1 the Concept of Nature in the Thought of John Philoponus “We

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

1 the Concept of Nature in the Thought of John Philoponus “We The Concept of Nature in the Thought of John Philoponus “We must now ask how this dynamic and relational way of thinking in his science, strictly in accordance with the nature or reality of things, affected Philoponos’ theology in giving it a dynamic form in the doctrine of God and of salvation.” ---Thomas F. Torrance in Theological and Natural Science, p. 6 This essay is an attempt to clarify the way that the great 6th Century Alexandrian Grammarian, John Philoponus, thought to employ his concept of nature both in his philosophical or scientific works and in his theological works. It is argued that, for Philoponus, there exists a real cognitive interface between the science of his theology and the science or philosophy of his physics and cosmology. It is further argued that, standing on the holy ground of this interface, we may seek to understand the contingent order of the Universe as it comes to us from the Word or Logos of the Almighty. Take the concept associated with the term ‘Israel’. It means different things to different people, even in the Biblical World. It signifies differently to different peoples in various epochs in the history of the Biblical World. At Fuller Theological Seminary, the Bible scholar William Sanford LaSor, in his book entitled Israel, explored the meaning of this term across the epochs of the Biblical history with some sense of its mystery in its times and spaces in the history of the world. As a concept, the term possessed various significations across different centuries in numbers of diverse contexts, indicating a range of meanings with regard to the realities to which such a concept belongs. The Bible reader if referred all of these realities by this one term.1 In a similar way, the concept of Nature had meant different things to different people in various times and different contexts in our efforts to read the nature of the Universe. The great Quantum physicist, Paul Dirac, could employ the term in his science with the assumption of the real solidity of its significance for his physics.2 Yet only a few years later, the Cambridge physicist, Roger Penrose, in his magisterial work entitled The Road to Reality, can write about the possibility of understanding the wholeness of this Universe: “True---so they might argue- --we have been fortunate enough to stumble upon mathematical schemes that accord with Nature in remarkable ways, but the unity of Nature as a whole with some mathematical scheme can be no more than a ‘pipe-dream’. Others might take the view that the very notion of ‘physical reality’ with a truly objective nature, independent of how we might choose to look at it, is itself a ‘pipe-dream’.”3 In contrast to the reserve of our more modern scientists about the concept of nature, we find with our philosophers about 1 W.S. LaSor, Israel, (Eerdmans: Grand Rapids, 1976) 2 P.A.M. Dirac, Directions of Physics, (John Wiley & Sons: New York, 1978.) “The argument of the variation of the gravitational constant comes from a study of the constants of Nature. Nature provides us with the various constants: the velocity of light, the charge of the electron, the mass of the electron, and quantities like that.” (p. 72) 3 R. Penrose, The Road to Reality, (A. Knopf: New York, 2005), p. 1027 1 science, like André Mercier, ample attention to the concept along the lines of Dirac’s assumption.4 What has happened here? Professor Penrose’s only reference to the term nature in his Table of Contents is made with regard to the ‘holistic’ nature of the wave function in the Quantum World.5 However, he has contributed to a study exploring the concept of nature where he has distinguished SUPERB theories from USEFUL or TENTATIVE ones about the nature of the physical world.6. Still there is no reference in his index to the term. No effort is made to define the Universe as a whole.7 We will not find a discussion of nature as a general principle or concept in his thought. It seems implicit in his many of his explications of the various phenomena throughout this magisterial work, whose science he attempts to show us, but the concept of nature as a whole, it seems, remain something of a ‘pipe- dream’ for scientists today. Evidently, we can speak about the nature of various fields, with their continuums and their particles of energies, as we speculate about the ways we might become able to integrate these fields and particles in the future, yet knowledge of the Nature of the Universe as a whole must remain presently beyond our grasp. Unlike the ancient philosophers, today’s physicists are reluctant to conceive of the Nature of the whole Cosmos or Universe, let alone the Nature of God