Functions and Inverses

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Functions and Inverses Functions and Inverses CS 2800: Discrete Structures, Spring 2015 Sid Chaudhuri Recap: Relations and Functions ● A relation between sets A !the domain) and B !the codomain" is a set of ordered pairs (a, b) such that a ∈ A, b ∈ B !i.e. it is a subset o# A × B" Cartesian product – The relation maps each a to the corresponding b ● Neither all possible a%s, nor all possible b%s, need be covered – Can be one-one, one&'an(, man(&one, man(&man( Alice CS 2800 Bob A Carol CS 2110 B David CS 3110 Recap: Relations and Functions ● ) function is a relation that maps each element of A to a single element of B – Can be one-one or man(&one – )ll elements o# A must be covered, though not necessaril( all elements o# B – Subset o# B covered b( the #unction is its range/image Alice Balch Bob A Carol Jameson B David Mews Recap: Relations and Functions ● Instead of writing the #unction f as a set of pairs, e usually speci#y its domain and codomain as: f : A → B * and the mapping via a rule such as: f (Heads) = 0.5, f (Tails) = 0.5 or f : x ↦ x2 +he function f maps x to x2 Recap: Relations and Functions ● Instead of writing the #unction f as a set of pairs, e usually speci#y its domain and codomain as: f : A → B * and the mapping via a rule such as: f (Heads) = 0.5, f (Tails) = 0.5 2 or f : x ↦ x f(x) ● Note: the function is f, not f(x), – f(x) is the value assigned b( f the #unction f to input x x Recap: Injectivity ● ) function is injective (one-to-one) if every element in the domain has a unique i'age in the codomain – +hat is, f(x) = f(y) implies x = y Albany NY New York A MA Sacramento B CA Boston ... ... Recap: Surjectivity ● ) function if surjective (onto) if every element of the codomain has a prei'age in the domain – +hat is, for every b ∈ B there is some a ∈ A such that f(a) = b – +hat is, the codomain is equal to the range/image August September October November Autumn December January Winter A February B March Spring April Summer May June July Recap: Surjectivity ● ) function if surjective (onto) if every element of the codomain has a prei'age in the domain – +hat is, for every b ∈ B there is some a ∈ A such that f(a) = b – +hat is, the codomain is equal to the range/image August September (Ithaca etc) October November Almost Winter December January Winter A February B March Still Winter April Road Construction May June July Recap: 0ijectivity ● ) function is bijective if it is both surjective and injective January 1 February 2 March 3 April 4 May 5 June 6 A July 7 B August 8 September 9 October 10 November 11 December 12 Composition o# Functions ● +he composition o# t o #unctions f : B → C g : A → B is the function f ○ g : A → C de1ned as f ○ g : x ↦ f ( g (x) ) g x 1 f Even y 2 Odd z 3 A B C Composition o# Functions ● +he composition o# t o #unctions f : B → C g ○ f is not possible g : A → B unless A = C ! is the function f ○ g : A → C de1ned as f ○ g : x ↦ f ( g (x) ) x f ○ g Even y Odd z A C Factoid o# the Day 21 Composition is associative (f ○ g) ○ h = f ○ (g ○ h) (two functions are equal if for every input, they give the same output) Prove it! h x 1 g Even f True y 2 False z 3 Odd A B C D 3e#t Inverse o# a Function ● g : B → A is a left inverse of f : A → B i# g ( f (a) ) = a for all a ∈ A – If you follo the function from the domain to the codomain, the left inverse tells you ho to go back to here you started f a f(a) A B 3e#t Inverse o# a Function ● g : B → A is a left inverse of f : A → B i# g ( f (a) ) = a for all a ∈ A – If you follo the function from the domain to the codomain, the left inverse tells you ho to go back to here you started f a f(a) A 5 B 3e#t Inverse o# a Function ● g : B → A is a left inverse of f : A → B i# g ( f (a) ) = a for all a ∈ A – If you follo the function from the domain to the codomain, the left inverse tells you ho to go back to here you started f a f(a) g A B Right Inverse o# a Function ● h : B → A is a right inverse of f : A → B i# f ( h (b) ) = b for all b ∈ B – If you're trying to get to a destination in the codomain, the right inverse tells you a possible place to start b A B Right Inverse o# a Function ● h : B → A is a right inverse of f : A → B i# f ( h (b) ) = b for all b ∈ B – If you're trying to get to a destination in the codomain, the right inverse tells you a possible place to start f 5 b A B Right Inverse o# a Function ● h : B → A is a right inverse of f : A → B i# f ( h (b) ) = b for all b ∈ B – If you're trying to get to a destination in the codomain, the right inverse tells you a possible