Philosophy of Science and "The" Scientific Method

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Philosophy of Science and Philosophy of Science and "The" Scientific Jim Griesemer, an assistant professor of philosophy at the Univ. of Califomia, Davis, CA 95616, did his undergraduatework in ge- netics at the Univ. of Califomia at Berkeley. There he became in- Method terested in the foundations evolutionary theory, going on to a master's in biology and a Ph.D. in the Committee on Conceptual Foundations of Science of the Univ. of Chicago. He has worked on the development of exhibits at the Museum of Science and In- dustry in Chicago, and is currently doing researchin the founda- tions of multi-level selection theory, representations of scientific Jim Griesemer reasoning, and the institutional history of biology. Downloaded from http://online.ucpress.edu/abt/article-pdf/47/4/211/86196/4448021.pdf by guest on 01 October 2021 The Argument od will be fundamentally changed, and indeed, the perception that there ever was a definitive Philosophy of science addresses two central ques- conception of scientific method is a myth stem- tions: (1) what is the structure of a scientific theory?, ming from an ahistorical, nondevelopmental and (2) what are the processes of growth or change view of philosophy of science. of science over time? The gulf between philosophical 3. One should therefore be circumspect in teach- treatments of these two questions is one of the great ing "the" scientific method or wielding "the" ironies of a discipline which prides itself on system- scientific method in argument against propo- aticity, comprehensiveness, and coherence. Separate nents of opposing scientific views. traditions have emerged since the 1960s to deal with There is a pernicious consilience, or false co- the two questions, rendering the gulf between them herence or robustness, about this myth of the scien- nearly institutionalized; the inheritors of logical em- tific method which stems from the fact that it has piricism, the formalists, analyze the structure of the- two rather different sources of support. One source ories in formal terms which promote an ahistorical, is the traditional emphasis philosophers of science asocial analysis of scientific change. The new histor- have placed on formalist accounts of theory struc- ical movement, heralded by Kuhn, but prefigured ture. The logician's deductive standard for scientific by others, explains the patterns of growth and explanation and rationality, and the attendant view change in science with socio-historicalmodels of sci- of theories as sets of axioms and rules in a formal entific work, leaving the structure of the products of language, leads to the idea that there is only one pos- science unanalyzed entirely or only inchoately spec- sible scientific method because there is only one ified and incommensurable with the analyses of the standard of logical deduction to all and only valid formalists. conclusions [see Suppe (1977) for a detailed account As this gap has become recognized as the sort of of the history of these ideas; Nagel (1961) and foundational problem which can lead either to the Hempel (1965) give important statements of the subdivision of the field into a formalist program and view]. "The" scientific method is, accordingly, the a socio-historicalprogram, or to a grand unification, testing of universal statements offered as scientific philosophy of science has entered a period of tumult laws by comparing deductive consequences of laws and transition. In this essay I wish to draw a lesson with statements of observational facts about the from these observations which has not been widely world. Karl Popper (1965) calls it the method of appreciated outside history, philosophy, and so- "conjecturesand refutations." ciology of science that has particularrelevance to sci- The other main source of the myth of the scientific ence educators. The argument I wish to make is as method comes from a historical view of science, con- follows: ditioned by philosophical treatments (by both phi- 1. A clearer conception of scientific method is rec- losophers and scientists), which fails to recognize ognized on both sides as a central element of any diversity of goals, interests, or motives among any possible reconciliationbetween the two tra- the people who do science that might influence their ditions in philosophy of science. methods. This view is a species of "essentialism" 2. Regardless of the outcome (philosophy of sci- applied to science, i.e., that there is a timeless es- ence split into two or more disciplines or grand sence of science which captures the important fea- unification), our conception of scientific meth- tures, all others being mere distraction [see Hull PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE 211 (1975, 1983) for extensive criticism of essentialism in The FormalistConception of history and philosophy of science]. Science seeks Explanationand ScientificChange "the" truth about the world, and the rational scien- The deductive-nomological model of explanation tist pursues "the" best method for attaining truth. (see