<<

Grazer PhilosophischeStudien 62(2001)17-63

SENSE DATA:THE SENSIBLE APPROACH *

Manuel GARCÍA-CARPINTERO Universitat de Barcelona

Summary Inthis paper,I presenta versionof asense-data approachto perception, whichdiffers to a certain extent fromwell-knownversions like the oneput forwardby Jackson.I comparethe sense-data viewto the currentlymost popularalternative theories ofperception, the so-called Theoryof Ap- pearing(a veryspecific formof disjunctivist approaches)on theonehand andreductive representational ist approacheson the other.I defendthe sense-data approachon the basis that it improvessubstantially onthoseal- ternative theories.

1. The Theory of Appearing

Sense data are out of favor these days. Most philosophers currently writing on conscious experience and perception go to great pains to avoid them. In arecent paper onperception Alston writes: “Since sense datum theory has been almost universally abandoned for good and sufficient reason, Ineed not spend time bad mouthing it” (Alston 1999, 189). Only two pages later, however, inresponse to the main argument for sense data, Alston (who purports to defend a

*Earlier drafts ofthis paperwere presented at the LOGOSseminar, Universitat deBarcelona,and at OxfordUniversity. I wouldlike to thankthe au- diences there forvery useful suggestions,and in particular Martin Davies,José AntonioDí ez,Dan Ló pez de Sa,Josep Maciàand Manuel Pé rez. V erydetailed comments byKevinMulligan led to manyimprovements, both of style andsub- stance. Financial supportwas providedby the research projects BFF2001-3466, fundedby the DGI,SpanishGovernment, and SGR2001-001 8,Generalitat de Catalunya. 18 version of the Theory ofAppearing) contends that in hallucination subjects are inexperiential relations with “aparticularly vivid men- tal image,”amental particular.Thus, although Alston dismisses sense data, he isprepared to commit himself to what was tradition- ally supposed tobe the main ontological burden ofthose theories. One then wonders what hetakes tobethe “good and sufficient rea- sons”to dismiss sense data. It is healthy toremember that it has not always been so;for agood half ofthe past century,sense data were taken for granted by most philosophers. For better orfor worse, anew trend was forcefully es- tablished bythe joint efforts of philosophers such as Austin, Ryle, Sellars and Wittgenstein, which has acquired the force of estab- lished presumption. Philosophers take for granted that Austin, Ryle, Sellars and Wittgenstein gave arguments that made it clear that sense data are one more philosophical invention; but they are not very explicit about how exactly the arguments go. There are, of course, some exceptions, outstanding among them Jackson (1977) and Perkins (1983). This paper isan attempt at avindication of sense data against currently fashionable alternative proposals, which de- parts at some points from their views but has been influenced by them. Like other accounts of sensory experience envisaging sense data, the one presented in this paper posits them as part of acausal account of perception. Any correct explication of perception will involve distinctive conscious sensory experiences. Perception isaform of ; perceptual states have arepresentational content, cor- rectness conditions that are as amatter of fact satisfied. There isa systematic, non-accidental relationship such that perceptual states with different intentional contents typically involve sensory experi- ences with different . Wereport the phenomenal character of perceptual experiences involved inperceptual states by resorting to “look”or “appear”talk: “it appears to Sas if abright red solid sphere of radius of about one foot hovers at about one yard in front of him against anundifferentiated gray background”. Asthis example reminds us, sensory experiences are quite com- plex. Itisnatural toisolate inthem phenomenal features: the appar- ent color, shape and size ofthe sphere, its apparent distance and po - sition with respect to the subject’s body,its apparent solidity,and so 19 on. These phenomenal features will be called henceforth qualia. This term is introduced without presupposing anything very contro- versial. Itisleft open here whether or not individual phenomenal features are relational, even when, as with appearances of shapes and colors for instance, they do not seem so at first sight. Qualia might be relational in the sense that the instantiation ofaquale al- ways involves the instantiation of an intentional object; this isso on the view advanced here. Qualia might even be relational in the most straightforward sense that the instantiation of aquale in the sensory experience in acase of perception always consists in the instan- tiation of arelation between the perceiving subject and afeature instantiated inamaterial object. This is the disjunctivist claim char- acterizing one of the views that Iwill be questioning, the Theory of Appearing. These introductory stipulations leave also open whether or not qualia are reductively definable in intentional terms –asan- other view on perception that Iwill becriticizing holds. Qualia can be isolated inour typically complex sensory experi- ences in amethodologically perspicuous way,by taking advantage of an important fact about them. The fact isthat instances of qualia are constitutively related to other qualia, relations ofwhich subjects aware ofthose instances are also consciously aware. Asubject expe- riencing an instance ofaquale will be able to recognize other in- stances of the same quale, and to discriminate them from other qualia. Also, he will typically beable to merely imagine qualia, and thus to be in adifferent conscious relation with them. Asubject will thereby be able to consciously appreciate how anew token feature of which heisaware orwhich he imagines shares some qualia with oth- ers he has experienced, and differs in some other qualia from them. Subjects are also consciously aware of determinables of which qualia as those previously mentioned are determinates, and also of orderings ofthe determinates in each determinable along different dimensions (hue, brightness and saturation for appearances of col- ors, pitch and timbre for appearances of sounds, intensity for most qualities, etc). Qualia thus belong in amulti-dimensional space. Elaborating on previous proposals by Carnap and Goodman, Clark (1993) shows how the presumption that specific qualia can be iso- lated inour complex sensory fields can be scientifically cashed out on that basis. 20