place to start h(b) b h A B Right Inverse o# a Function ● h : B → A is a right inverse of f : A → B i# f ( h (b) ) = b for all b ∈ B – If you're trying to get to a destination in the codomain, the right inverse tells you a possible place to start f h(b) b h A B 6ote the subtle difference, ● +he left inverse tells (ou ho to exactly retrace (our steps, if (ou 'anaged to get to a destination – “Some places might be unreachable, but I can al a(s put (ou on the return 8ight” ● +he right inverse tells (ou here (ou might have come from, #or any possible destination – :)ll places are reachable, but I can%t put (ou on the return 8ight because I don%t 4no e;actl( here (ou came #ro'9 Factoid o# the Day 22 3eft and right inverses need not e;ist, and need not be uni.ue Can you come up with some examples? 3e#t inverse ⇔ Injective ● Theorem: ) function is injective !one-to-one) i7 it has a left inverse ● Proof (⇐): )ssume f : A → B has left inverse g – If f(x) = f(y) ... – … then g(f(x)) = g(f(y)) !any fn maps equals to equals" – … i.e. x = y !since g is a left inverse" – <ence f is injective 3e#t inverse ⇔ Injective ● Theorem: ) function is injective !one-to-one) i7 it has a left inverse ● Proof (⇒): )ssume f : A → B is injective – =ick any a0 in A, and defineg as a if f(a) = b g(b) = a0 otherwise – +his is a well-defined function: since f is injective, there can be at most a single a such that f(a) = b – )lso, if f(a) = b then g(f(a)) = a, by construction – <ence g is a left inverse of f Right inverse ⇔ Surjective ● Theorem: ) function is surjective !onto) i7 it has a right inverse ● Proof (⇐): )ssume f : A → B has right inverse h – For any b ∈ B, we can apply h to it to get h(b) – Since h is a right inverse, f(h(b)) = b – +herefore every element of B has a preimage in A – <ence f is sur-ective Right inverse ⇔ Surjective ● Theorem: ) function is surjective !onto) i7 it has a right inverse ● Proof (⇒): )ssume f : A → B is surjective – For every b ∈ B, there is a non-empty set Ab ⊆ A such that for every a ∈ Ab, f(a) = b !since f is surjective) – Define h : b ↦ an arbitrary element of Ab – )gain, this is a well-defined function since Ab is non‑empty (and assuming the “axiom of choice”," – )lso, f(h(b)) = b for all b ∈ B, by construction – <ence h is a right inverse of f Recap: 3e#t and Right Inverses ● ) function is injective !one-to-one) i7 it has a left inverse ● ) function is surjective (onto) i7 it has a right inverse Factoid #or the Day 2? If a function has both a left inverse and a right inverse, then the t o inverses are identical, and this com'on inverse is unique (Prove!) +his is called the two-sided inverse, or usually just the inverse f –1 of the function f http:// .cs.cornell.edu/courses/cs2800/2015sp/handouts/-onpa4@function_notes.pdf 0ijection and two-sided inverse ● ) function f is bijective i7 it has a t o-sided inverse ● Proof (⇒): If it is bijective, it has a left inverse !since injective) and a right inverse (since surjective), which must be one and the sa'e by the previous factoid ● Proof (⇐): If it has a t o-sided inverse, it is both injective (since there is a left inverse) and surjective (since there is a right inverse). <ence it is bijective..
Recommended publications
  • A Proof of Cantor's Theorem
    Cantor’s Theorem Joe Roussos 1 Preliminary ideas Two sets have the same number of elements (are equinumerous, or have the same cardinality) iff there is a bijection between the two sets. Mappings: A mapping, or function, is a rule that associates elements of one set with elements of another set. We write this f : X ! Y , f is called the function/mapping, the set X is called the domain, and Y is called the codomain. We specify what the rule is by writing f(x) = y or f : x 7! y. e.g. X = f1; 2; 3g;Y = f2; 4; 6g, the map f(x) = 2x associates each element x 2 X with the element in Y that is double it. A bijection is a mapping that is injective and surjective.1 • Injective (one-to-one): A function is injective if it takes each element of the do- main onto at most one element of the codomain. It never maps more than one element in the domain onto the same element in the codomain. Formally, if f is a function between set X and set Y , then f is injective iff 8a; b 2 X; f(a) = f(b) ! a = b • Surjective (onto): A function is surjective if it maps something onto every element of the codomain. It can map more than one thing onto the same element in the codomain, but it needs to hit everything in the codomain. Formally, if f is a function between set X and set Y , then f is surjective iff 8y 2 Y; 9x 2 X; f(x) = y Figure 1: Injective map.
