The Incongruity of Incongruity Theories of Humor
Total Page:16
File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb
THE INCONGRUITY OF INCONGRUITY THEORIES OF HUMOR Tomáš Kulka ABSTRACT: The article critically reviews the Incongruity Theory of Humor reaching the conclusion that it has to be essentially restructured. Leaving aside the question of scope, it is shown that the theory is inadequate even for those cases for which it is thought to be especially well suited – that it cannot account either for the pleasurable effect of jokes or for aesthetic pleasure. I argue that it is the resolution of the incongruity rather than its mere apprehension, which is that source of the amusement or aesthetic delight. Once the theory is thus restructured, the Superiority Theory of Humor and the Relief Theory can be seen as supplementary to it. KEYWORDS: Humor, Resolution of Incongruity Socrates: And when we laugh ... do we feel pain or pleasure? Protarchus: Clearly we feel pleasure. (Plato, Philebus, 50) In the literature on humor and laughter it is customary to distinguish between three classical theories: The Superiority Theory (Plato, Aristotle, Hobbes), the Relief Theory (Spencer, Freud) and the Incongruity Theory (Cicero, Kant, Schopenhauer, Kierkegaard).1 The three theories are usually seen as rivals, competing for the most plausible answers to ques- tions like: „Why do we laugh?“, „What is the nature of humor?“, or „What does the comical consist of?“ The Superiority Theory says that the comical is perceived as inferior and our laughter is an expression of the sudden realization of our superiority. The Relief Theory emphasizes the liberating effect of humor. Laughter is seen as a discharge of surplus energy which alleviates psy- chic tension. The Incongruity Theory maintains that the object of amuse- 1 See, for example, Monroe (1967). See also Morreall (1987a). This anthology contains a selection of texts from the classical representatives of the three theories, as well as ar- ticles of contemporary theoreticians. All the references and quotations refer to this ant- hology. ORGANON F 14 (2007), No. 3, 320 − 333 Copyright © Filozofický ústav SAV, Bratislava The Incongruity of Incongruity Theories of Humor ment consists in some kind of incongruity and that laughter is an expression of our enjoyment of the incongruous. The Incongruity Theory is the most popular of the three at present. This is mainly because its rivals are considered discredited. Hutcheson, in his response to Hobbes, has already pointed out that feelings of supe- riority are neither necessary nor sufficient for amusement or laughter.2 As to the Relief Theory, it has been noted that it „simply seems false that every time we laugh we are working off excess energy“ (Morreall 1987a, 6). More generally, the two rival theories are seen „inadequate in captu- ring the essence of humor, because they focus on the incidental benefits to the amused person rather than on what it is about amusing things that makes them amusing“ (Morreall 1987a, 6). The Incongruity Theory, especially in its contemporary versions, fo- cuses on the formal object of amusement. The theory is considered to be particularly well suited to account for the humorous laughter and amu- sement occasioned by jokes, though it has often been extended to other objects of amusement (comedy, satire, parody, mimic, clowning, tricke- ry, caricature, slapstick, absent-mindedness, folly, etc.). Some authors also claim that the Incongruity Theory reveals the connection between the humorous and the aesthetic, that the enjoyment of incongruities forms the basis of aesthetic enjoyment. I shall not be concerned here with the question whether the concept of incongruity adequately covers all cases of laughter, humorous amusement, or aesthetic pleasure, since I shall argue that the Incongruity Theory is inadequate even for those cases for which it is thought to be especially well suited. I will show that the Incongruity Theory cannot account either for the pleasurable effect of jokes or for aesthetic pleasure. I argue that the Incongruity Theory, as it stands, stands on its head; that it has to be essentially restructured if it is to account for what it purports to account for. I also show that once the Incongruity Theory is restructured, the Superiority Theory and the Relief Theory can be seen as supplementary to it. The first traces of the Incongruity Theory can be found in Cicero and Kant, but it was not until Schopenhauer that the theory was fully arti- 2 Hutcheson, F.: Reflections upon Laughter. Glasgow 1750. See esp. Morreall (1987a, 26 – 31). − 321 − Tomáš Kulka culated. Indeed, Schopenhauer is the locus classicus; the following passa- ge is often invoked by contemporary incongruists: The cause of Laughter in every case is simply the sudden perception of the incongruity between a concept and the real objects which have been thought through it in some relation, and laughter itself is just the expression of this incongruity. It often occurs in this way: two or more real objects are thought through one concept and the identity of the concept is transferred to the ob- jects; it then becomes strikingly apparent from the entire difference of the objects in other respects, that the concept was only applicable to them from a one-sided point of view.3 Contemporary followers of the Incongruity Theory consider this account to be in need of refinement and revision, but the central idea, that the object of amusement and laughter is the incongruous, has been accepted by all.4 Let us see how it is supposed to work. Here are two jokes analyzed by Schopenhauer: When someone had declared that he was fond of walking alone, an Austrian said to him: „You like walking alone; so do I: Therefore we can go together.