Ihave so far made the relatively uncontroversial claim that per- ception constitutively involves sensory experiences, states consist- ing in the perceptual subject being consciously aware of specific phenomenal qualities. What Iplan to do in the rest of the paper isto defend asense data theory of aparticular sort, by arguing that ithas clear advantages over alternative accounts of perceptual experience. Iwill consider two views: disjunctivism, inthe form of the Theory of Appearing (TA),aview that qualified observers consider the stron- gest rival of sense data accounts. 1 Iwill present this view inthe rest of this section. In the second section Iwill present and criticize a functional-cum-physical representationalist approach. The third section ofthe paper will outline the main traits of the sense data the- ory that Itake tobe correct. The fourth and final section contains my criticism of TA. TA(in Jackson’s (1977) terms, the Multiple Relation Theory of Appearing)is already discussed inclassic papers by Moore (1918-9), Chisholm (1950), Sellars (1963) and others, and has been given asharp formulation by Langsam (1997). Johnston (1997) and Alston (1999) have recently praised itasthe best account ofpercep- tual experience. The theory embodies aform ofthe disjunctive con- ception of experience incompatible (in contrast with other forms of disjunctivism) with sense data accounts. The main claim character- izing TAis that “phenomenal features such asredness are relations between material objects and minds”(Langsam 1997, 35). Asubject S experiences aphenomenal feature F if and only if S is in aprimitive relation with amaterial thing; this isthe relation consisting of that material thing appearing red to S.Itisthe primitiveness ofthe rela- tion which characterizes TA.As Jackson (1977, 91) emphasizes, sense data theorists do not dispute that when S perceives O to be red, O appears red to S.According tothem, however, the fact that amate- rial thing appears F to the perceiving subject is tobeanalyzed in

1.One suchqualified observer,C. D.Broad,wrote: “Howare weto describe [appearance]and to analyzeit? Twodifferent types oftheoryseem tobe possible, whichI will call respectively the Multiple RelationTheory , and the Object The- ory ofsensible appearance”(Broad 1965, 88). The first is Broad’s term forthe theoryof appearing(towards which he, like Mooreat times, was notentirely un- sympathetic, althoughboth he andMoore are classic proponentsof the sense data approach),the secondis his term forthe sense data theory. 21 causal terms involvingsense data. 2 It is therefore of the essence of TA thatthe relationof amaterial object appearing F to asubject be unanalyzable. This iscompatible with consideringthe appearing-re- lation as explainable (as opposed to analyzable)in scientificterms, even inscientific terms involving something called ‘sensations’. Most defenders of the theory of appearing, as we willsee, would support a claimof explainability,as opposed to one of analyzability. 3 The philosophical primitiveness of the relations postulated by the theory of appearing makes acausal analysis of Sperceives O out of the question. There is in this afurther incompatibility with sense data theories that explain the relation between sense data and per- ceived objects in causal terms. If the perceptual experience inacase in which S perceives O instantiating agivenfeature attconceptually involves the instantiation by O of that feature at t,nocausal claim linking the relevant state of O and the relevant experience E can be sensibly made under those .Surely causally related par- ticular events are “distinct existences”at the very least inthat, under the descriptions relevant for the evaluation ofthe causal claim relat- ing them, the of the effect shouldonly contingentlyrequire that ofthe cause. If c causes e, then, if c had not occurred, e would not have occurred either. But this counterfactual claim has adifferent force than this: if Socrates had not died, Xanthippe would not have become awidow; Socrates’s death did not cause Xanthippe’s wid- owhood. One difference lies inthat the former counterfactual, but not the latter, ismade with respect toacontext which includes possi- ble worlds (albeit sufficiently remote from actuality) inwhich e oc- curs without c having occurred. 4

2.In phenomenalistversions ofthe sense data theory,the relation wouldbe analyzedinstead as that ofa“material”thing – amere possibility ofsensation – becomingmanifest tothe subject byits definingpotentiality forsensations ofde- terminate types beingactualized. 3.See Moore(1918-9, 23), Chisholm (1950, 173), Sellars (1963a,141), Johnston(1997, 174)andAlston (1999,183).Sellars (1963a,150),whoseems at times to favorthe theoryof appearing,also advocated“ the idea that ‘immediate experiences’play a role analogousto that ofthe molecules ofthe kinetic theory.” Later Iwill interpret this as proposinga reductivist “third way”,close tothe view recently advancedby Tye(1984, 1995). 4.I rely hereon Lewis’(1973) well-known analysis ofcounterfactuals. 22