    [Show full text]
  • Linear Transformation (Sections 1.8, 1.9) General View: Given an Input, the Transformation Produces an Output
    Linear Transformation (Sections 1.8, 1.9) General view: Given an input, the transformation produces an output. In this sense, a function is also a transformation. 1 4 3 1 3 Example. Let A = and x = 1 . Describe matrix-vector multiplication Ax 2 0 5 1 1 1 in the language of transformation. 1 4 3 1 31 5 Ax b 2 0 5 11 8 1 Vector x is transformed into vector b by left matrix multiplication Definition and terminologies. Transformation (or function or mapping) T from Rn to Rm is a rule that assigns to each vector x in Rn a vector T(x) in Rm. • Notation: T: Rn → Rm • Rn is the domain of T • Rm is the codomain of T • T(x) is the image of vector x • The set of all images T(x) is the range of T • When T(x) = Ax, A is a m×n size matrix. Range of T = Span{ column vectors of A} (HW1.8.7) See class notes for other examples. Linear Transformation --- Existence and Uniqueness Questions (Section 1.9) Definition 1: T: Rn → Rm is onto if each b in Rm is the image of at least one x in Rn. • i.e. codomain Rm = range of T • When solve T(x) = b for x (or Ax=b, A is the standard matrix), there exists at least one solution (Existence question). Definition 2: T: Rn → Rm is one-to-one if each b in Rm is the image of at most one x in Rn. • i.e. When solve T(x) = b for x (or Ax=b, A is the standard matrix), there exists either a unique solution or none at all (Uniqueness question).
    [Show full text]
  • Math 101 B-Packet
    Math 101 B-Packet Scott Rome Winter 2012-13 1 Redefining functions This quarter we have defined a function as a rule which assigns exactly one output to each input, and so far we have been happy with this definition. Unfortunately, this way of thinking of a function is insufficient as things become more complicated in mathematics. For a better understanding of a function, we will first need to define it better. Definition 1.1. Let X; Y be any sets. A function f : X ! Y is a rule which assigns every element of X to an element of Y . The sets X and Y are called the domain and codomain of f respectively. x f(x) y Figure 1: This function f : X ! Y maps x 7! f(x). The green circle indicates the range of the function. Notice y is in the codomain, but f does not map to it. Remark 1.2. It is necessary to define the rule, the domain, and the codomain to define a function. Thus far in the class, we have been \sloppy" when working with functions. Remark 1.3. Notice how in the definition, the function is defined by three things: the rule, the domain, and the codomain. That means you can define functions that seem to be the same, but are actually different as we will see. The domain of a function can be thought of as the set of all inputs (that is, everything in the domain will be mapped somewhere by the function). On the other hand, the codomain of a function is the set of all possible outputs, and a function may not necessarily map to every element of the codomain.
    [Show full text]
  • Sets, Functions, and Domains
    Sets, Functions, and Domains Functions are fundamental to denotational semantics. This chapter introduces functions through set theory, which provides a precise yet intuitive formulation. In addition, the con- cepts of set theory form a foundation for the theory of semantic domains, the value spaces used for giving meaning to languages. We examine the basic principles of sets, functions, and domains in turn. 2.1 SETS __________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________________ A set is a collection; it can contain numbers, persons, other sets, or (almost) anything one wishes. Most of the examples in this book use numbers and sets of numbers as the members of sets. Like any concept, a set needs a representation so that it can be written down. Braces are used to enclose the members of a set. Thus, { 1, 4, 7 } represents the set containing the numbers 1, 4, and 7. These are also sets: { 1, { 1, 4, 7 }, 4 } { red, yellow, grey } {} The last example is the empty set, the set with no members, also written as ∅. When a set has a large number of members, it is more convenient to specify the condi- tions for membership than to write all the members. A set S can be de®ned by S= { x | P(x) }, which says that an object a belongs to S iff (if and only if) a has property P, that is, P(a) holds true. For example, let P be the property ``is an even integer.'' Then { x | x is an even integer } de®nes the set of even integers, an in®nite set. Note that ∅ can be de®ned as the set { x | x≠x }.