Himself.8 Concepts like ‘Israel’ then and nature, face us with perplexing referencing power. They belong to a realm of consciousness and conscience that confronts us with on-going challenges as to the actual substance of their significance. I would refer to them as ‘fluid axioms’ in the history of thought. We may employ them without a final definition, even as we are free to seek to discover and understand some real correspondence between them and the realities to which they would refer us in our times. The history of our experience with these axioms evidently requires an appreciation of our freedom to learn with our use of them of realities we apprehend only with a deep appreciation for the incomprehensible. These problems that we face about some real correspondence between theory and experience, the intelligible and the sensible, when we seek to understand the whole and parts in any field of knowledge, is wondrously evident throughout the works of Philoponus.9 Evidently, the use of terms and concepts associated with nature, their 4 A. Mercier, God, World, and Time, (Peter Lang: Berne, 1996). His index lists no less than 65 references to the term nature. He quotes Pascal for the general idea: “Man isn’t but a reed, the weakest, one in the whole of Nature; yet a thinking reed.” (p. 2-3) Also see, D.C. Lindberg and R. Numbers, God & Nature, (University of California Press: 1986), especially pp. 38-39 for Philoponus. 5 R. Penrose, op. cit., p. ix, where he writes ‘Wave functions have a strongly non-local character; in this sense they are completely holistic entities.’ The problem of ‘instantaneous communication’ is wondrous in the relationship between the holistic wave and the particle in the theory (pp. 512ff). 6 Roger Penrose, ‘The Modern Physicist View of Nature’, in John Torrance, ed., The Concept of Nature, Clarendon Press: 1992). Chapter 5, pp. 117-166. 7 Ibid, p. 363, ‘Mathematical elegance alone is not enough to determine correspondence with physical laws.’ 8 See R. Sorabji, Time, Creation & The Continuum, Cornell University Press: Ithaca: Yew York, 1983) for Philoponus on the nature time, infinity, and creation out of nothing in the Beginning (especially pp. 194- 231). Sorabji sides with Philoponus against his contemporaries, but up against modern developments of of concepts of infinity he is not so compelling. 9 See T.F. Torrance, Theological and Natural Science, (Wipf & Stock: Eugene, Oregon, 2002), Chapter Six, where a full discussion of the important terms in the debates that include the concept of nature in 2 universal and particular properties, their wholes and their parts, are to be variously assessed in diverse fields of knowledge across the centuries of the development of human thought. Our efforts to understand the fundamental realities that belong to the vital correspondence between thought and experience in our relations with nature is in fact at the very heart of the interface of our concerns both then and now. In 6th century Alexandria, the Grammarian, John Philoponus, sought to understand anew the nature of the Creator and the nature of the physics of His Creation, the nature of God and the nature of the Cosmos as it was conceived in his time. This same problem has confronted the both ancient and modern philosophers in fact, both modern researchers and ancient seekers of wisdom among the ages of civilization. It remains fundamental to our progress for human thought and knowledge. In these efforts, wonder and knowledge, freedom and the human imagination, are seen to resonate across centuries of civilized endeavor. They mark with steady progress the miracles of our understanding, the blood, sweat, and tears of human life and endeavor. We believe, with Philoponus, that those who seek the fruits of such efforts in our Creator become Incarnate in His Cosmos may find directions in their times that characterize the advance of civilization. If we work for the joy and beauty of this understanding, we work to obey His Command among the nations in our world. Perhaps in our time the confrontation between the Biblical World and the Physical World is more vital than ever for this progress. Perhaps it will take a new courage for philosophers, scientists, and theologians alike to discover our obedience to this Command. In any case, we may and we must seek still today for such resolutions between these worlds that must belong to the real future of our race upon this earth.10 Such challenges arise when we seek to understand the wholes and the parts of our experience, the universal with its particulars, in dynamical fields of knowledge that together make up the potential and actual relations between the physical universe and human consciousness. These challenges that Philoponus sought to face still face us Greek Science and Christian Theology with Philoponus.