Traditional arguments for sense data elaborate two related con- siderations. In the first place, considerations based onthe facts of perceptual illusions ormisperceptions (including here the temporal illusions on which the “time-gap”argument isbased), and halluci- nations. In the second place, considerations based onthe need to dis- tinguish primary from secondary qualities. The arguments to bepro- vided here do not depart from these traditional themes. Ionly claim a measure of originality inthe specific way in which they will bede- ployed against recent supporters of alternative accounts, who seem not to appreciate the force of the traditional concerns regarding views like those they hold. Let us see at this point how the defender of TAattempts to handle the first sort ofargument. If we look at ared surface with one eye for about aminute, while keeping the other eye closed, and then immediately afterwards look at the surface alternately with the accustomed and the unaccustomed eye, we will realize that the color looks noticeably different. It looks bright red when looking with the unaccustomed eye, butis aconsid- erably darker shade of red when looking with the accustomed eye. 5 The appearance obtained with the accustomed eye is amispercep- tion, because the surface does not change color when we alternate eyes. TAhandles cases like this bycontending that one and the same material thing –the colored surface asitis atacertain time –appears to usbright red in one case and dark red in the other.That is tosay, one is in each case in adifferent primitive, unanalyzable relation with an unchanged material thing. Essentially the same consider- ations serve tohandle “time-gap”arguments. The subject isat time t unanalyzably related toamaterial thing as itwas at the time t – a (a > 0) when the material thing triggered the causal chain leading to the subject’s experience. The relation itself in fact obtains at t, the object appearing to have whatever properties the subject perceives it to have contemporarily with hisexperience. This temporal appearance may or may not be illusory,butthere are good reasons not tocount it so in most ordinary cases. 6 This same treatment cannot be applied to hallucinations, how- ever, for there is no material thing perceived inthose cases. 7 TA re- 5.I borrowthe examplefrom Clark (1993). 6.See the illuminating discussion ofthe time-gap issue bySuchting(1969). 7.It is probablybecause of this that Sellars (1963a,142) refuses to count‘ O 23 jects the common assumption that the appearances experienced in hallucination can be identical tocorresponding appearances present in subjectively indistinguishable cases of veridical perception or misperception. TAadopts instead the most radical form ofwhat has come to be known asthe Disjunctive Conception ofExperience –or disjunctivism for short. This view,advocated by philosophers like McDowell (1982 and 1986) and Snowdon (1981 and 1990), denies – in McDowell’s suggestive phrase –that the experiences involvedin vision and hallucination share a“highest common factor.” Thus, Langsam has this response to objections to TAbased on hallucinations: “Ideny …that the indistinguishability of perceptual experiences and their corresponding hallucinations can be ex- plained only in terms of their instantiating the same phenomenal fea- tures …it issufficient ifthey instantiate similar phenomenal fea- tures, phenomenal features that are the same insome respects but different in others …they need not share the same ontological char- acter; inparticular, the phenomenal features of perceptual experi- ences can beinstantiations of relations between material objects and minds even though the phenomenal features ofhallucinations are not. There isno reason tothink that two phenomenal features cannot share the same appearance yet differ inontological character” (Langsam 1992, 39). Iwill postpone acritical discussion of TAuntil the final section; my argument will beessentially abductive (sense data theories are better qualified toaccount for the relevant facts than their rivals), and only bythen will be the main considerations for this form of ar- gument in place. Against Langsam, Iwill present considerations there insupport of the view that the appearances in perceptual expe- riences and corresponding hallucinations share an ontological char- acter. Iwill argue that, atthe relevant first-personal level and not merely at the causal-explanatory level, there is no room for the wedge that Langsam seeks todrive between asubjective commonal- ity and areal distinction. There is something, however, that Ifind ap- pealing inthe disjunctive conception ofexperience, and Iwant to looksF to S’asrelational atall. Heposits acommonexplanatory factor to the three standardcases in which“ looks”talk is used,veridical perception,illusion andhallucination. This is the main reasonsupporting the representationalist in- terpretation ofhis views,to be providedin the nextsection. 24 grant itnow: itsrefusal tocountenance asymmetrical treatment of the experiences involvedin cases of hallucinations and cases ofper- ception. Perception is aform of knowledge, and perceptual experi- ences are constitutively intended toplay arole in accounting for the claims of perception onthat score. Experiences involved in percep- tion and in hallucination are asymmetric from an epistemological point of view; and the epistemic factors that determine the asymme- try ought to betaken into consideration in aphilosophical explica- tion ofperceptual experiences. 8 The main lesson from discussions ofthe Gettier-like counter- examples totraditional analyses of knowledge lies precisely here. There is little chance ofreductively capturing perception, or any other form of knowledge for that matter, by starting from afully non-factive notion (belief, in the general case; apurely internal no- tion of experience inthe specific case of perception) and adding fur- ther conditions toit. Only already factive states with the content that p can lead to knowledge that p;onlyalready factiveexperiences with the content that p can be abasis for the perceptual knowledge that p.9 It is beliefthat isto be explained onthe basis of the concept of knowl- edge,and not the other way around. Likewise, hallucinatory experi- ence is to be explicated on the basis of afactive concept of successful experience. Afundamental asymmetry should be recognized in the epistemic status of those experiences involved inperception vis-à-vis that of those involved in hallucination. The disjunctive conception of experience constitutes away ofcapturing this. The externalist form ofthe sense data theory recommended here isin harmony with this point; asprevious writers have noted, there are forms of disjunctivism compatible with the causal theory ofper- ception.10 What Ireject isthe strong externalism that distinguishes the theory of appearing, according towhich perceived objects them- selves individuate perceptual experiences. Onthe view of empirical

8.As Peacocke(1999, ch. 2) putsthe point,phenomenal features playa con- stitutive role in the individuationof observationalconcepts (those that figurein perceptualjudgments), and these are epistemically individuated concepts: “con- cepts …individuated,partly orwholly,in terms ofthe conditionsfor a thinker’s knowingcertain contents containingthose concepts.” 9.Williamson (1995)argues for this; see also McDowell(1995). 10.Child (1992,303) considers aviewlike the onedefended here. 25 judgments promoted here, it is only some material properties (to- gether with some previously encountered instances of them) that in- dividuate experiences, not the perceived concrete instances ofthose properties. 11 In any particular case of perception, the phenomenal features of perceptual experiences are tobe analyzed asindividuated independently of the perceived object. It is compatible with the na- ture ofthe particular experience as such that it might have been hal- lucinatory; itis because it has been caused by the perceived object that itisnot hallucinatory.However, this does not mean that percep- tual knowledge is tobe understood as involving astate individuated without any commitments concerning external objects, plus concep- tually contingent causal relations with external objects. Tosatisfy the requirements ofthe causal theory,any particular perception will be understood toinvolve experiences individuated without the aid of the perceived objects. But Iwill also claim that the perceptual expe- rience in any such particular case of perception is in its nature one such that experiences of the same kind are instantiated in cases of perceptual knowledge. 12 The concept of experience cannot be expli- cated without the notion ofexperiences that are (primitively) cases of knowledge.

