rest, due to the effective quantum gravity to the one loop order and compare with similar results in the literature. PACS.: 04.60.+n Submitted to Physics Letters B 1 E-mail addresses: [email protected], bellucciQlnf.infn.it, [email protected] — 2 1 Introduction A longstanding puzzle in quantum physics is how to marry the description of gravity with the field theory of elementary particles.
    [Show full text]
  • Quantum Eraser
    Quantum Eraser March 18, 2015 It was in 1935 that Albert Einstein, with his collaborators Boris Podolsky and Nathan Rosen, exploiting the bizarre property of quantum entanglement (not yet known under that name which was coined in Schrödinger (1935)), noted that QM demands that systems maintain a variety of ‘correlational properties’ amongst their parts no matter how far the parts might be sepa- rated from each other (see 1935, the source of what has become known as the EPR paradox). In itself there appears to be nothing strange in this; such cor- relational properties are common in classical physics no less than in ordinary experience. Consider two qualitatively identical billiard balls approaching each other with equal but opposite velocities. The total momentum is zero. After they collide and rebound, measurement of the velocity of one ball will naturally reveal the velocity of the other. But the EPR argument coupled this observation with the orthodox Copen- hagen interpretation of QM, which states that until a measurement of a par- ticular property is made on a system, that system cannot, in general, be said to possess any definite value of that property. It is easy to see that if dis- tant correlations are preserved through measurement processes that ‘bring into being’ the measured values there is a prima facie conflict between the Copenhagen interpretation and the relativistic stricture that no information can be transmitted faster than the speed of light. Suppose, for example, we have a system with some property which is anti-correlated (in real cases, this property could be spin).
    [Show full text]
  • Required Readings
    HPS/PHIL 93872 Spring 2006 Historical Foundations of the Quantum Theory Don Howard, Instructor Required Readings: Topic: Readings: Planck and black-body radiation. Martin Klein. “Planck, Entropy, and Quanta, 19011906.” The Natural Philosopher 1 (1963), 83-108. Martin Klein. “Einstein’s First Paper on Quanta.” The Natural Einstein and the photo-electric effect. Philosopher 2 (1963), 59-86. Max Jammer. “Regularities in Line Spectra”; “Bohr’s Theory The Bohr model of the atom and spectral of the Hydrogen Atom.” In The Conceptual Development of series. Quantum Mechanics. New York: McGraw-Hill, 1966, pp. 62- 88. The Bohr-Sommerfeld “old” quantum Max Jammer. “The Older Quantum Theory.” In The Conceptual theory; Einstein on transition Development of Quantum Mechanics. New York: McGraw-Hill, probabilities. 1966, pp. 89-156. The Bohr-Kramers-Slater theory. Max Jammer. “The Transition to Quantum Mechanics.” In The Conceptual Development of Quantum Mechanics. New York: McGraw-Hill, 1966, pp. 157-195. Bose-Einstein statistics. Don Howard. “‘Nicht sein kann was nicht sein darf,’ or the Prehistory of EPR, 1909-1935: Einstein’s Early Worries about the Quantum Mechanics of Composite Systems.” In Sixty-Two Years of Uncertainty: Historical, Philosophical, and Physical Inquiries into the Foundations of Quantum Mechanics. Arthur Miller, ed. New York: Plenum, 1990, pp. 61-111. Max Jammer. “The Formation of Quantum Mechanics.” In The Schrödinger and wave mechanics; Conceptual Development of Quantum Mechanics. New York: Heisenberg and matrix mechanics. McGraw-Hill, 1966, pp. 196-280. James T. Cushing. “Early Attempts at Causal Theories: A De Broglie and the origins of pilot-wave Stillborn Program.” In Quantum Mechanics: Historical theory.
    [Show full text]
  • Vacuum Energy
    Vacuum Energy Mark D. Roberts, 117 Queen’s Road, Wimbledon, London SW19 8NS, Email:[email protected] http://cosmology.mth.uct.ac.za/ roberts ∼ February 1, 2008 Eprint: hep-th/0012062 Comments: A comprehensive review of Vacuum Energy, which is an extended version of a poster presented at L¨uderitz (2000). This is not a review of the cosmolog- ical constant per se, but rather vacuum energy in general, my approach to the cosmological constant is not standard. Lots of very small changes and several additions for the second and third versions: constructive feedback still welcome, but the next version will be sometime in coming due to my sporadiac internet access. First Version 153 pages, 368 references. Second Version 161 pages, 399 references. arXiv:hep-th/0012062v3 22 Jul 2001 Third Version 167 pages, 412 references. The 1999 PACS Physics and Astronomy Classification Scheme: http://publish.aps.org/eprint/gateway/pacslist 11.10.+x, 04.62.+v, 98.80.-k, 03.70.+k; The 2000 Mathematical Classification Scheme: http://www.ams.org/msc 81T20, 83E99, 81Q99, 83F05. 3 KEYPHRASES: Vacuum Energy, Inertial Mass, Principle of Equivalence. 1 Abstract There appears to be three, perhaps related, ways of approaching the nature of vacuum energy. The first is to say that it is just the lowest energy state of a given, usually quantum, system. The second is to equate vacuum energy with the Casimir energy. The third is to note that an energy difference from a complete vacuum might have some long range effect, typically this energy difference is interpreted as the cosmological constant.