Recommended publications
  • Projectile Motion Acc
    PHY1033C/HIS3931/IDH 3931 : Discovering Physics: The Universe and Humanity’s Place in It Fall 2016 Prof. Peter Hirschfeld, Physics Announcements • HW 1 due today; HW 2 posted, due Sept. 13 • Lab 1 today 2nd hour • Reading: Gregory Chs. 2,3 Wertheim (coursepack), Lindberg (coursepack) • HW/office hours 10:40 M,T, 11:45 W email/call to make appt. if these are bad Last time Improvements to Aristotle/Eudoxus Appolonius of Perga (~20 -190 BCE) : proposed: 1) eccentric orbits (planet goes in circle at const. speed, but Earth was off center) 2) epicycles (planet moves on own circle [epicycle] around a point that travels in another circle [deferent] around E. His model explained • variation in brightness of planets • changes in angular speed Ptolemy (AD 100 – c. 170): Almagest summarized ancient ideas about solar system. He himself proposed “equant point”: eccentric point about which planet moved with constant angular speed. Not true uniform circular motion, but explained data better. Ptolemaic universe (Equant point suppressed) • Note: this picture puts planets at a distance relative to Earth corresponding to our modern knowledge, but Ptolemaic system did not predict order of planets (or care!) • Exception: inner planets had to have orbits that kept them between Earth and Sun • Why epicycles? Not asked. Clicker quickies Q1: Ptolemy’s model explained retrograde motion of the planets. This means that A. Some planets moved clockwise while others moved counterclockwise along their orbits B. Some planets moved outside the plane of the ecliptic C. Some planets were observed to stop in the sky, move apparently backwards along their path, forward again D.
    [Show full text]
  • Philoponus on Topos
    Philoponus on τόπος. Redefining Place in Late Antiquity D i s s e r t a t i o n zur Erlangung des akademischen Grades Doctor philosophiae (Dr. phil.) eingereicht an der Philosophischen Fakultät I der Humboldt-Universität zu Berlin und verteidigt am 25. October 2013 von Ioannis Papachristou Der Präsident der Humboldt-Universität zu Berlin Prof. Dr. Jan-Hendrik Olbertz Der Dekan der Philosophischen Fakultät I Prof. Michael Seadle, PhD Gutachter Erstgutachter: Prof. Dr. Christoph Helmig Zweitgutachter: Prof. Dr. Christian Wildberg The dissertation attempts to interpret afresh, on the one hand, the form, methodology and structure of Philoponus’ commentary on the Physics and, on the other hand, to study in depth his theory of place (topos). The book extends over five chapters and includes a preface, an epilogue and a bibliography. Philoponus attempts a double determination of place. He distinguishes between the place which is void, three-dimensional extension that is ontological different from bodies, and the concept of place that is filled by bodies. Philoponus wishes to redefine the relationship between place and body and he underlines the ontological difference that a bodiless extension should have from a bodily extension. The thesis also focuses on Philoponus’ critique of Aristotle’s definition of place and the Peripatetic tradition (Eudemus, Themistius) regarding the place of the heavens. The book concludes that, Philoponus’ strategy in the digressions of the commentary, but also in certain parts of his exegeses, can be seen in three stages: first, he repudiates the cogency of Aristotle’s and Themistius’ critique to the concept of local extension; second, he attacks the Aristotelian definition of place by showing its weaknesses and inconsistencies with the nature of things; and third, he establishes his own theory of place.
    [Show full text]
  • 375 A. Mark Smith A. Mark Smith's Lucidly Written Account of The
    book reviews Early Science and Medicine 21 (2016) 375-377 375 A. Mark Smith From Sight to Light: The Passage from Ancient to Modern Optics (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2015), pp. 480, $45.00 (cloth), ISBN 978 02 261 7476 1. A. Mark Smith’s lucidly written account of the history of optics, from the an- cient world to the late seventeenth century, is comprehensive in scope and presents a radical break from the traditional narrative of the role medieval per- spectiva played in Johannes Kepler’s visual theory. Smith argues in a convinc- ing manner that while Kepler was clearly aware of perspectival sources, several elements of his thinking, and particularly his decision to accept the inverted retinal image as the principal means of sight, indicates a revolutionary turn away from the medieval tradition. This “Keplerian turn” had both analytic and epistemological elements, which Smith details at great length in his penulti- mate chapter. Smith characterizes his work as a “revamping” of David Lind- berg’s equally grand historical narrative Theories of Vision from Al-Kindi to Kepler, first published in 1976 (p. 4). In many ways this is an accurate assess- ment, barring Smith’s significant argumentative departure from the idea that Kepler relied on a firm grounding in perspectiva. Smith shifts his focus away from solely technical descriptions of optical theories, which can be found in Lindberg, and provides a much more inclusive history that treats the im- portance of psychological and theological texts in the development of perspec- tiva. Smith begins his narrative by exploring the earliest roots of perspectiva in the ancient sources, particularly Plato, Aristotle, Galen, Euclid, and Ptolemy.