2. ASellarsian Third Way

Having presented TA,inthis section Iwill introduce the other main contender as aphilosophical account of perceptual experience: (reductive) representationalism. Iwill discuss Sellars’(1963a) views on perception, because the sense data theory that Iwill present in the following section incorporates some of his insights. This is the way Sellars describes the three kinds ofcases that any philosophical account ofperception should consider ( op. cit., 151-

11.I amaiming hereat distinction whichhas links with McGinn’s (1989)be- tweenstrong and weak externalism. Burge’s views onthese issues havealso been most influential onme; see, forinstance, his (1977). 12.More precisely ,onesuch that experiences ofrelated kinds are instantiated in cases ofperceptual knowledge. This is requiredto givecontent to phenomenal features to whichno actually instantiated material propertycorresponds – like Hume’s missing shadeof blue. 26

2): (a) seeing that O,over there, isred (a claim made in cases one considers veridical); (b) its looking to S that O,over there, is red (a claim made in cases one has reasons toconsider misperceptions), and (c) itslooking toone as though there were ared object over there (a claim made in cases one has reasons to consider hallucinatory). According toSellars, in all these cases there isacommon proposi- tional content, concerning the instantiation of an observable prop- erty by the scene before the eyes. This common propositional con- tent is endorsed with different forces inthe three cases: it isfully en- dorsed in the veridical case, partially inthe misperception case (only the presence of O isendorsed there) and not at all inthe hallucina- tory case. As Iinterpret him, Sellars shares with sense data theorists the anti-disjunctivist contention that, as he puts it, in addition to the common propositional content there isin these three cases afurther commonality,acommon descriptive content. This content is charac- terized bythe fact that its instances (in contrast with the instances of the observable properties) can never bemerely intentional, but are real constituents ofthe actual world. For the sense data theorist, itis ared sense datum being experienced inthe three cases; for Sellars, it isa brain state, to be fully characterized byfuture neuroscience. I will borrow at this point adevice introduced by Peacocke (1983) ina related context. The device consists in writing predicates signifying observable properties with primes when they are used to refer to those “descriptive contents”of experiences. Iwill say that the de- scriptive commonality that Sellars talks about consists in the fact that in all three ascriptions (a)-(c), in addition tothe common repre- sentational content, the instantiation in the experience of acommon sensuous feature red’ is presuppositionally involved. By resorting to Peacocke’s primed predicates, Ileave open whether the redness actually instantiated inthe three cases (a)-(c) is the very same property asthe redness whose instantiation by the ma- terial scene before the eyes isin question. Some sense data theorists, including Jackson, believe them tobe the same; Idisagree, for rea- sons to be given shortly.Iwill refer tothe properties signified by primed predicates as primed properties ;taking them to be constitu- tive of phenomenal properties would beg the main issue at stake against the other theorist. AsSellars correctly indicates, the com- 27 mon descriptive character red’ is intrinsic –or, atleast, less extrinsic than the phenomenal features involved inperception according to TA.13 It isintrinsic in that particular instances of red’exist independ- ently ofthe existence of arelated instance of the corresponding ma- terial property,or any other similar property.This is of course re- quired by the claim that the primed properties are the same also when they occur in hallucinations. Thus, instances of red’ are not re- lational inthe strict sense that phenomenal qualities are relational according tothe theory of appearing. Thanks to this non-relational- ity,primed properties can be properly mentioned ina causal account of how perception occurs in the veridical case and in mispercep- tions. The representationalist “third way”between the sense data view and TAshares with sense data accounts the claim that there is, ana- lytically,acommon factor toall three cases (a)-(c), which isto be in- voked in acausal analysis ofperception. There isa constitutive rela- tion between the meanings of ‘red’and ‘square’on the one hand, and those of ‘looks red’and ‘looks square’on the other, in virtue of which the latter predicates do not signify primitive or unanalyzable relations, but are definable partly in terms ofthe former. The third way disagrees with sense data accounts, however, in taking the phe- nomenal common factor to(a)-(c) relevant for aphilosophical expli- cation ofperceptual experience tobeanintentional instantiation of an observable property of material objects. According to this third way,that common factor isfully specifiable in terms of the redness of material things, the beliefs ofsubjects about itsinstantiation in certain circumstances, and the actions these beliefs dispose them to perform. Given the existence of this analysis, in any given experi- ence the instance of the relevant phenomenal property (identical with an observable property) might beamerely intentional object if the experience is hallucinatory.Thus, this view isreductivist about qualia,inthat ittakes them to be fully characterizable in causal-ex- planatory terms. Now,while sense data theorists might agree with the third way that looks F isdefinable interms of F and a common factor along the suggested lines, they disagree with the third way on the issue whether the common factor itself can be so reductively un-

13.See Langton& Lewis (1998),for a useful explication of intrinsicness . 28 derstood. Although for sense data theorists qualia constitutively in- volve the observable features of material things, they cannot be reductively analyzed in terms ofthem; for qualia are also consti- tuted, irreducibly,by the sensuous primed properties. The descriptive primed properties posited by Sellars are not rela- tional in the strict sense inwhich phenomenal properties are rela- tional according tothe theory of appearing, butthey are relational in aless demanding sense on hisaccount. On Sellars’view a red’ sen- sation isone typically caused in normal subjects byred objects in normal circumstances, which then typically causes inproperly equipped subjects who think that the circumstances are normal for perception the judgment that something red is instantiated by the scene before their eyes. The subjects then count thereby as perceiv- ing ared expanse, if they infact know that circumstances are ade- quate for perception. Sellars thought that sensations instantiate ana- logues of the observable properties causing them. He writes that “the essential feature of the analogy is that visual impressions stand to one another in asystem of ways of resembling and differing which is structurally similar tothe ways inwhich the colors and shapes of visible objects resemble and differ”( op. cit.,193). Wecould make the point by resorting tothe previous indication that qualia belong in aqualitative space. Both the manifest properties ofmaterial things that figure in the propositional content of ‘looks’talk, and the primed properties of appearances whose instantiation we presup- pose in that talk, belong instructurally isomorphic qualitative spaces: one space for the manifest properties of ordinary material objects, another for the primed properties. 14 Because the relational properties determining those spaces are an integral part ofour con- ception of both manifest and sensational properties, it is analogi- cally correct touse the same predicates for both. This usage is nevertheless merely analogical. There ismore to a primed property than its position in qualitative space, among other

