The Axiom of Infinity and the Natural Numbers

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Axiom of Infinity and the Natural Numbers Axiom of Infinity Natural Numbers Axiomatic Systems The Axiom of Infinity and The Natural Numbers Bernd Schroder¨ logo1 Bernd Schroder¨ Louisiana Tech University, College of Engineering and Science The Axiom of Infinity and The Natural Numbers 1. The axioms that we have introduced so far provide for a rich theory. 2. But they do not guarantee the existence of infinite sets. 3. In fact, the superstructure over the empty set is a model that satisfies all the axioms so far and which does not contain any infinite sets. (Remember that the superstructure itself is not a set in the model.) Axiom of Infinity Natural Numbers Axiomatic Systems Infinite Sets logo1 Bernd Schroder¨ Louisiana Tech University, College of Engineering and Science The Axiom of Infinity and The Natural Numbers 2. But they do not guarantee the existence of infinite sets. 3. In fact, the superstructure over the empty set is a model that satisfies all the axioms so far and which does not contain any infinite sets. (Remember that the superstructure itself is not a set in the model.) Axiom of Infinity Natural Numbers Axiomatic Systems Infinite Sets 1. The axioms that we have introduced so far provide for a rich theory. logo1 Bernd Schroder¨ Louisiana Tech University, College of Engineering and Science The Axiom of Infinity and The Natural Numbers 3. In fact, the superstructure over the empty set is a model that satisfies all the axioms so far and which does not contain any infinite sets. (Remember that the superstructure itself is not a set in the model.) Axiom of Infinity Natural Numbers Axiomatic Systems Infinite Sets 1. The axioms that we have introduced so far provide for a rich theory. 2. But they do not guarantee the existence of infinite sets. logo1 Bernd Schroder¨ Louisiana Tech University, College of Engineering and Science The Axiom of Infinity and The Natural Numbers (Remember that the superstructure itself is not a set in the model.) Axiom of Infinity Natural Numbers Axiomatic Systems Infinite Sets 1. The axioms that we have introduced so far provide for a rich theory. 2. But they do not guarantee the existence of infinite sets. 3. In fact, the superstructure over the empty set is a model that satisfies all the axioms so far and which does not contain any infinite sets. logo1 Bernd Schroder¨ Louisiana Tech University, College of Engineering and Science The Axiom of Infinity and The Natural Numbers Axiom of Infinity Natural Numbers Axiomatic Systems Infinite Sets 1. The axioms that we have introduced so far provide for a rich theory. 2. But they do not guarantee the existence of infinite sets. 3. In fact, the superstructure over the empty set is a model that satisfies all the axioms so far and which does not contain any infinite sets. (Remember that the superstructure itself is not a set in the model.) logo1 Bernd Schroder¨ Louisiana Tech University, College of Engineering and Science The Axiom of Infinity and The Natural Numbers There is a set I that contains /0 as an element, and for each a 2 I the set a [ fag is also in I. In some ways this axiom says we can “cut across” the different levels of a superstructure and still obtain a set. The superstructure over I is a model that satisfies all axioms introduced so far. Axiom of Infinity Natural Numbers Axiomatic Systems The Axiom of Infinity logo1 Bernd Schroder¨ Louisiana Tech University, College of Engineering and Science The Axiom of Infinity and The Natural Numbers In some ways this axiom says we can “cut across” the different levels of a superstructure and still obtain a set. The superstructure over I is a model that satisfies all axioms introduced so far. Axiom of Infinity Natural Numbers Axiomatic Systems The Axiom of Infinity There is a set I that contains /0 as an element, and for each a 2 I the set a [ fag is also in I. logo1 Bernd Schroder¨ Louisiana Tech University, College of Engineering and Science The Axiom of Infinity and The Natural Numbers The superstructure over I is a model that satisfies all axioms introduced so far. Axiom of Infinity Natural Numbers Axiomatic Systems The Axiom of Infinity There is a set I that contains /0 as an element, and for each a 2 I the set a [ fag is also in I. In some ways this axiom says we can “cut across” the different levels of a superstructure and still