    [Show full text]
  • Intermediary Structural Analysis Force
    Intermediary Structural Analysis Force Victor E. Saouma [email protected] University of Colorado, Boulder Fall 2017 Victor E. Saouma; CVEN 4525/5525; Univ. of Colorado Introduction 1/12 Table of ContentsI 1 What is Force Aristotelian Medieval Newtonian Victor E. Saouma; CVEN 4525/5525; Univ. of Colorado Introduction 2/12 What is Force What is Force? Force is in general defined as the cause of acceleration. Since acceleration is observable, its cause must be something real. Thus, force is real. However, some physicists and philosophers of science have, pointed out that force does not exist in reality. Broadly speaking, we can distinguish two movements: Aristotelian (pre 17th century) Newtonian (17th century onward) may possibly add one “Einstenian”. Excellent reference Concept of Force by M. Jammer. Victor E. Saouma; CVEN 4525/5525; Univ. of Colorado Introduction 3/12 What is Force Aristotelian AristotelianI Aristotle (384 BC-322 BC), pupil of Plato, tutor of Alexander the Great, writings cover physics, biology, zoology, metaphysics, logic, ethics, aesthetics, poetry, theater, music, rhetoric, linguistics, politics and government and constitute the first comprehensive system of Western philosophy. Rather than assigning a “divine” explanation of nature, through observation he sought to discover the principles and causes of (and not merely to describe) and then developed systematic set of ideas by categorizing things: most famously believed that earth was made up of four main elements: earth, air, water, and fire. Likewise, he classified motion as either Natural associated with celestial motion (circular), or terrestial (rectilinear). Violent: Force responsible for motion had to be in constant physical contact with the moved body.
    [Show full text]
  • Avicenna's Theory of Minima Naturalia Jon Mcginnis University of Missouri-St
    University of Missouri, St. Louis IRL @ UMSL Philosophy Faculty Works Philosophy 1-2015 A Small Discovery: Avicenna's Theory of Minima Naturalia Jon McGinnis University of Missouri-St. Louis, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: http://irl.umsl.edu/philosophy-faculty Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation McGinnis, J. "A Small Discovery: Avicenna’s Theory of Minima Naturalia." Journal of the History of Philosophy, vol. 53 no. 1, 2015, pp. 1-24. Project MUSE, doi:10.1353/hph.2015.0002 http://irl.umsl.edu/philosophy-faculty/1 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Philosophy at IRL @ UMSL. It has been accepted for inclusion in Philosophy Faculty Works by an authorized administrator of IRL @ UMSL. For more information, please contact [email protected]. A Small Discovery: Avicenna’s Theory of Minima Naturalia Jon McGinnis Journal of the History of Philosophy, Volume 53, Number 1, January 2015, pp. 1-24 (Article) Published by Johns Hopkins University Press DOI: https://doi.org/10.1353/hph.2015.0002 For additional information about this article https://muse.jhu.edu/article/566924 Access provided by Missouri @ St Louis, Univ of (17 Feb 2017 19:06 GMT) A Small Discovery: Avicenna’s Theory of Minima Naturalia JON MCGINNIS* ABSTRACT There has been a long-held misconception among historians of philosophy and science that apart from brief comments in Aristotle and Averroes, the theory of minima naturalia had to await Latin Schoolmen for its full articulation. Recently scholars have shown that far from sporadic comments on minima naturalia, Averroes in fact had a fully developed and well-integrated theory of them.