“ Schopenhauer explains: „He starts from the conception, ‚A pleasure which two love they can enjoy in common,‘ and subsumes under it the very case which excludes community.“ The soldiers in the guardroom who allowed a prisoner who was brought in to join in their game of cards, then quarreled with him for cheating, and turned him out. Schopenhauer explains: „They let themselves be led by the general con- ception, ‚Bad companions are turned out,‘ and forgot that he is also a prisoner.“5 This seems basically right. Yet there is a problem. From Plato to the present day, all theoreticians of humor have stressed that amusement and laughter are pleasurable. The pleasurable effect of the comical could easily be accounted for by the Relief from Restraint Theory or by the Superiority Theory. But what 3 Schopenhauer, A.: The World as Will and Idea, quoted from Morreall (1987a, 52). 4 See, for example, Clark (1987), Morreall (1987b), Scruton (1987), and Martin (1987). 5 Morreall (1987a, 58). Basically the same analysis of examples of amusing stories is giv- en by Clark (1987, 147 – 148). − 322 − The Incongruity of Incongruity Theories of Humor about the Incongruity Theory? Is it reasonable to assume that we find pleasure in incongruities? The Oxford English Dictionary assigns to „incongruity“ the following meanings: (i) Disagreement in character or qualities; want of accordance or harmony; discrepancy; inconsistency. (ii) Want of accordance with what is reasonable or fitting; unsui- tableness, inappropriateness, absurdity. (iii) Want of harmony of parts or elements; want of self-consis- tency. The range of these meanings certainly covers the sense in which Scho- penhauer and his followers use the concept. Yet when we reflect upon them they do not strike us as conveying or invoking pleasurable conno- tations. In fact, our associations seem to go in the opposite direction. We tend to associate „discrepancy“, „inconsistency“, „inappropriateness“, „want of harmony“, etc., with something disagreeable, displeasing or disturbing, rather than with something agreeable or pleasing. This uneasy feeling is only strengthened when we consider explana- tions offered by other classical proponents of the Incongruity Theory. In Chapter 63, Book II, On the Orator, Cicero writes: The most common kind of joke is that in which we expect one thing and ano- ther is said: here our own disappointed expectation makes us laugh. (Morreall 1987a, 18) But why should disappointed expectations make us laugh? Normally, when our expectations are disappointed we just feel disappointment, which is hardly a pleasurable feeling. With Kant‘s explanation of laugh- ter we get the same problem. In The Critique of Judgement he writes: Laughter is an affection arising from the sudden transformation of a strained expectation into nothing (Morreall 1987a, 47). Shouldn‘t we feel frustrated rather than amused? The same problem afflicts contemporary versions of the Incongruity Theory. Thus, for example, John Morreall says that „humor always in- volves the enjoyment of a perceived or imagined incongruity“ (Morreall 1987b, 136), and Michael Clark writes: „I have insisted that a reason for the enjoyment in cases of amusement must be the apparent incongruity of the object“ (Clark 1987, 154). − 323 − Tomáš Kulka It is not difficult to see why the incongruity theorists were led to believe that incongruities are enjoyable. Since we enjoy jokes, and since jokes involve incongruities, they (erroneously) concluded that „humor always involves the enjoyment of a perceived or imagined incongruity“, that ‘the incongruous‘ as such is the reason, or at least „a reason for the enjoyment.“ Schopenhauer himself (unlike some of his followers) did not consider this conclusion quite so self-evident, and he offered an elaborate argument in its support. Let me quote in full: In every suddenly appearing conflict between what is perceived and what is thought, what is perceived is always unquestionably right; for it is not subject to error at all, requires no confirmation from without, but answers for itself. Its conflict with what is thought springs ultimately from the fact that the latter, with its abstract conceptions, cannot get down to the infinite multifa- riousness and fine shades of difference of the concrete.