obtain a set. logo1 Bernd Schroder¨ Louisiana Tech University, College of Engineering and Science The Axiom of Infinity and The Natural Numbers Axiom of Infinity Natural Numbers Axiomatic Systems The Axiom of Infinity There is a set I that contains /0 as an element, and for each a 2 I the set a [ fag is also in I. In some ways this axiom says we can “cut across” the different levels of a superstructure and still obtain a set. The superstructure over I is a model that satisfies all axioms introduced so far. logo1 Bernd Schroder¨ Louisiana Tech University, College of Engineering and Science The Axiom of Infinity and The Natural Numbers (Existence of the natural numbers.) There is a set, denoted N and called the set of natural numbers, so that the following hold. 1. There is a special element in N, which we denote by 1. 0 2. For each n 2 N, there is a corresponding element n 2 N, called the successor of n. 3. The element 1 is not the successor of any natural number. 4. Principle of Induction. If S ⊆ N is such that 1 2 S and for 0 each n 2 S we also have n 2 S, then S = N. 0 0 5. For all m;n 2 N if m = n , then m = n. The above properties are also called the Peano Axioms for the natural numbers. Axiom of Infinity Natural Numbers Axiomatic Systems Theorem. logo1 Bernd Schroder¨ Louisiana Tech University, College of Engineering and Science The Axiom of Infinity and The Natural Numbers There is a set, denoted N and called the set of natural numbers, so that the following hold. 1. There is a special element in N, which we denote by 1. 0 2. For each n 2 N, there is a corresponding element n 2 N, called the successor of n. 3. The element 1 is not the successor of any natural number. 4. Principle of Induction. If S ⊆ N is such that 1 2 S and for 0 each n 2 S we also have n 2 S, then S = N. 0 0 5. For all m;n 2 N if m = n , then m = n. The above properties are also called the Peano Axioms for the natural numbers. Axiom of Infinity Natural Numbers Axiomatic Systems Theorem. (Existence of the natural numbers.) logo1 Bernd Schroder¨ Louisiana Tech University, College of Engineering and Science The Axiom of Infinity and The Natural Numbers 1. There is a special element in N, which we denote by 1. 0 2. For each n 2 N, there is a corresponding element n 2 N, called the successor of n. 3. The element 1 is not the successor of any natural number. 4. Principle of Induction. If S ⊆ N is such that 1 2 S and for 0 each n 2 S we also have n 2 S, then S = N. 0 0 5. For all m;n 2 N if m = n , then m = n. The above properties are also called the Peano Axioms for the natural numbers. Axiom of Infinity Natural Numbers Axiomatic Systems Theorem. (Existence of the natural numbers.) There is a set, denoted N and called the set of natural numbers, so that the following hold. logo1 Bernd Schroder¨ Louisiana Tech University, College of Engineering and Science The Axiom of Infinity and The Natural Numbers 0 2. For each n 2 N, there is a corresponding element n 2 N, called the successor of n. 3. The element 1 is not the successor of any natural number. 4. Principle of Induction. If S ⊆ N is such that 1 2 S and for 0 each n 2 S we also have n 2 S, then S = N. 0 0 5. For all m;n 2 N if m = n , then m = n. The above properties are also called the Peano Axioms for the natural numbers. Axiom of Infinity Natural Numbers Axiomatic Systems Theorem. (Existence of the natural numbers.) There is a set, denoted N and called the set of natural numbers, so that the following hold. 1. There is a special element in N, which we denote by 1. logo1 Bernd Schroder¨ Louisiana Tech University, College of Engineering and Science The Axiom of Infinity and The Natural Numbers 3. The element 1 is not the successor of any natural number. 4. Principle of Induction. If S ⊆ N is such that 1 2 S and for 0 each n 2 S we also have n 2 S, then S = N. 0 0 5. For all m;n 2 N if m = n , then m = n. The above properties are also called the Peano Axioms for the natural numbers. Axiom of Infinity Natural Numbers Axiomatic Systems Theorem. (Existence of the natural numbers.) There is a set, denoted N and called the set of natural numbers, so that the following hold. 1. There is a special element in N, which we denote by 1. 0 2. For each n 2 N, there is a corresponding element n 2 N, called the successor of n. logo1 Bernd Schroder¨ Louisiana Tech University, College of Engineering and Science The Axiom of Infinity and The Natural Numbers 4.