    [Show full text]
  • The Resurrected Body, Will It Be of Flesh Or Spiritual? Theological Discussions from the Time of the Apostle Paul up to the Sixth Century AD
    The Resurrected Body, WillScrinium It Be 11Of (2015) Flesh 225-241 Or Spiritual? 225 Journal of Patrology and Critical Hagiography www.brill.com/scri The Resurrected Body, Will It Be of Flesh or Spiritual? Theological Discussions from the Time of the Apostle Paul up to the Sixth Century AD Antonia S. Kakavelaki University of Athens, Athens, Greece [email protected] Summary The resurrection of the dead according to Origen and Philoponus is spiritual and not of the flesh. Their opinion, contrary to the official Christian view, was influenced by the neo-Platonic doctrine of “the subtle body of the soul” and based upon Aristotelian logic. Origen’s argumentation was formed as a personal interpretation of the passage of the Apostle Paul (1 Cor. 15:39–47) where Paul mentions that the risen body will be spiritual. Philoponus argumentation, on the other hand, was mostly based upon the Aristotelian logic and he thus directed his polemic against the irrationality of the arguments of Cyril of Alexandria and of Gregory of Nyssa. Keywords bodily resurrection – anthropology – Origenism – Gregory of Nyssa – Cyril of Alexandria – John Philoponus 1 Introduction In this article we are attempting to give a comparative account of the theo- logical thought mainly of Origen and John Philoponus upon the subject of the resurrection of the dead. In the long history of the Eastern Church this sub- ject matter received different interpretations from the time of the Apostle Paul up to the sixth century (which will be the chronological limit of our pres- ent study).
    [Show full text]
  • "Brief Bibliographic Guide in Medieval Islamic Philosophy and Theology
    BRIEF BIBLIOGRAPHICAL GUIDE IN MEDIEVAL AND POST-CLASSICAL ISLAMIC PHILOSOPHY AND THEOLOGY (2019-2020) Thérèse-Anne Druart The Catholic University of America I cannot thank enough all the scholars who kindly sent me information, and in particular those, who provided me with a copy or scan of their publications or of tables of contents of collective works. They are true scholars and true friends. I also wish to thank very much colleagues, who patiently checked the draft of this installment and provided supplementary information. Their invaluable help was a true work of mercy and scholarship. Collective Works or Collections of Articles Ansari, Hassan & Schmidtke, Sabine, Studies in Medieval Islamic Intellectual Traditions. Atlanta, GA: Lockwood Press, 2017, 495 pp., ISBN 9781937040918; e-bk 9781937040925 [updates of items previously published]. Avicenna – ein Universalgelehrter. Eine Gegenwärtige Analyse des Prinzen der Philosophen Ibn Sīnā, ed. by Merdan Günes (Veröffentlichungen des Instituts für Islamische Theologie der Universität Osnabrück 008). Osnabrück: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 2020, 169 pp., ISBN 9783847111047. La conoscenza scientifica nell’Alto Medioevo (Spoleto, 25 aprile – 1 maggio 2019) 2 vol. (Settimane di Studio della Fondazione, Centro Italiano di Studi sull’Alto Medioevo 67). Spoleto: Fondazione Centro Italiano di Studi sull’Alto Medioevo, 2020, 1196 pp., ISBN 9788868092832. Contre Galien. Critiques d’une autorité médicale de l’Antiquité à l’âge moderne, ed. by Antoine Pietrobelli (Sciences techniques 21). Paris: Honoré Champion, 2020, 302 pp., ISBN 9782745353269. La dottrina dell’analogia dell’essere nella “Metafisica” di Aristotele e i suoi sviluppi nel pensiero tardo-antico e medievale, ed. by Rita Salis (Subsidia Mediaevalia Patavina 14).