Hempel 1965, 1966) epitomizes the best and This conception of science led Popper (1959, p. 15) worst of the formalist approach. Explanations are to argue that "The central problem of epistemology deductive arguments, on this view, with the conclu- has always been and still is the problem of the sion being the "explanandum" and the premises growth of knowledge. And thegrowth of knowledgecan consisting of sentences stating general laws and be studiedbest by studyingthe growthof scientificknowl- spe- cial rules (see Hempel 1966, Ch. 5 for a brief intro- edge."This presumably follows from the assumption duction). The explanandum sentence is that if anyone gains knowledge, it's the scientists, so typically supposed to describe an event or state of The we should study them in order to develop a para- affairs. chief virtue of this "covering-law model" (where the digm description of the growth of knowledge. laws deductively "cover" the explanandum) is the The turmoil in philosophy of science today stems, rigor with which deductive inferences can be made. in part, from a move away from essentialist thinking Only true conclusions can follow from (Hull 1975, 1983; Toulmin 1967, 1971, 1972) which deductively true premises, so it appears very powerful to consid- has, in turn, been motivated by increased considera- Downloaded from http://online.ucpress.edu/abt/article-pdf/47/4/211/86196/4448021.pdf by guest on 01 October 2021 er as a form of deductive inference. tion of biology as a subject of philosophical study. explanation Several sorts of when Biology is much less easily pigeon-holed by formalist difficulty arise, however, this analysis is applied to scientific practice. First, approaches than physics has been in the past. Biolo- of formal gists would be hard pressed to find much biological the technical difficulties analysis of scien- tific theories expressed in natural insight in Woodger's (1937) attempt to axiomatize bi- language are for- midable. A comparison of the text of Darwin's ology, though Mary Williams' efforts (1970) are of (1859) On the Origin with more interest precisely because they show how far a of Species Mary Williams' (1970) axiom system sobers one to the reform of our concept of deduction is required to re- immensity of the task. since theories are main within the outlines of formalism. On the one Second, viewed as linguistic structures sets of hand biology is much less highly mathematized than (i.e., sentences), deep problems of epistemology arise in linking scientific theories physics, so it is more difficult to see how to proceed to the world. sentences can be from ax- with formal analysis. On the other hand, much of Only derived what are the criteria the existing historical scholarship on biology has de- ioms, so by which we judge that a particularexplanandum veloped in the same period as the philosophical de- sentence corresponds to an event or state of affairs in the velopments under discussion, so there is a reduced world? Logic is on this word-world relation. tendency toward the kind of linear story-telling silent of which has added to the false sense of correctness of Third, the singular goal deductive inference, to that truth will essentialist analyses of physics. guarantee only emerge from scientific In the remainder of this essay I will discuss se- arguments with true premises, elevates truth and to an lected features of the two traditions, draw some im- explanation excessively exalted height. Deduc- tive to plications for our understanding of scientific meth- logic provides no machinery analyze the crea- tion, or dissemination, or reception of scientific od, and describe some new directions for research ideas. Popper (1959, p. 31) addresses this which emphasize the importance of the pedagogical problem a hard line limitations of "the" scientific method. Because phi- by drawing between the process of scien- tific discovery on the one hand and losophy of science research is becoming (1) more the process of scientific justification on the other, delegating the pluralistic in its conception of method and simul- former process to the sciences taneously more cautious in generalizing from one special and retaining only the hard nut with some for domain of science to others, and (2) more centrally promise deductive in his He concerned to base answers to bothtraditional philo- analysis program. writes, sophical questions about science on a broad account The initial stage, the act of conceiving or inventing a of scientific method, educators should discuss ques- theory, seems to me neither to call for logical analysis nor to be susceptible of it. The question how it hap- tions of method with historical and philosophical pens that a new idea occurs to a man-whether it is a sensitivity. Students who learn that "the" scientific musical theme, a dramaticconflict, or a scientific the- method is a myth will be less inclined to view sci- ory-may be of great interest to empirical psychol- ence as a cookbook procedure and more able to re- ogy; but it is irrelevant to the logical analysis of scien- flect on the complexity and excitement of scientific tificknowledge.