    [Show full text]
  • Parametrised Enumeration
    Parametrised Enumeration Arne Meier Februar 2020 color guide (the dark blue is the same with the Gottfried Wilhelm Leibnizuniversity Universität logo) Hannover c: 100 m: 70 Institut für y: 0 k: 0 Theoretische c: 35 m: 0 y: 10 Informatik k: 0 c: 0 m: 0 y: 0 k: 35 Fakultät für Elektrotechnik und Informatik Institut für Theoretische Informatik Fachgebiet TheoretischeWednesday, February 18, 15 Informatik Habilitationsschrift Parametrised Enumeration Arne Meier geboren am 6. Mai 1982 in Hannover Februar 2020 Gutachter Till Tantau Institut für Theoretische Informatik Universität zu Lübeck Gutachter Stefan Woltran Institut für Logic and Computation 192-02 Technische Universität Wien Arne Meier Parametrised Enumeration Habilitationsschrift, Datum der Annahme: 20.11.2019 Gutachter: Till Tantau, Stefan Woltran Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz Universität Hannover Fachgebiet Theoretische Informatik Institut für Theoretische Informatik Fakultät für Elektrotechnik und Informatik Appelstrasse 4 30167 Hannover Dieses Werk ist lizenziert unter einer Creative Commons “Namensnennung-Nicht kommerziell 3.0 Deutschland” Lizenz. Für Julia, Jonas Heinrich und Leonie Anna. Ihr seid mein größtes Glück auf Erden. Danke für eure Geduld, euer Verständnis und eure Unterstützung. Euer Rückhalt bedeutet mir sehr viel. ♥ If I had an hour to solve a problem, I’d spend 55 minutes thinking about the problem and 5 min- “ utes thinking about solutions. ” — Albert Einstein Abstract In this thesis, we develop a framework of parametrised enumeration complexity. At first, we provide the reader with preliminary notions such as machine models and complexity classes besides proving them to be well-chosen. Then, we study the interplay and the landscape of these classes and present connections to classical enumeration classes.
    [Show full text]
  • Categories and Computability
    Categories and Computability J.R.B. Cockett ∗ Department of Computer Science, University of Calgary, Calgary, T2N 1N4, Alberta, Canada February 22, 2010 Contents 1 Introduction 3 1.1 Categories and foundations . ........ 3 1.2 Categoriesandcomputerscience . ......... 4 1.3 Categoriesandcomputability . ......... 4 I Basic Categories 6 2 Categories and examples 7 2.1 Thedefinitionofacategory . ....... 7 2.1.1 Categories as graphs with composition . ......... 7 2.1.2 Categories as partial semigroups . ........ 8 2.1.3 Categoriesasenrichedcategories . ......... 9 2.1.4 The opposite category and duality . ....... 9 2.2 Examplesofcategories. ....... 10 2.2.1 Preorders ..................................... 10 2.2.2 Finitecategories .............................. 11 2.2.3 Categoriesenrichedinfinitesets . ........ 11 2.2.4 Monoids....................................... 13 2.2.5 Pathcategories................................ 13 2.2.6 Matricesoverarig .............................. 13 2.2.7 Kleenecategories.............................. 14 2.2.8 Sets ......................................... 15 2.2.9 Programminglanguages . 15 2.2.10 Productsandsumsofcategories . ....... 16 2.2.11 Slicecategories .............................. ..... 16 ∗Partially supported by NSERC, Canada. 1 3 Elements of category theory 18 3.1 Epics, monics, retractions, and sections . ............. 18 3.2 Functors........................................ 20 3.3 Natural transformations . ........ 23 3.4 Adjoints........................................ 25 3.4.1 Theuniversalproperty.