    [Show full text]
  • The Disagreement Between Avicenna and Al-Ghazali on the Issue of The
    The Disagreement between Avicenna and al-Ghazali on the Issue of the Pre-eternity of the Universe, how their Arguments Originated from Greek Philosophers and their Effect on Muslim Philosophers by Sulaiman Ahmed A thesis submitted to the University of Wales Trinity Saint David in partial fulfilment of the requirements of the degree of MRES Philosophy in the department of Humanities and Performing Arts Philosophy University of Wales Trinity Saint David Wales Supervisor: Dr Tristan Nash October 2017 © Sulaiman Ahmed, 2017 1 ABSTRACT AUTHOR Sulaiman Ahmed TITLE OF THESIS The Disagreement between Avicenna and al-Ghazali on the Issue of the Pre-eternity of the Universe, how their Arguments Originated from Greek Philosophers and their Effect on Muslim Philosophers DEPARTMENT Humanities and Performing Arts University of Wales Trinity Saint David DEGREE Master of Philosophy The aim of this thesis is to explore one of the three condemnations by al-Ghazali of Avicenna in his widely publicised book ‘Incoherence of the Philosophers’. The paper will focus on one of these three specific issues because it was these topics that were used by al-Ghazali to insinuate that Avicenna had transgressed the boundaries of valid traditional Islamic belief (kufr). The refutation of al-Ghazali are found in three parochial topics: (I) pre-eternity of matter and temporal nature of the world (II) God’s knowledge of particulars and universals, (III) the relationship between the resurrection of the body and the soul. The focus of this thesis will be on the issue of presenting the opinions of both the proponents of pre-eternity of matter as well as advocates of the universe being created out of nothing (creatio ex nihilo).
    [Show full text]
  • “Creatio Ex Nihilo” – a Genuinely Philosophical Insight Derived from Plato and Aristotle? Some Notes on the Treatise on the Harmony Between the Two Sages
    Zurich Open Repository and Archive University of Zurich Main Library Strickhofstrasse 39 CH-8057 Zurich www.zora.uzh.ch Year: 2012 “Creatio ex nihilo” – a genuinely philosophical insight derived from Plato and Aristotle? Some notes on the treatise on the harmony between the two sages Gleede, Benjamin Abstract: The article aims at demonstrating that in attributing the creatio ex nihilo to both Plato and Aristotle as their unanimous philosophical conviction the Treatise on the Harmony between the Two Sages deeply depends upon the Neoplatonic reading of those two philosophers. The main obstacles for such a view in the works of the two sages are Plato’s assumption of a precosmic chaos in the Timaeus and Aristotle’s denial of any efficient causality to the unmoved mover in the Metaphysics. Both of these points had been, however, done away with by the Neoplatonist commentators already, especially by Ammonius in his lost treatise on efficient and final causality in Aristotle the use of which in the Harmony isshown by a comparison with Simplicius. Christian and Muslim readers just had to transfer those arguments and hermeneutical techniques into an anti-eternalist context in order to make the two philosophers agree with one of the basic tenents of their face, a hermeneutical technique considerably different from the one employed by al-Fārābī in his exposition of Plato’s and Aristotle’s philosophy which is compared to the Harmony in a briefly sketched concluding section. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1017/S0957423911000117 Posted at the Zurich Open Repository and Archive, University of Zurich ZORA URL: https://doi.org/10.5167/uzh-69967 Journal Article Published Version Originally published at: Gleede, Benjamin (2012).
    [Show full text]
  • 199 Avicennan Infinity
    click here: authors/works; manuscripts; subjects AVICENNAN INFINITY 199 JON MCGINNIS Avicennan Infinity : A Select History of the Infinite through Avicenna 1. INTRODUCTION Puzzles arising from the notion of infinity have been part of the philosophical landscape since virtually the beginning of Western philosophy. One needs merely think of Zeno’s famous dichotomy paradox with its infinity of halfway points. Yet denying the infinite is equally paradoxical. One needs merely think of numbers, for if they were not infinite it would seem that there would be some greatest number to which the unit one cannot be added. Moreover, banish the infinite and one banishes irrational numbers, such as pi, as well as continuous magnitudes. It was the appearance of puzzles such as these and others that motivated Aristotle to explore the notion of the infinite in the detail that he did in both his Physics and De Caelo1 . Moreover, it was Aristotle’s analysis of the infinite that would dominate much of the subsequent discussion of the topic in the ancient world. Thus claims such as ‘an actual infinite is impossible’2 and ‘the infinite cannot be traversed’3 — both claims that Aristotle makes and uses throughout his physical writing — came to be treated as virtual dogma by many subsequent philosophers. Despite the authority of Aristotle, the medieval Muslim philosopher Avicenna (980-1037) in some way denied both of these points as well as others that involved Aristotle’s conception of the infinite. In fact, I shall argue that as a result of certain modifications that Avicenna makes in clarifying what infinity is, he develops the concept to a point that it can no longer be thought of as a strictly Aristotelian infinity, but must be viewed as an Avicennan infinity.