Recommended publications
  • Jackson: Choosing a Methodology: Philosophical Underpinning
    JACKSON: CHOOSING A METHODOLOGY: PHILOSOPHICAL UNDERPINNING Choosing a Methodology: Philosophical Practitioner Research Underpinning In Higher Education Copyright © 2013 University of Cumbria Vol 7 (1) pages 49-62 Elizabeth Jackson University of Cumbria [email protected] Abstract As a university lecturer, I find that a frequent question raised by Masters students concerns the methodology chosen for research and the rationale required in dissertations. This paper unpicks some of the philosophical coherence that can inform choices to be made regarding methodology and a well-thought out rationale that can add to the rigour of a research project. It considers the conceptual framework for research including the ontological and epistemological perspectives that are pertinent in choosing a methodology and subsequently the methods to be used. The discussion is exemplified using a concrete example of a research project in order to contextualise theory within practice. Key words Ontology; epistemology; positionality; relationality; methodology; method. Introduction This paper arises from work with students writing Masters dissertations who frequently express confusion and doubt about how appropriate methodology is chosen for research. It will be argued here that consideration of philosophical underpinning can be crucial for both shaping research design and for explaining approaches taken in order to support credibility of research outcomes. It is beneficial, within the unique context of the research, for the researcher to carefully
    [Show full text]
  • Science Standards
    SCIENCE It is the policy of the Oklahoma State Department of Education (OSDE) not to discriminate on the basis of race, color, religion, gender, national origin, age, or disability in its programs or employment practices as required by Title VI and VII of the Civil Rights Act of 1964, Title IX of the Education Amendments of 1972, and Section 504 of the Rehabilitation Act of 1973. Civil rights compliance inquiries related to the OSDE may be directed to the Affirmative Action Officer, Room 111, 2500 North Lincoln Boulevard, Oklahoma City, Oklahoma 73105-4599, telephone number (405) 522-4930; or, the United States Department of Education’s Assistant Secretary for Civil Rights. Inquires or concerns regarding compliance with Title IX by local school districts should be presented to the local school district Title IX coordinator. This publication, printed by the State Department of Education Printing Services, is issued by the Oklahoma State Department of Education as authorized by 70 O.S. § 3-104. Five hundred copies have been prepared using Title I, Part A, School Improvement funds at a cost of $.15 per copy. Copies have been deposited with the Publications Clearinghouse of the Oklahoma Department of Libraries. DECEMBER 2013. SCIENCE Table of Contents 5-8 Introduction 9 K-5 Overview 10-18 ■ KINDERGARTEN 19-28 ■ 1ST GRADE 29-39 ■ 2ND GRADE 40-54 ■ 3RD GRADE 55-68 ■ 4TH GRADE 69-82 ■ 5TH GRADE 83 6-12 Overview 84-101 ■ 6TH GRADE 102-119 ■ 7TH GRADE 120-137 ■ 8TH GRADE 138-152 ■ PHYSICAL SCIENCE 153-165 ■ CHEMISTRY 166-181 ■ PHYSICS 182-203 ■ BIOLOGY I 204-219 ■ EARTH & SPACE SCIENCE 220-235 ■ ENVIRONMENTAL SCIENCE Introduction Science uses observation and experimentation to explain natural phenomena.
    [Show full text]
  • What Is That Thing Called Philosophy of Technology? - R
    HISTORY AND PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE AND TECHNOLOGY – Vol. IV - What Is That Thing Called Philosophy of Technology? - R. J. Gómez WHAT IS THAT THING CALLED PHILOSOPHY OF TECHNOLOGY? R. J. Gómez Department of Philosophy. California State University (LA). USA Keywords: Adorno, Aristotle, Bunge, Ellul, Feenberg, Habermas, Heidegger, Horkheimer, Jonas, Latour, Marcuse, Mumford, Naess, Shrader-Frechette, artifact, assessment, determinism, ecosophy, ends, enlightenment, efficiency, epistemology, enframing, ideology, life-form, megamachine, metaphysics, method, naturalistic, fallacy, new, ethics, progress, rationality, rule, science, techno-philosophy Contents 1. Introduction 2. Locating technology with respect to science 2.1. Structure and Content 2.2. Method 2.3. Aim 2.4. Pattern of Change 3. Locating philosophy of technology 4. Early philosophies of technology 4.1. Aristotelianism 4.2. Technological Pessimism 4.3. Technological Optimism 4.4. Heidegger’s Existentialism and the Essence of Technology 4.5. Mumford’s Megamachinism 4.6. Neomarxism 4.6.1. Adorno-Horkheimer 4.6.2. Marcuse 4.6.3. Habermas 5. Recent philosophies of technology 5.1. L. Winner 5.2. A. Feenberg 5.3. EcosophyUNESCO – EOLSS 6. Technology and values 6.1. Shrader-Frechette Claims 6.2. H Jonas 7. Conclusions SAMPLE CHAPTERS Glossary Bibliography Biographical Sketch Summary A philosophy of technology is mainly a critical reflection on technology from the point of view of the main chapters of philosophy, e.g., metaphysics, epistemology and ethics. Technology has had a fast development since the middle of the 20th century , especially ©Encyclopedia of Life Support Systems (EOLSS) HISTORY AND PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE AND TECHNOLOGY – Vol. IV - What Is That Thing Called Philosophy of Technology? - R.