14.See Mulligan (1995).While the relations determiningthe spaces might bethe same insome cases –forinstance inthe case ofspatio-temporal properties andtheir primedcorrelates –theymight notbeexactly the same, butonly struc- turally related in others.A case in pointis the relations ofintensity forsounds, vis-à-vis the correspondingrelation ofdegreesof loudnessfor their phenomenal correlates, whichdiffer in significant respects. 29 things because it is conceptually possible that the relevant qualita- tive space has atleast two different points holding the same patterns of relations to other pointsin the space. An automorphism (a one-to-one function) other than the identity relation could be de- fined from the set ofpoints constituting the space onto itself, pre- serving the relations that define the space. There would then be at least two different points inthe space (two different primed proper- ties) standing inthe same relations to other points. 15 For Sellars, the specific character identifying primed properties over and above their position inqualitative space isa neurological property.For the sense data theorist, itisan irreducible experiential character (which, Isubmit, might be identified aposteriori with aneurological prop- erty). Similarly,there is more to the manifest properties than their position in their ownqualitative space. Manifest properties are ana- lytically said to cause sensations with corresponding primed proper- ties innormal circumstances. They must have some specific cate- gorical nature over and above their position inqualitative space to have this causal efficacy,which there is no reason tothink will coin- cide with the categorical nature of the primed properties caused by them.16 Thus, on Sellars’account primed properties are not relational in the demanding sense required by the theory of appearing; but they are relational on two less demanding counts. First, there are causal relations holding innormal circumstances between instances of ob-

15.Aiming to promote a reductivefunctionalist analysis, Clark (1993, 178-184)defines individualqualia exclusively bytheir relations inqualitative space to otherqualia. The considerations in the text showthat Clark’s proposal fails asananalysis. Inresponseto this problem(see pp.203-205),Clark seems to beprepared to accept “definitions”which do not determine uniquereferents across the relevant set ofpossible circumstances. Ifindthis unacceptable.The correct alternative is toinclude, as anadditional part ofthe definition,something overand abovethe structural aspects; something,as Clark envisages,indexically introduced.(Paradigm cases ofprimed properties, introduced directly by ostension asinLoar’ s (1997)theory of phenomenalconcepts, or indirectly by ostension ofcorrespondingmaterial properties.)Perhaps this is, after all, whathe himself wouldsuggest. 16.I departhere from Jackson, who claims (1977,74-81 and 103)that mani- fest properties are predicatedin the same univocalsense ofmaterial things and sense data. 30 servable properties and them, and between them and instances of mental states. Invirtue ofthese relations, primed properties essen- tially contribute to the fact that the experiences in which they are instantiated have intentional contents of afunctional-cum-teleologi- cal character.Second, primed properties are essentially inaqualita- tive space determined by their relations toother primed properties. The two relational aspects are related. Orderly variations of observ- able properties along the dimensions in their qualitative space would give rise, in normal circumstances, to sensations whose primed properties vary along corresponding dimensions in their corre- sponding qualitative space. They in turn would give rise, in the ap- propriate conditions, to judgments with correspondingly varying contents, thus tobeliefs and, in the presence of the relevant desires, to action. Now,the sense data theory that Iwill advance takes phe- nomenal features to beconstituted by sensuous primed properties, understood as Sellars suggests. Inorder to distinguish the demand- ing relationality attributed to phenomenal features in TAfrom the less demanding one present inSellars’ views on primed properties, I will say that on such aview phenomenal features are ta-intrinsic. They are not absolutely intrinsic, because of the two relational as- pects we have emphasized; but they do not have the demanding relationality attributed to them in TA. If atheorist merely ascribes acausal-explanatory role toprimed properties of experiences, there is no incompatibility with TA’s disjunctivism (its opposition to a“highest common factor”) result- ing from the fact that primed properties are TA-intrinsic. TAis aphil- osophical explication of experiences, as mental states operating at the personal level –atthe level at which reflective folk-psychologi- cal rationalizing explications (aided by philosophical theorizing) are provided. The fact that a“highest common factor”to veridical perception, misperception and hallucination isposited at asubper- sonal, merely causal-explanatory level, does not contradict the main claims ofthe theorists we are discussing (as, for instance, Snowdon (1990) rightly emphasizes). If we took phenomenal features to be constituted by primed properties, aspart ofour philosophical expli- cation, we would bein fact rejecting the distinguishing tenet of the theory of appearing. But that would not follow if wethought of this identification as only required on the basis of aposteriori ,scientific 31 considerations. Sellars’views stand in contrast toTA,but not onac- count of his positing sensuous properties. This, by itself, is not in- compatible with the theory of appearing, inview of Sellars’insis- tence that sensations (instances ofprimed properties) have only a place “inthe logical space of an ideal scientific picture of the world” (op. cit.,153). What separates Sellars from TAishis identification of phenomenal properties with the intentional contents of experiences, which, aswe have seen, already provides for acommon factor to cases (a)-(c), thus avoiding the radical disjunctivism distinguishing TAand the associated difficulties (to be developed in section fourth). Sellars’account of perceptual experiences does feature common- alities inprimed properties, however, inaddition to intentional ones. Wemove inthe direction of asense data theory if we also acknowl- edge Sellars’sensuous properties in our philosophical explication of appearances. After all, the claims made so far about primed proper- ties do not rest for their justification on any empirical claim –on any claim whose we know through perception –more than any philosophical proposal does. They are based on considerations re- garding the commitments we incur in making perceptual ascrip- tions, relative to intuitions concerning clearly possible circum- stances inwhich weincur them; inparticular, those sharing the com- monalities and differing inthe ways highlighted by Sellars’cases (a)-(c).17 It might be objected that itisessential toSellars’ view that itis in- tended to be corroborated by empirical (say,neurological) findings. Sellars correctly insists that anexpression signifying aprimed qual- ity should be“truly aname, and not just shorthand for adefinite de-