    [Show full text]
  • The Entscheidungsproblem and Alan Turing
    The Entscheidungsproblem and Alan Turing Author: Laurel Brodkorb Advisor: Dr. Rachel Epstein Georgia College and State University December 18, 2019 1 Abstract Computability Theory is a branch of mathematics that was developed by Alonzo Church, Kurt G¨odel,and Alan Turing during the 1930s. This paper explores their work to formally define what it means for something to be computable. Most importantly, this paper gives an in-depth look at Turing's 1936 paper, \On Computable Numbers, with an Application to the Entscheidungsproblem." It further explores Turing's life and impact. 2 Historic Background Before 1930, not much was defined about computability theory because it was an unexplored field (Soare 4). From the late 1930s to the early 1940s, mathematicians worked to develop formal definitions of computable functions and sets, and applying those definitions to solve logic problems, but these problems were not new. It was not until the 1800s that mathematicians began to set an axiomatic system of math. This created problems like how to define computability. In the 1800s, Cantor defined what we call today \naive set theory" which was inconsistent. During the height of his mathematical period, Hilbert defended Cantor but suggested an axiomatic system be established, and characterized the Entscheidungsproblem as the \fundamental problem of mathemat- ical logic" (Soare 227). The Entscheidungsproblem was proposed by David Hilbert and Wilhelm Ackerman in 1928. The Entscheidungsproblem, or Decision Problem, states that given all the axioms of math, there is an algorithm that can tell if a proposition is provable. During the 1930s, Alonzo Church, Stephen Kleene, Kurt G¨odel,and Alan Turing worked to formalize how we compute anything from real numbers to sets of functions to solve the Entscheidungsproblem.
    [Show full text]
  • Consider the “Function” F(X) = 1 X − 4 . in Fact, This Is Not a Function Until I Have Told You It's Domain and Codomain
    Consider the “function” 1 f(x) = . x − 4 In fact, this is not a function until I have told you it’s domain and codomain. More accurately we have to talk about the function 1 f : R \{4} → R, f(x) = . x − 4 It’s important to get in the habit of specifying the domain and codomain. In fact the definition of function f : A → B specifies it as a subset of the cartesian produce A × B. From this point of view, our function is the set {(x, 1/(x − 4) : x ∈ R \{4}} ⊂ R \{4} × R 1 Note: my definition of function is different from that of the book. Book does not require that the function be defined everywhere in A. Range The range of a function f : A → B is the subset of B consisting of values of the function. A function is surjective (or onto) if the range equals the codomain. The function f : R \{4} → R given by f(x) = 1/(x − 4) is not surjective because it misses the value 0. That is, the equation g(x) = 0 has no solution in R \{4}. 2 However, if we define a new function g : R \{4} → R \{0}, using the same formula g(x) = 1/(x−4), then g is a surjective function. Note that although the formula is the same, this is a different function from f because we have changed the codomain. To prove g is surjective, we must show that if y ∈ R \{0}, then the equation g(x) = y has a solution x ∈ R\{4}.
    [Show full text]
  • SET THEORY for CATEGORY THEORY 3 the Category Is Well-Powered, Meaning That Each Object Has Only a Set of Iso- Morphism Classes of Subobjects
    SET THEORY FOR CATEGORY THEORY MICHAEL A. SHULMAN Abstract. Questions of set-theoretic size play an essential role in category theory, especially the distinction between sets and proper classes (or small sets and large sets). There are many different ways to formalize this, and which choice is made can have noticeable effects on what categorical constructions are permissible. In this expository paper we summarize and compare a num- ber of such “set-theoretic foundations for category theory,” and describe their implications for the everyday use of category theory. We assume the reader has some basic knowledge of category theory, but little or no prior experience with formal logic or set theory. 1. Introduction Since its earliest days, category theory has had to deal with set-theoretic ques- tions. This is because unlike in most fields of mathematics outside of set theory, questions of size play an essential role in category theory. A good example is Freyd’s Special Adjoint Functor Theorem: a functor from a complete, locally small, and well-powered category with a cogenerating set to a locally small category has a left adjoint if and only if it preserves small limits. This is always one of the first results I quote when people ask me “are there any real theorems in category theory?” So it is all the more striking that it involves in an essential way notions like ‘locally small’, ‘small limits’, and ‘cogenerating set’ which refer explicitly to the difference between sets and proper classes (or between small sets and large sets). Despite this, in my experience there is a certain amount of confusion among users and students of category theory about its foundations, and in particular about what constructions on large categories are or are not possible.