    [Show full text]
  • Consequences of Aristotle's Assertion in First
    ISSN: 2277-9655 [Sharma * et al., 7(2): February, 2018] Impact Factor: 5.164 IC™ Value: 3.00 CODEN: IJESS7 IJESRT INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF ENGINEERING SCIENCES & RESEARCH TECHNOLOGY CONSEQUENCES OF ARISTOTLE’S ASSERTION IN FIRST PART OF NEWTON’S FIRST LAW OF MOTION Ajay Sharma* *Fundamental Physics Society. His Mercy Enclave, Post Box 107. GPO Shimla 171001 HP. India DOI: 10.5281/zenodo.1165630 ABSTRACT Objective: One of the fundamental propositions of Aristotelian philosophy is that there is no effect without a cause. Aristotle justified that force is continuously needed to push or pull bodies. It was contradicted by Philonopus and Buridan, and then Galileo established law of inertia. Descartes and Newton’s laws are based on law of inertia. All facts are scientifically and neutrally discussed. However Aristotle’s assertion appears in first part of Newton’s first law of motion. Methods/Statistical analysis: The status of Aristotle’s, Galileo’s, Descartes and Newton’s laws is simultaneously reviewed. Basically Aristotle’s observation appears to correct in practical systems i.e. when resistive forces (gravitational, frictional and atmospheric) are present. Galileo’s law of inertia is applicable for system devoid of resistive forces i.e. for hypothetical systems. Findings: Aristotle’s assertion was criticized by many philosophers such as Philonopus, Buridan etc. Philonopus proposed that motion is due to kinetic force impressed by mover which exhausts gradually. Buridan proposed that motion is due to some property of body. Further Galileo expressed this property as inertia. Consequently Aristotle’s assertion was abandoned. However Newton’s first law simultaneously accounts for both Aristotle’s assertion (first part) and Galileo’s law of inertia (second part).
    [Show full text]
  • Humanities 116: Philosophical Perspectives on the Humanities Section No
    Humanities 116: Philosophical Perspectives on the Humanities Section no. 3. Mon. and Wed., 1:30–2:50pm, Cobb 304. Professor: Abe Stone [email protected] Office: Gates-Blake 228 Phone (office): 702-3085 Office hours: Mon., 11–12; Tues., 12:30–1:30; or by appointment. Writing Intern: Ed Upton [email protected] Course Requirements Classroom participation, including attendance at and participation in writing sem- inars. Three 4–6 page papers, due Mon., Jan. 27, Wed., Feb. 26, and Wed., Mar. 19. Texts Cervantes, Adventures of Don Quixote, tr. J.M. Cohen (Penguin Classics). (Note: there is a more recent Penguin Classics edition with a different translator, but I prefer this one.) Descartes, Selected Philosophical Writings, tr. J. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff and Dugald Murdoch (Cambridge). Hume, Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion, ed. R.H. Popkin, 2d ed. (Hackett). Leibniz, Philosophical Essays, ed. R. Ariew and D. Garber (Hackett). All texts should be available at the University of Chicago Bookstore (a.k.a. Barnes and Noble). Readings not on the above list will be made available as photocopies. (As was the case last quarter, you can use a different translation/edition at your own risk. We’re reading Hume in the original, of course.) Readings Mon., Jan. 6: (no reading, first class). Wed., Jan. 8: Cervantes, Don Quixote, pt. 1, Prologue and ch. 1–5, 7–10, and 15–18. Mon., Jan. 13: Cervantes, Don Quixote, pt. 1, ch. 20–22, 45-50 and 52. 1 Wed., Jan. 15: Descartes, Discourse on the Method, parts 1 and 2 (pp. 20–31); First Meditation (pp.
    [Show full text]