17.It is true that wetake ourselves to knowthat these represent clear-cut pos- sibilities forpotential perceptualascriptions onthe basis ofourpreviouspercep- tual experience;but we shouldnot confuseclaims whichdepend for their justifi- cation onperception,from claims whichdepend on perceptionin otherways. Onlythe formerdependence undoubtedly makes aclaim aposteriori. Recent dis- cussions ofa priori knowledgeinsist onthis distinction; see Bonjour(1998), Burge(1993) and Peacocke(1993). Snowdon (1990) evinces the confusionI am criticizing. Thediscussions ofapriori knowledgejust referredto also showdue sensitivity to the grainof truth in Quineanqualms, which is acknowledgedbe - low. 32 scription”( op. cit.,§24; see also §61, (2), inconnection with the discussion in §§51-55). The view here is, Ithink (to put it in Kripkean terms), that aprimed predicate isnot synonymous with a constructed on the basis of its functional role –the de- scription merely fixes its reference .The term is to all effects an atomic one, denoting (to the extent that the theory introducing itis true) the categorical basis of the functional state, as itmight some day come to be properly identified, in more direct ways, by using terms ofneurological theories. However, this only shows that claims justified on the basis of non-empirical considerations (and concepts introduced relative tothose claims) might also later receive empiri- cal justifications. 18 It also shows, correspondingly,that claims that are thought to bejustified on the basis of non-empirical consider- ations, might inprinciple later be rejected onthe basis of empirical . Both facts manifest that certain traditional conceptions of philosophical knowledge are incorrect –which isthe grain of truth in the Quinean qualms on the apriori. However, more sophisticated conceptions are possible, compatible with the facts. Bymoving from Sellars’views toasense-data account, more- over, we escape awell-known criticism that isotherwise well-taken. When Sellars examines in Science and (1969, ch. 1) the issues whose treatment in “ and the Philosophy ofMind” Ihave been discussing, he applies the term ‘non-conceptual’to sen- sations. He isthus indicating that sensations are introduced merely to explain causally the commonalities to cases of veridical, illusory and hallucinatory experience. 19 Sensations would have a non-con-