    [Show full text]
  • The Rhetoric of Positivism Versus Interpretivism: a Personal View1
    Weber/Editor’s Comments EDITOR’S COMMENTS The Rhetoric of Positivism Versus Interpretivism: A Personal View1 Many years ago I attended a conference on interpretive research in information systems. My goal was to learn more about interpretive research. In my Ph.D. education, I had studied primarily positivist research methods—for example, experiments, surveys, and field studies. I knew little, however, about interpretive methods. I hoped to improve my knowledge of interpretive methods with a view to using them in due course in my research work. A plenary session at the conference was devoted to a panel discussion on improving the acceptance of interpretive methods within the information systems discipline. During the session, a number of speakers criticized positivist research harshly. Many members in the audience also took up the cudgel to denigrate positivist research. If any other positivistic researchers were present at the session beside me, like me they were cowed. None of us dared to rise and speak in defence of positivism. Subsequently, I came to understand better the feelings of frustration and disaffection that many early interpretive researchers in the information systems discipline experienced when they attempted to publish their work. They felt that often their research was evaluated improperly and treated unfairly. They contended that colleagues who lacked knowledge of interpretive research methods controlled most of the journals. As a result, their work was evaluated using criteria attuned to positivism rather than interpretivism. My most-vivid memory of the panel session, however, was my surprise at the way positivism was being characterized by my colleagues in the session.
    [Show full text]
  • A Comprehensive Framework to Reinforce Evidence Synthesis Features in Cloud-Based Systematic Review Tools
    applied sciences Article A Comprehensive Framework to Reinforce Evidence Synthesis Features in Cloud-Based Systematic Review Tools Tatiana Person 1,* , Iván Ruiz-Rube 1 , José Miguel Mota 1 , Manuel Jesús Cobo 1 , Alexey Tselykh 2 and Juan Manuel Dodero 1 1 Department of Informatics Engineering, University of Cadiz, 11519 Puerto Real, Spain; [email protected] (I.R.-R.); [email protected] (J.M.M.); [email protected] (M.J.C.); [email protected] (J.M.D.) 2 Department of Information and Analytical Security Systems, Institute of Computer Technologies and Information Security, Southern Federal University, 347922 Taganrog, Russia; [email protected] * Correspondence: [email protected] Abstract: Systematic reviews are powerful methods used to determine the state-of-the-art in a given field from existing studies and literature. They are critical but time-consuming in research and decision making for various disciplines. When conducting a review, a large volume of data is usually generated from relevant studies. Computer-based tools are often used to manage such data and to support the systematic review process. This paper describes a comprehensive analysis to gather the required features of a systematic review tool, in order to support the complete evidence synthesis process. We propose a framework, elaborated by consulting experts in different knowledge areas, to evaluate significant features and thus reinforce existing tool capabilities. The framework will be used to enhance the currently available functionality of CloudSERA, a cloud-based systematic review Citation: Person, T.; Ruiz-Rube, I.; Mota, J.M.; Cobo, M.J.; Tselykh, A.; tool focused on Computer Science, to implement evidence-based systematic review processes in Dodero, J.M.
    [Show full text]
  • Theory of Change and Organizational Development Strategy INTRODUCTION Dear Reader
    Theory of Change and Organizational Development Strategy INTRODUCTION Dear Reader: The Fetzer Institute was founded in 1986 by John E. Fetzer with a vision of a transformed world, powered by love, in which all people can flourish. Our current mission, adopted in 2016, is to help build the spiritual foundation for a loving world. Over the past several years, we have been identifying and exploring new ways to make our vision of a loving world a reality. One aspect of this work has been the development of a new conceptual frame resulting in a comprehensive Theory of Change. This document aspires to ground our work for the next 25 years. Further, this in-depth articulation of our vision allows us to invite thought leaders across disciplines to help sharpen our thinking. This document represents a moment when many strands of work and planning by the Institute board and staff came together in a very powerful way that enabled us to articulate our Theory of Change. However, this is a dynamic, living document, and we encourage you to read it as such. For example, we are actively developing detailed goals and action plans, and we continue to examine our conceptual frame, even as we make common cause with all who are working toward a shared and transformative sacred story for humanity in the 21st century. We continue to use our Theory of Change to focus our work, inspire and grow our partnerships, and identify the most pressing needs in our world. I look forward to your feedback and invite you to learn about how our work is coming alive in the world through our program strategies, initiatives, and stories at Fetzer.org.