Recommended publications
  • Equivalents to the Axiom of Choice and Their Uses A
    EQUIVALENTS TO THE AXIOM OF CHOICE AND THEIR USES A Thesis Presented to The Faculty of the Department of Mathematics California State University, Los Angeles In Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree Master of Science in Mathematics By James Szufu Yang c 2015 James Szufu Yang ALL RIGHTS RESERVED ii The thesis of James Szufu Yang is approved. Mike Krebs, Ph.D. Kristin Webster, Ph.D. Michael Hoffman, Ph.D., Committee Chair Grant Fraser, Ph.D., Department Chair California State University, Los Angeles June 2015 iii ABSTRACT Equivalents to the Axiom of Choice and Their Uses By James Szufu Yang In set theory, the Axiom of Choice (AC) was formulated in 1904 by Ernst Zermelo. It is an addition to the older Zermelo-Fraenkel (ZF) set theory. We call it Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory with the Axiom of Choice and abbreviate it as ZFC. This paper starts with an introduction to the foundations of ZFC set the- ory, which includes the Zermelo-Fraenkel axioms, partially ordered sets (posets), the Cartesian product, the Axiom of Choice, and their related proofs. It then intro- duces several equivalent forms of the Axiom of Choice and proves that they are all equivalent. In the end, equivalents to the Axiom of Choice are used to prove a few fundamental theorems in set theory, linear analysis, and abstract algebra. This paper is concluded by a brief review of the work in it, followed by a few points of interest for further study in mathematics and/or set theory. iv ACKNOWLEDGMENTS Between the two department requirements to complete a master's degree in mathematics − the comprehensive exams and a thesis, I really wanted to experience doing a research and writing a serious academic paper.
    [Show full text]
  • Axioms of Set Theory and Equivalents of Axiom of Choice Farighon Abdul Rahim Boise State University, [email protected]
    Boise State University ScholarWorks Mathematics Undergraduate Theses Department of Mathematics 5-2014 Axioms of Set Theory and Equivalents of Axiom of Choice Farighon Abdul Rahim Boise State University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://scholarworks.boisestate.edu/ math_undergraduate_theses Part of the Set Theory Commons Recommended Citation Rahim, Farighon Abdul, "Axioms of Set Theory and Equivalents of Axiom of Choice" (2014). Mathematics Undergraduate Theses. Paper 1. Axioms of Set Theory and Equivalents of Axiom of Choice Farighon Abdul Rahim Advisor: Samuel Coskey Boise State University May 2014 1 Introduction Sets are all around us. A bag of potato chips, for instance, is a set containing certain number of individual chip’s that are its elements. University is another example of a set with students as its elements. By elements, we mean members. But sets should not be confused as to what they really are. A daughter of a blacksmith is an element of a set that contains her mother, father, and her siblings. Then this set is an element of a set that contains all the other families that live in the nearby town. So a set itself can be an element of a bigger set. In mathematics, axiom is defined to be a rule or a statement that is accepted to be true regardless of having to prove it. In a sense, axioms are self evident. In set theory, we deal with sets. Each time we state an axiom, we will do so by considering sets. Example of the set containing the blacksmith family might make it seem as if sets are finite.