18.I say ‘non-empirical’instead ofplainly ‘apriori’because some philoso- pherswould balk at countingas apriori ajustification that involvespropositions concerningmatters ofparticular fact, evenif these matters arenotknownpercep- tually butintrospectively. 19.However, while playingthis explanatorytask sensations also playfor Sellars anepistemological role: their existence accountsfor the “receptivity”of perception– forageneraldependence of perceptualbelief onthe character ofthe external world– whichthe mythof the Givenwas wronglyintended to account for.McDowell (1998, first lecture) sees adifferencein Sellars’presentation of his views onthis matter in chapter1 of Scienceand Metaphysics with respect to those headvancesin “Empiricism andthe Philosophyof Mind”which I am un- able to discern.As far asIcansee, sensations are also introducedin this workto 33 ceptual content in that they play acontent-involving explanatory role merely atthe subpersonal level ofthe information-processing states posited by cognitive scientists; they do not belong in the per- sonal-level “logical space of reasons.”Thus understood, the fact that they have propositional content (correctness conditions, which we might present in terms, say,ofpossible circumstances compatible with their veridicality) 20 isnot sufficient togivethem arationalizing role. In order to have arationalizing role, their subjects should meet aquite demanding condition, which McDowell characterizes thus: “itisessential toconceptual capacities, inthe demanding sense, that they can be exploited inactive thinking, thinking that isopen tore- flection about itsown rational credentials”(1994, 47; see also pp. 10-13). ByMcDowell’ s lights, to enjoy contentful states positioned “inthe logical space of reasons”entails having the capacity to reflect about the epistemic status of those states. For him, perceptual expe- riences are capable of offering justification and have “conceptual content”; but only subjects having general views about conditions in which they can trust their senses, and ingeneral the “rational creden- tials”of their thoughts, can enjoy them. This threatens an obvious regress, which Sellars confronted in this way: “all that the view that Iam defending requires isthat no tokening by S now of ‘this isgreen’is to count as ‘expressing obser- vational knowledge’unless itis also correct to say of Sthat he now knows the appropriate fact ofthe form Xisareliable symptom of Y , namely that …utterances of ‘This isgreen’ are reliable indicators of the presence ofgreen objects in standard conditions ofperception. And while the correctness of this statement about Jones requires that Jones could now cite prior particular facts as evidence for the idea that these utterances are reliable indicators, it requires only that itis correct to say that Jones now knows, thus remembers [fn: My thought was that one can have direct (non-inferential) knowledge of apast fact which one did not or even (as inthe case envisaged) could not conceptualize at the time itwas present.] that these particular properlyaccount for the dependenceof oursystem ofknowledgeon the external world. 20.Most properly,in terms closer toPeacocke’ s (1992,ch. 3)“scenario con- tent”. 34 facts did obtain. It does not require that itbe correct tosay that at the time these facts did obtain he then knew them to obtain. And the re- gress disappears”(Sellars 1963a, §37, 169). AsBrewer (1996) aptly indicates, what Sellars’argument tore- ject the regress requires isnot quite the possibility that he suggests in the quoted footnote. If those past events that the subject did not at the time conceptualize had been cognitively present tohim, and the sub- ject had kept memory of them, hemight justificatorily invoke them later, when he is in aposition to apply the required concepts. Sup- pose that S has been seeing for some time alight turned on inhis car, without knowing that the event indicates that the car isrunning out of gasoline –Smight even lack the very concept ofaninstrument whose function itis toindicate such athing. Suppose that hehas no- ticed that, more orless coincidentally with the light going on, the en- gine makes apeculiar sound. When he becomes knowledgeable about the function ofthe light, he might also come toknow of areli- able correlation between the noise and the car running out ofgaso- line. This is made possible by the fact that the subject is able to cognitively register the fact, even though helacks the concept of the indicator.Sellars’suggestions, however, require something much more difficult tounderstand, if we assume that the ‘non-conceptual’ character of the primed properties implies that their subject lacks cognitive access to them. It requires that something like that ispossi- ble “even if there isno sense whatsoever in which such afact was ac- tually present tothe subject at the earlier time”(Brewer 1996, 265). This isdifficult toaccept: “my memory at some time t1 of what was the case atan earlier time t0 radically depends on myconceptual so- phistication at t1 inthe following sense. Imight have known abso- lutely nothing at t 0, about the way things then were in the world around me, or indeed about anything else; yet Imight at t1 directly (non-inferentially) remember that there was agreen object infront of me at t0” (ibid.). The sense data theorist has amore satisfactory way around this is- sue. Because hefinds the common descriptive factor atthe proper personal level ofrationalizing explanation, he can appeal toSellars’ suggestion to avoid the regress, without falling prey to Brewer’s ob- jection. According to him, experiences have primed properties that (i) are common to the likes of cases (a)-(c), (ii) are analogous to 35 manifest properties of perceptible material beings inthe way sug- gested bySellars, and (iii) have contents derived from the instan- tiation of those manifest properties innormal circumstances also in the way suggested bySellars. Sense data theorists classify the con- tents of experiences asnon-conceptual toindicate that they can be shared by discursive adult humans, capable of playing the lan- guage-game ofjustifying their claims, and byanimals and children who lack that capability.This notwithstanding, experiences so con- ceived are postulated at afirst-personal level: they are capable of playing arationalizing, justificatory role. They are notmerely posits of the empirical theories ofcognitive scientist, which only relative to purely reliabilist accounts of knowledge could bethought toplay a justificatory role. Experiences asunderstood inthe sense data ac- count are posits ofapersonal-level explication of perception, play- ing afully-fledged epistemic role inordinary folk-psychological ra- tionalizing explanations. This does not require counting the relation between sense-experiences and ordinary perceptual judgments as strictly speaking inferential. AsBroad said: “Perceptual judgments are indeed based upon sensa and their properties to the extent that if we were not aware of asensum we should not now judge that any physical object is present to our senses, and that ifthis sensum had different properties we should ascribe different properties to the physical object. But the relation between the sensum and its proper- ties, onthe one hand, and the perceptual judgment about the physical object, on the other, isnot that of inference”(Broad, 1965, 96). Broad’s point here isnot that the relation ismerely causal. He goes onto offer awell-known analogy. 21 Sensa stand to the percep- tual objects weaccess by means of them aswords stand to the ob- jects words tell usabout: while reading, wefocus onthe meaning, not the words; typically wewould be able to report the content of a message at alater time, but not the words in which it was expressed. But we could not have accessed the meanings without accessing the words. Similarly,we could not have knowledge of observable prop- erties of material objects without being aware of the relevant proper- ties ofour sense impressions. This awareness plays arationalizing and justificatory role infolk-psychological, personal-level explana-

21.Kevin Mulligan informedme that the analogycomes fromHusserl. 36 tions.22 The Sellarsian third way we have been discussing has inits favor that itis astraightforward naturalistic proposal, while sense data theories are at the very least not obviously so. Alas, in spite of this strength, like any other similarly reductive theory 23 the Sellarsian third way cannot be right. In addition to the epistemological consid- erations that Ihave just marshaled against it, Ihave only space to mention the two main problems with reductive accounts, well elabo- rated inthe literature. The first comes from inverted spectrum con- siderations. Thought-experiments like those by Block (1990), Peacocke (1983) and Shoemaker (1984) show that there are concep- tual possibilities which areductive analysis cannot recognize. Some reductive theorists advance their proposals in aframework in which conceptual and empirical claims are not separated. Astrategy avail- able tothem isto suggest that so-called cases ofinverted qualia al- ways involve, asamatter of empirical fact, functional differences hidden from common sense. Ido notthink this helps reductivism in general, inpart because Ithink that the presupposed Quinean frame- work is wrong; our discussion assumes an epistemological distinc- tion between conceptual anempirical claims. The second difficulty for reductivism comes from the problem ofdistinguishing primary from secondary qualities. Areductive account would have tocount all observable properties asequally objective. Inmy view,however, there are very good reasons for aresponse-dependent treatment of some manifest properties, most prominently colors. 24

22.The viewhas points ofcontact with the oneadvanced by Searle (1983). Theform of externalism defendedbelow distinguish es it fromSearle’ s. García-Carpintero (1999) discusses the relations betweenSearle’ s views and sense data theories. 23.Representationalist theories of qualia close tothe Sellarsian third way havebeen advocated by Dretske (1995),Harman (1989), and Tye (1995). 24.Johnston (1992) offers some ofthese reasons.I shouldsay that Johnston haschangedhis views here,as is coherentwith his adoptionof the theoryof ap- pearing.See Johnston1998, for his newreasons against the response-depend- enceof manifest properties.The twoproblems I havementionedare discussed by Jackson(1977, 33-48). The need for reductivists to assume anobjectivist ac- countof all properties configuringthe immediately perceptible material world (including,for instance, painfulbodily conditions perceived in feeling pains), 37