    [Show full text]
  • Mothers in Science
    The aim of this book is to illustrate, graphically, that it is perfectly possible to combine a successful and fulfilling career in research science with motherhood, and that there are no rules about how to do this. On each page you will find a timeline showing on one side, the career path of a research group leader in academic science, and on the other side, important events in her family life. Each contributor has also provided a brief text about their research and about how they have combined their career and family commitments. This project was funded by a Rosalind Franklin Award from the Royal Society 1 Foreword It is well known that women are under-represented in careers in These rules are part of a much wider mythology among scientists of science. In academia, considerable attention has been focused on the both genders at the PhD and post-doctoral stages in their careers. paucity of women at lecturer level, and the even more lamentable The myths bubble up from the combination of two aspects of the state of affairs at more senior levels. The academic career path has academic science environment. First, a quick look at the numbers a long apprenticeship. Typically there is an undergraduate degree, immediately shows that there are far fewer lectureship positions followed by a PhD, then some post-doctoral research contracts and than qualified candidates to fill them. Second, the mentors of early research fellowships, and then finally a more stable lectureship or career researchers are academic scientists who have successfully permanent research leader position, with promotion on up the made the transition to lectureships and beyond.
    [Show full text]
  • Kant's Definition of Science in the Architectonic of Pure Reason And
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Institutional Research Information System University of Turin 372DOI 10.1515/kant-2014-0016Gabriele Gava KANT-STUDIEN 2014; 105(3): 372–393 Gabriele Gava Kant’s Definition of Science in the Architectonic of Pure Reason and the Essential Ends of Reason Abstract: The paper analyses the definition of science as an architectonic unity, which Kant gives in the Architectonic of Pure Reason. I will show how this defini- tion is problematic, insofar as it is affected by the various ways in which the rela- tionship of reason to ends is discussed in this chapter of the Critique of Pure Rea- son. Kant sometimes claims that architectonic unity is only obtainable thanks to an actual reference to the essential practical ends of human reason, but he also identifies disciplines that do not make this reference as scientific. In order to find a solution to this apparent contradiction, I will first present Kant’s distinction be- tween a scholastic and a cosmic concept of philosophy. This distinction expresses Kant’s foreshadowing of his later insistence on the priority of practical philos- ophy within a true system of philosophy. Then, I will present a related distinction between technical and architectonic unity and show how Kant seems to use two different conceptions of science, one simply attributing systematic unity to science, the other claiming that science should consider the essential practical ends of human beings. I will propose a solution to this problem by arguing that, if we give a closer look to Kant’s claims, the unity of scientific disciplines can be considered architectonic without taking into consideration the essential practi- cal ends of human reason.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy of Science Reading List
    Philosophy of Science Area Comprehensive Exam Reading List Revised September 2011 Exam Format: Students will have four hours to write answers to four questions, chosen from a list of approximately 20-30 questions organized according to topic: I. General Philosophy of Science II. History of Philosophy of Science III. Special Topics a. Philosophy of Physics b. Philosophy of Biology c. Philosophy of Mind / Cognitive Science d. Logic and Foundations of Mathematics Students are required to answer a total of three questions from sections I and II (at least one from each section), and one question from section III. For each section, we have provided a list of core readings—mostly journal articles and book chapters—that are representative of the material with which we expect you to be familiar. Many of these readings will already be familiar to you from your coursework and other reading. Use this as a guide to filling in areas in which you are less well- prepared. Please note, however, that these readings do not constitute necessary or sufficient background to pass the comp. The Philosophy of Science area committee assumes that anyone who plans to write this exam has a good general background in the area acquired through previous coursework and independent reading. Some anthologies There are several good anthologies of Philosophy of Science that will be useful for further background (many of the articles listed below are anthologized; references included in the list below). Richard Boyd, Philip Gasper, and J.D. Trout, eds., The Philosophy of Science (MIT Press, 991). Martin Curd and J.