    [Show full text]
  • Chapter 1. Informal Introdution to the Axioms of ZF.∗
    Chapter 1. Informal introdution to the axioms of ZF.∗ 1.1. Extension. Our conception of sets comes from set of objects that we know well such as N, Q and R, and subsets we can form from these determined by their properties. Here are two very simple examples: {r ∈ R | 0 ≤ r} = {r ∈ R | r has a square root in R} {x | x 6= x} = {n ∈ N | n even, greater than two and a prime}. (This last example gives two definitions of the empty set, ∅). The notion of set is an abstraction of the notion of a property. So if X, Y are sets we have that ∀x ( x ∈ X ⇐⇒ x ∈ Y ) =⇒ X = Y . One can immediately see that this implies that the empty set is unique. 1.2. Unions. Once we have some sets to play with we can consider sets of sets, for example: {xi | i ∈ I } for I some set of indices. We also have the set that consists of all objects that belong S S to some xi for i ∈ I. The indexing set I is not relevant for us, so {xi | i ∈ I } = xi can be S i∈I written X, where X = {xi | i ∈ I }. Typically we will use a, b, c, w, x, z, ... as names of sets, so we can write [ [ x = {z | z ∈ x} = {w | ∃z such that w ∈ z and z ∈ x}. Or simply: S x = {w | ∃z ∈ x w ∈ z }. (To explain this again we have [ [ [ y = {y | y ∈ x} = {z | ∃y ∈ x z ∈ y }. y∈x So we have already changed our way of thinking about sets and elements as different things to thinking about all sets as things of the same sort, where the elements of a set are simply other sets.) 1.3.
    [Show full text]
  • SET THEORY Andrea K. Dieterly a Thesis Submitted to the Graduate
    SET THEORY Andrea K. Dieterly A Thesis Submitted to the Graduate College of Bowling Green State University in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of MASTER OF ARTS August 2011 Committee: Warren Wm. McGovern, Advisor Juan Bes Rieuwert Blok i Abstract Warren Wm. McGovern, Advisor This manuscript was to show the equivalency of the Axiom of Choice, Zorn's Lemma and Zermelo's Well-Ordering Principle. Starting with a brief history of the development of set history, this work introduced the Axioms of Zermelo-Fraenkel, common applications of the axioms, and set theoretic descriptions of sets of numbers. The book, Introduction to Set Theory, by Karel Hrbacek and Thomas Jech was the primary resource with other sources providing additional background information. ii Acknowledgements I would like to thank Warren Wm. McGovern for his assistance and guidance while working and writing this thesis. I also want to thank Reiuwert Blok and Juan Bes for being on my committee. Thank you to Dan Shifflet and Nate Iverson for help with the typesetting program LATEX. A personal thank you to my husband, Don, for his love and support. iii Contents Contents . iii 1 Introduction 1 1.1 Naive Set Theory . 2 1.2 The Axiom of Choice . 4 1.3 Russell's Paradox . 5 2 Axioms of Zermelo-Fraenkel 7 2.1 First Order Logic . 7 2.2 The Axioms of Zermelo-Fraenkel . 8 2.3 The Recursive Theorem . 13 3 Development of Numbers 16 3.1 Natural Numbers and Integers . 16 3.2 Rational Numbers . 20 3.3 Real Numbers .
    [Show full text]
  • How Set Theory Impinges on Logic
    1 Jesús Mosterín HOW SET THEORY IMPINGES ON LOGIC The set-theoretical universe Reality often cannot be grasped and understood in its unfathomable richness and mind-blowing complexity. Think only of the trivial case of the shape of the Earth. Every time the wind blows, a bird flies, a tree drops a leave, every time it rains, a car moves or we get a haircut, the form of the Earth changes. No available or conceivable geometry can describe the ever changing form of the surface of our planet. Sometimes the best we can do is to apply the method of theoretical science: to pick up a mathematical structure from the set-theoretical universe, a structure that has some formal similarities with some features of the real world situation we are interested in, and to use that structure as a model of that parcel of the world. In the case of the Earth, the structure can be an Euclidean sphere, or a sphere flattened at the poles, or an ellipsoid, but of course these structures do not represent the car and the hair, and so are realistic only up to a point. The largest part of scientific activity results in data, in contributions to history (in a broad sense). Only exceptionally does scientific activity result in abstract schemata, in formulas, in theories. In history there is truth and falsity, but we are not sure whether it makes sense to apply these same categories to an abstract theory. We pick up a mathematical structure and construct a theory. We still have to determine its scope of application or validity, the range of its realizations.