    [Show full text]
  • A WORLD WITHOUT CAUSE and EFFECT Logic-Defying Experiments Into Quantum Causality Scramble the Notion of Time Itself
    A WORLD WITHOUT CAUSE AND EFFECT Logic-defying experiments into quantum causality scramble the notion of time itself. BY PHILIP BALL lbert Einstein is heading out for his This finding1 in 2015 made the quantum the constraints of a predefined causal structure daily stroll and has to pass through world seem even stranger than scientists had might solve some problems faster than con- Atwo doorways. First he walks through thought. Walther’s experiments mash up cau- ventional quantum computers,” says quantum the green door, and then through the red one. sality: the idea that one thing leads to another. theorist Giulio Chiribella of the University of Or wait — did he go through the red first and It is as if the physicists have scrambled the con- Hong Kong. then the green? It must have been one or the cept of time itself, so that it seems to run in two What’s more, thinking about the ‘causal struc- other. The events had have to happened in a directions at once. ture’ of quantum mechanics — which events EDGAR BĄK BY ILLUSTRATION sequence, right? In everyday language, that sounds nonsen- precede or succeed others — might prove to be Not if Einstein were riding on one of the sical. But within the mathematical formalism more productive, and ultimately more intuitive, photons ricocheting through Philip Walther’s of quantum theory, ambiguity about causation than couching it in the typical mind-bending lab at the University of Vienna. Walther’s group emerges in a perfectly logical and consistent language that describes photons as being both has shown that it is impossible to say in which way.
    [Show full text]
  • An Introduction to Loop Quantum Gravity with Application to Cosmology
    DEPARTMENT OF PHYSICS IMPERIAL COLLEGE LONDON MSC DISSERTATION An Introduction to Loop Quantum Gravity with Application to Cosmology Author: Supervisor: Wan Mohamad Husni Wan Mokhtar Prof. Jo~ao Magueijo September 2014 Submitted in partial fulfilment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Science of Imperial College London Abstract The development of a quantum theory of gravity has been ongoing in the theoretical physics community for about 80 years, yet it remains unsolved. In this dissertation, we review the loop quantum gravity approach and its application to cosmology, better known as loop quantum cosmology. In particular, we present the background formalism of the full theory together with its main result, namely the discreteness of space on the Planck scale. For its application to cosmology, we focus on the homogeneous isotropic universe with free massless scalar field. We present the kinematical structure and the features it shares with the full theory. Also, we review the way in which classical Big Bang singularity is avoided in this model. Specifically, the spectrum of the operator corresponding to the classical inverse scale factor is bounded from above, the quantum evolution is governed by a difference rather than a differential equation and the Big Bang is replaced by a Big Bounce. i Acknowledgement In the name of Allah, the Most Gracious, the Most Merciful. All praise be to Allah for giving me the opportunity to pursue my study of the fundamentals of nature. In particular, I am very grateful for the opportunity to explore loop quantum gravity and its application to cosmology for my MSc dissertation.
    [Show full text]
  • Can Quantum-Mechanical Description of Physical Reality Be Considered
    Can quantum-mechanical description of physical reality be considered incomplete? Gilles Brassard Andr´eAllan M´ethot D´epartement d’informatique et de recherche op´erationnelle Universit´ede Montr´eal, C.P. 6128, Succ. Centre-Ville Montr´eal (QC), H3C 3J7 Canada {brassard, methotan}@iro.umontreal.ca 13 June 2005 Abstract In loving memory of Asher Peres, we discuss a most important and influential paper written in 1935 by his thesis supervisor and men- tor Nathan Rosen, together with Albert Einstein and Boris Podolsky. In that paper, the trio known as EPR questioned the completeness of quantum mechanics. The authors argued that the then-new theory should not be considered final because they believed it incapable of describing physical reality. The epic battle between Einstein and Bohr arXiv:quant-ph/0701001v1 30 Dec 2006 intensified following the latter’s response later the same year. Three decades elapsed before John S. Bell gave a devastating proof that the EPR argument was fatally flawed. The modest purpose of our paper is to give a critical analysis of the original EPR paper and point out its logical shortcomings in a way that could have been done 70 years ago, with no need to wait for Bell’s theorem. We also present an overview of Bohr’s response in the interest of showing how it failed to address the gist of the EPR argument. Dedicated to the memory of Asher Peres 1 Introduction In 1935, Albert Einstein, Boris Podolsky and Nathan Rosen published a paper that sent shock waves in the physics community [5], especially in Copenhagen.
    [Show full text]