    [Show full text]
  • The Mereological Foundation of Megethology
    The Mereological foundation of Megethology Massimiliano Carrara, Enrico Martino FISPPA Department, University of Padua (Italy) April 24, 2015 Abstract In Mathematics is megethology (Lewis, 1993) David K. Lewis pro- poses a structuralist reconstruction of classical set theory based on mereology. In order to formulate suitable hypotheses about the size of the universe of individuals without the help of set-theoretical notions, he uses the device of Boolos' plural quantification for treating second order logic without commitment to set-theoretical entities. In this paper we show how, assuming the existence of a pairing function on atoms, as the unique assumption non expressed in a mere- ological language, a mereological foundation of set theory is achievable within first order logic. Furthermore, we show how a mereological cod- ification of ordered pairs is achievable with a very restricted use of the notion of plurality without plural quantification. 1 1 Introduction David Lewis (Lewis, 1993) proposes a reconstruction of classical set theory grounded on mereology and plural quantification (see also (Lewis, 1991)).1 Mereology is the theory of parthood relation. One of its first formaliza- tions is Leonard and Goodman Calculus of individuals ((Leonard & Good- man, 1940), 33-40).2 Plural quantification is a reinterpretation of second order monadic logic, proposed by Boolos in (Boolos, 1984), (Boolos, 1985).3 In Boolos' perspective second order monadic logic is ontologically innocent: contrary to the most accredited view, it doesn't entail any commitment to classes or to properties but only to individuals, as first order logic does. Acccording to Boolos, second order quantification differs from first order quantification only in that it refers to individuals plurally, while the latter refers to individuals singularly.
    [Show full text]
  • Sets, Relations, Functions
    Part I Sets, Relations, Functions 1 The material in this part is a reasonably complete introduction to basic naive set theory. Unless students can be assumed to have this background, it's probably advisable to start a course with a review of this material, at least the part on sets, functions, and relations. This should ensure that all students have the basic facility with mathematical notation required for any of the other logical sections. NB: This part does not cover induction directly. The presentation here would benefit from additional examples, espe- cially, \real life" examples of relations of interest to the audience. It is planned to expand this part to cover naive set theory more exten- sively. 2 sets-functions-relations rev: 41837d3 (2019-08-27) by OLP/ CC{BY Chapter 1 Sets 1.1 Basics sfr:set:bas: Sets are the most fundamental building blocks of mathematical objects. In fact, explanation sec almost every mathematical object can be seen as a set of some kind. In logic, as in other parts of mathematics, sets and set-theoretical talk is ubiquitous. So it will be important to discuss what sets are, and introduce the notations necessary to talk about sets and operations on sets in a standard way. Definition 1.1 (Set). A set is a collection of objects, considered independently of the way it is specified, of the order of the objects in the set, or of their multiplicity. The objects making up the set are called elements or members of the set. If a is an element of a set X, we write a 2 X (otherwise, a2 = X).
    [Show full text]
  • Two Constructivist Aspects of Category Theory
    Philosophia Scientiæ Travaux d'histoire et de philosophie des sciences CS 6 | 2006 Constructivism: Mathematics, Logic, Philosophy and Linguistics Two Constructivist Aspects of Category Theory Colin McLarty Electronic version URL: http://journals.openedition.org/philosophiascientiae/413 DOI: 10.4000/philosophiascientiae.413 ISSN: 1775-4283 Publisher Éditions Kimé Printed version Date of publication: 1 September 2006 Number of pages: 95-114 ISBN: 2-84174-399-3 ISSN: 1281-2463 Electronic reference Colin McLarty, “Two Constructivist Aspects of Category Theory”, Philosophia Scientiæ [Online], CS 6 | 2006, Online since 01 September 2009, connection on 17 January 2021. URL: http:// journals.openedition.org/philosophiascientiae/413 ; DOI: https://doi.org/10.4000/ philosophiascientiae.413 Tous droits réservés Two Constructivist Aspects of Category Theory Colin McLarty Case Western Reserve University (USA) Abstract: Category theory has two unexpected links to constructivism: First, why is topos logic so close to intuitionistic logic? The paper argues that in part the resemblance is superficial, in part it is due to selective attention, and in part topos theory is objectively tied to the motives for later intuitionistic logic little related to Brouwer’s own stated motives. Second, why is so much of general category theory somehow constructive? The paper aims to synthesize three hypotheses on why it would be so, with three that suggest it is not. Philosophia Scientiæ, Cahier spécial 6, 2006, 95–114. 96 Colin McLarty The founders of category theory were not sympathetic to construc- tivism or to the idea that there can be a systematically constructive mathematics. Yet category theory has two unexpected links to construc- tivism which deserve to be posed as questions rather than stated as facts.
    [Show full text]