    [Show full text]
  • PDF Download Starting with Science Strategies for Introducing Young Children to Inquiry 1St Edition Ebook
    STARTING WITH SCIENCE STRATEGIES FOR INTRODUCING YOUNG CHILDREN TO INQUIRY 1ST EDITION PDF, EPUB, EBOOK Marcia Talhelm Edson | 9781571108074 | | | | | Starting with Science Strategies for Introducing Young Children to Inquiry 1st edition PDF Book The presentation of the material is as good as the material utilizing star trek analogies, ancient wisdom and literature and so much more. Using Multivariate Statistics. Michael Gramling examines the impact of policy on practice in early childhood education. Part of a series on. Schauble and colleagues , for example, found that fifth grade students designed better experiments after instruction about the purpose of experimentation. For example, some suggest that learning about NoS enables children to understand the tentative and developmental NoS and science as a human activity, which makes science more interesting for children to learn Abd-El-Khalick a ; Driver et al. Research on teaching and learning of nature of science. The authors begin with theory in a cultural context as a foundation. What makes professional development effective? Frequently, the term NoS is utilised when considering matters about science. This book is a documentary account of a young intern who worked in the Reggio system in Italy and how she brought this pedagogy home to her school in St. Taking Science to School answers such questions as:. The content of the inquiries in science in the professional development programme was based on the different strands of the primary science curriculum, namely Living Things, Energy and Forces, Materials and Environmental Awareness and Care DES Exit interview. Begin to address the necessity of understanding other usually peer positions before they can discuss or comment on those positions.
    [Show full text]
  • Using the Scientific Method
    Using the Scientific Method 2002 and 2014 GED Content Area: Science Focus: Scientific Method (2002) and Scientific Hypothesis and Investigation(2014) Activity Type: Graphic Organizer and GED Practice Objectives Students will be able to: Appreciate the purpose of the Scientific Method Understand key terms related to the Scientific Method: observation, hypothesis, test, experiment, result, conclusion Relate the Scientific Method to an experiment Answer GED questions based on the Scientific Method Directions 1. Print the handout “Using the Scientific Method” (next page). Pass out the handout to the class. 2. Explain that the scientific method is the way scientists learn about the world around us. This involves several steps, often in the form of experiments. Discuss the 5 steps in the chart on the handout and define the highlighted words. 3. Have a student or students read the first passage out loud. Ask the class to fill in the chart. They can fill in the chart individually or in pairs (discussing these concepts can help students develop their thinking skills). 4. Discuss the students’ answers. Samples: 1. Observation: Where there was Penicillium mold, there were also dead bacteria. 2. Hypothesis: The mold must produce a chemical that kills the bacteria. 3. Test: Grow more of the mold separately and then return it to the bacteria. 4. Result: When the material is returned to the mold, the bacteria died. 5. Conclusion: Penicillium kills bacteria. 5. Have students read the passage at the bottom of the page and answer the GED practice question. Choice (4) is correct because the doctor saw that when the chickens ate whole‐grain rice with thiamine, they did not have the disease.
    [Show full text]
  • Foundations of Nursing Science 9781284041347 CH01.Indd Page 2 10/23/13 10:44 AM Ff-446 /207/JB00090/Work/Indd
    9781284041347_CH01.indd Page 1 10/23/13 10:44 AM ff-446 /207/JB00090/work/indd © Jones & Bartlett Learning, LLC. NOT FOR SALE OR DISTRIBUTION PART 1 Foundations of Nursing Science 9781284041347_CH01.indd Page 2 10/23/13 10:44 AM ff-446 /207/JB00090/work/indd © Jones & Bartlett Learning, LLC. NOT FOR SALE OR DISTRIBUTION 9781284041347_CH01.indd Page 3 10/23/13 10:44 AM ff-446 /207/JB00090/work/indd © Jones & Bartlett Learning, LLC. NOT FOR SALE OR DISTRIBUTION CHAPTER Philosophy of Science: An Introduction 1 E. Carol Polifroni Introduction A philosophy of science is a perspective—a lens, a way one views the world, and, in the case of advanced practice nurses, the viewpoint the nurse acts from in every encounter with a patient, family, or group. A person’s philosophy of science cre- ates the frame on a picture—a message that becomes a paradigm and a point of reference. Each individual’s philosophy of science will permit some things to be seen and cause others to be blocked. It allows people to be open to some thoughts and potentially keeps them closed to others. A philosophy will deem some ideas correct, others inconsistent, and some simply wrong. While philosophy of sci- ence is not meant to be viewed as a black or white proposition, it does provide perspectives that include some ideas and thoughts and, therefore, it must neces- sarily exclude others. The important key is to ensure that the ideas and thoughts within a given philosophy remain consistent with one another, rather than being in opposition.
    [Show full text]