    [Show full text]
  • 1. the Zermelo Fraenkel Axioms of Set Theory
    1. The Zermelo Fraenkel Axioms of Set Theory The naive definition of a set as a collection of objects is unsatisfactory: The objects within a set may themselves be sets, whose elements are also sets, etc. This leads to an infinite regression. Should this be allowed? If the answer is “yes”, then such a set certainly would not meet our intuitive expectations of a set. In particular, a set for which A A holds contradicts our intuition about a set. This could be formulated as a first∈ axiom towards a formal approach towards sets. It will be a later, and not very essential axiom. Not essential because A A will not lead to a logical contradiction. This is different from Russel’s paradox:∈ Let us assume that there is something like a universe of all sets. Given the property A/ A it should define a set R of all sets for which this property holds. Thus R = A∈ A/ A . Is R such a set A? Of course, we must be able to ask this { | ∈ } question. Notice, if R is one of the A0s it must satisfy the condition R/ R. But by the very definition of R, namely R = A A/ A we get R R iff R/∈ R. Of course, this is a logical contradiction. But{ how| can∈ } we resolve it?∈ The answer∈ will be given by an axiom that restricts the definition of sets by properties. The scope of a property P (A), like P (A) A/ A, must itself be a set, say B. Thus, instead of R = A A/ A we define≡ for any∈ set B the set R(B) = A A B, A / A .
    [Show full text]
  • A SET-THEORETIC APPROACH to OBTAINING INFINITY by MATTHEW MICHAEL JONES B.A., University of Colorado, Colorado Springs, 2013
    A SET-THEORETIC APPROACH TO OBTAINING INFINITY by MATTHEW MICHAEL JONES B.A., University of Colorado, Colorado Springs, 2013 A thesis submitted to the Graduate Faculty of the University of Colorado Colorado Springs in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Science Department of Mathematics 2016 ii This thesis for the Master of Science degree by Matthew Michael Jones has been approved for the Department of Mathematics by Greg Oman Gene Abrams Greg Morrow Date: 12/14/2016 iii Jones, Matthew Michael (M.S., Mathematics) A Set-Theoretic Approach To Obtaining Infinity Thesis directed by Assistant Professor of Mathematics, Dr. Greg Oman ABSTRACT Many set-theoretic axioms have been formulated over the years which imply (along with the other axioms for set theory) the existence of what one would intuitively regard as an infinite set. In this thesis, we identify a property common to many such axioms, and then we obtain a more general class of “infinity axioms.” iv TABLE OF CONTENTS CHAPTER I. INTRODUCTION 1 II. PRELIMINARIES 6 III. RESULTS 16 REFERENCES 25 1 CHAPTER I INTRODUCTION The concept of “infinity” is ubiquitous in mathematics. Indeed, the collection of real numbers, the collection of prime numbers, and the collection of real-valued, continuous functions are all examples of infinite collections of objects. This is a notion we intuitively understand: a collection of objects is infinite if, in some sense, its elements “go on forever.” In modern mathematics, this is hardly precise enough to be a formal definition. But how can one define infinity? There are many answers in the literature.
    [Show full text]
  • Arxiv:1711.01603V1 [Math.HO] 5 Nov 2017 Bolzano's Infinite Quantities
    Bolzano’s Infinite Quantities Katerinaˇ Trlifajova´ November 7, 2017 Abstract In his Foundations of a General Theory of Manifolds, Georg Cantor praised Bernard Bolzano as a clear defender of actual infinity who had the courage to work with infinite numbers. At the same time, he sharply crit- icized the way Bolzano dealt with them. Cantor’s concept was based on the existence of a one-to-one correspondence, while Bolzano insisted on Euclid’s Axiom of the whole being greater than a part. Cantor’s set the- ory has eventually prevailed, and became a formal basis of contemporary mathematics, while Bolzano’s approach is generally considered a step in the wrong direction. In the present paper, we demonstrate that a fragment of Bolzano’s theory of infinite quantities retaining the part-whole principle can be extended to a consistent mathematical structure. It can be interpreted in several possible ways. We obtain either a linearly ordered ring of finite and infinitely great quantities, or a a partially ordered ring containing infinitely small, finite and infinitely great quantities. These structures can be used as a basis of the infinitesimal calculus similarly as in Non-standard Analysis, whether in its full version employing ultrafilters due to Abraham Robinson, or in the recent “cheap version” avoiding ultrafilters due to Terrence Tao. arXiv:1711.01603v1 [math.HO] 5 Nov 2017 1 Introduction 1.1 Existence of an actual infinity There are two major questions that anyone dealing with actual infinity has to ad- dress: 1. Is there any actual infinity? 2. If so, are there multiple infinities? How can we compare them? 1 An answer to the first question has been sought by many eminent thinkers, philosophers and mathematicians, starting from Aristotle, who formulated the question, to Cantor (Sebest´ıkˇ 1992).
    [Show full text]
  • LONG BOREL GAMES 3 Large Cardinal Axioms, Or Strengthenings of the Axiom of Infinity, and Use Them to Prove the Determinacy of Games on the Natural Numbers
    LONG BOREL GAMES J. P. AGUILERA Abstract. We study games of length ω2 with moves in N and Borel payoff. These are, e.g., games in which two players alternate turns playing digits to produce a real number in [0, 1] infinitely many times, after which the winner is decided in terms of the sequence belonging to a Borel set in the product space [0, 1]N. The main theorem is that Borel games of length ω2 are determined if, and only if, for every countable ordinal α, there is a fine-structural, countably iterable model of Zermelo set theory with α-many iterated powersets above a limit of Woodin cardinals. Contents 1. Introduction 1 2. Preliminaries 5 3. Determinacy and L(R) 7 4. Proof of Lemma 3.1 18 5. Derived model theorems 25 References 28 1. Introduction Given a Borel subset A of the Hilbert space ℓ2, define a two-player perfect- information, zero-sum game in which Player I and Player II alternate turns playing 0 digits xi ∈{0, 1,..., 9} infinitely often, giving rise to a real number ∞ x0 x0 = i . X 10i+1 i=0 arXiv:1906.11757v1 [math.LO] 27 Jun 2019 Afterwards, they continue alternating turns to produce real numbers x1, x2, and so on. To ensure that the sequence belongs to ℓ2, we normalize, e.g., by setting xi yi = . i +1 Player I wins the game if, and only if, ~y ∈ A; otherwise Player II wins. These are games of transfinite length ω2. (Recall that ω denotes the order-type of the natural numbers.) It is a natural question whether these games are determined, i.e., whether one of the players has a winning strategy.
    [Show full text]
  • Axioms and Models for an Extended Set Theory
    AXIOMS AND MODELS FOR AN EXTENDED SET THEORY ANDREAS BLASS AND D L CHILDS Abstract. We present the axioms of extended set theory (XST) and the ideas underlying the axioms. We also present an interpre- tation of XST in ZFC plus “there exist arbitrarily large inaccessible cardinals,” thereby proving the consistency of XST relative to this mild large-cardinal extension of ZFC. 1. Introduction This paper presents an extended set theory (XST) and proves its consistency relative to the classical Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory with the axiom of choice (ZFC) and an axiom asserting the existence of arbitrarily large inaccessible cardinals (also known as Grothendieck’s axiom of universes). The original motivation for this development of XST was to provide an improved, flexible mathematical foundation for certain constructions, like tuples and functions, that play important roles in computing. Subsequent developments revealed that XST also provides a smooth way of handling the set-class distinction that turns up especially in category theory. We shall comment on these matters in more detail after the axioms of XST have been introduced. The extended set theory XST differs from Zermelo-Fraenkel set the- ory ZFC in three major ways (and several minor ways). The biggest difference between XST and ZFC is that the fundamental membership relation of XST is a ternary relation, written x ∈s y and read “x is an element of y with scope s.” Most of the axioms of XST are analogs of traditional ZFC axioms, modified to account for membership scopes, and allowing atoms (also called urelements). This aspect of XST can be interpreted in ZFC quite straightforwardly.
    [Show full text]
  • The Mathematical Infinite As a Matter of Method
    Annals of the Japan Association for Philosophy of Science Vol.20 (2012) 1~13 1 The Mathematical Infinite as a Matter of Method Akihiro Kanamori∗ Abstract I address the historical emergence of the mathematical infinite, and how we are to take the infinite in and out of mathematics. The thesis is that the mathe- matical infinite in mathematics is a matter of method. The infinite, of course, is a large topic. At the outset, one can historically dis- cern two overlapping clusters of concepts: (1) wholeness, completeness, universality, absoluteness. (2) endlessness, boundlessness, indivisibility, continuousness. The first, the metaphysical infinite, I shall set aside. It is the second, the mathematical infinite, that I will address. Furthermore, I will address the mathematical infinite by con- sidering its historical emergence in set theory and how we are to take the infinite in and out of mathematics. Insofar as physics and, more broadly, science deals with the mathematical infinite through mathematical language and techniques, my remarks should be subsuming and consequent. The main underlying point is that how the mathematical infinite is approached, assimilated, and applied in mathematics is not a matter of “ontological commitment”, of coming to terms with whatever that might mean, but rather of epistemological articulation, of coming to terms through knowledge. The mathematical infinite in mathematics is a matter of method. How we deal with the specific individual is- sues involving the infinite turns on the narrative we present about how it fits into methodological mathematical frameworks established and being established. The first section discusses the mathematical infinite in historical context, and the second, set theory and the emergence of the mathematical infinite.
    [Show full text]
  • The Axiom of Choice and Its Implications in Mathematics
    Treball final de grau GRAU DE MATEMATIQUES` Facultat de Matem`atiquesi Inform`atica Universitat de Barcelona The Axiom of Choice and its implications in mathematics Autor: Gina Garcia Tarrach Director: Dr. Joan Bagaria Realitzat a: Departament de Matem`atiques i Inform`atica Barcelona, 29 de juny de 2017 Abstract The Axiom of Choice is an axiom of set theory which states that, given a collection of non-empty sets, it is possible to choose an element out of each set of the collection. The implications of the acceptance of the Axiom are many, some of them essential to the de- velopment of contemporary mathematics. In this work, we give a basic presentation of the Axiom and its consequences: we study the Axiom of Choice as well as some of its equivalent forms such as the Well Ordering Theorem and Zorn's Lemma, some weaker choice principles, the implications of the Axiom in different fields of mathematics, so- me paradoxical results implied by it, and its role within the Zermelo-Fraenkel axiomatic theory. i Contents Introduction 1 0 Some preliminary notes on well-orders, ordinal and cardinal numbers 3 1 Historical background 6 2 The Axiom of Choice and its Equivalent Forms 9 2.1 The Axiom of Choice . 9 2.2 The Well Ordering Theorem . 10 2.3 Zorn's Lemma . 12 2.4 Other equivalent forms . 13 3 Weaker Forms of the Axiom of Choice 14 3.1 The Axiom of Dependent Choice . 14 3.2 The Axiom of Countable Choice . 15 3.3 The Boolean Prime Ideal Theorem .
    [Show full text]