3. Outline of aSense data Theory

In this section Iwill present the main features of asense data theory and acausal account of perception involvingsense data. It offers in my view the best explication of perception, in view ofthe difficulties for representationalism we have just mentioned, and those of TA that will be developed inthe nextsection. Space only allows the bar- est sketch,but Ihope itwill be sufficient to show at least that the view is not obviously wrong. Our favored analysis for Sperceives O will include the following claims:25

(i) The experience E constitutively involved when subject S perceives object O consists of arelation of awareness be- tween subject S and an(event-like) object, s-d(E),consisting of the instantiation ofacomplex ofphenomenal properties in anegocentric spatio-temporally structured array.

This first claim, by itself, does not go far beyond what was taken as common ground in the first section. If each particular phenomenal feature instantiated in s-d(E) consists in aprimitive relation ofap- pearance with O,or if itcan be reductively analyzed by means of physicaland/ or functional properties involvingO, then s-d(E) would not be asense datum in any problematic sense ofthat notion. (The term ‘sense datum’is introduced in classical discussions with the same lack ofcommitment towhether itsreferents are essentially ex- periential relations with features of material things, or rather intrin- sically mental, that we used in introducing ‘phenomenal feature’ earlier; see Moore, 1918-9, as an example of this.) The main point of andthe implausibility ofdoingso, constitutes the main bodyofthe detailed argu- ment byPerkins (1983)for sense data.Jackson also mentions these difficulties. Insum, the conditionsmentioned in reductiveanalyses (causation undernormal circumstances ofthe phenomenalfeatures bythe observationalproperties, belief that the observationalproperties are instantiated, orboth)are not sufficient for the truth of“ phenomenal-look”ascriptions. Nevertheless, Ibelieve,against Jackson,that bothsorts ofconditionsare necessary. 25.Although the points Iwill bediscussing are intendedto applyto percep- tual claims generally,I will mostly concentrateon vision. 38 mentioning events in (i) is, firstly,toallocate sense data to what I take to betheir proper ontological slot. Sense data are particulars, granted, butevent- or state-like; they are not particulars that endure through time, but particulars that stretch through time as enduring things extend in space. In addition to this, (i) puts the present view in opposition to the adverbial analysis ofexperience –atypical logical device inthe ar- mory of defenders ofthe theory ofappearing. Adverbial analyses are an attempt at getting rid of any objects susceptible of having properties like those ascribed by means ofobservational predicates, ‘red’, ‘cube’, ‘solid’, etc, other than the perceived material objects. In order toavoid the commitment of sense data theories tomental objects to which primed analogues of those predicates are properly applied, adverbialists suggest that wethink of experience as a deter- minable for atype of state. Determinates for this determinable are obtained byusing the observational predicates, semantically speak- ing, like adverbial modifiers. Thus, when S experiences ahallucina- tory red after-image, the determinable ‘experiencing’applies to S adverbially modified with ‘redly’: S isexperiencing red-ly.No red object of S’sexperience has toexist; it isonly that the more determi- nate property, experiencing red-ly applies to S’scondition. 26 Jackson (1977, 58-72) submits adverbial analyses toathorough criticism, to which Idonot think their proponents have acceptable replies. Jackson’s criticism isbased on two related objections, the “many-property”objection and the “complement”objection. The first is the problem for the adverbialist todistinguish, say,experienc- ing the appearance of ared square besides agreen circle, from expe- riencing the appearance of agreen circle besides ared square. Adverbialism threatens toconflate them into something like experi- encing red-ly,circular-ly,green-ly and square-ly .The second isthe problem for the adverbialist to avoidabsurdly concluding, from the fact that Sexperiences ared appearance and agreen, i.e., non-red ap- pearance, that Sis atthe same time both experiencing and not expe- riencing (“red-ly”). Tye(1984; the main claims are still endorsed in his 1995) con-

26.Adverbial analyses havebeen proposed, among others, by Chisholm (1957,115-25), Sellars (1963b)and Tye (1984). 39 fronts Jackson’s objections. It does not distort matters to present his proposal in two stages. Tye first introduces aphenomenal spatio- temporally structured visual field, and two relations of “coinci- dence”and “separation”of phenomenal qualities in the apparent spatiotemporal structure. (Togeneralize the solution, we should contemplate experiential fields with perhaps spatial and always tem- poral apparent structures.) 27 The first step to deal with the many- property problem isthen todescribe matters thus: it isfor the subject as if redness coincided with squareness and greenness with circular- ity in his visual field. Todeal with the complement problem: itisfor the subject as if there were redness separated from greenness in his visual field. If the maneuver ended here, it would achieve nothing for the adverbialist. For positing concrete instances of merely apparent sen- sory fields, with richly structured spatio-temporal-like parts deter- mined by analogues of the observable properties, is precisely the move made bythe sense data theorist whose views the adverbialist ultimately wants to oppose. Tye’s second step is therefore crucial for the success of his adverbialist proposal. The second step is a reductive analysis ofascriptions of appearances as of spatio-tempo- rally structured sensory fields: “The operation ofcoincidence itself, therefore, may be thought of as mapping any two given sensory modes or functions F-ly and G-ly onto afunction which, in turn, maps the property ofsensing onto afurther sensing property which isusually instantiated in normal perceivers by virtue of their view- ing aphysical object, which is both F and G,in standard circum- stances”(T ye 1984, 218; analogous claims are made about the oper- ation of separation on p. 222). In sum, sensing coincidental- with(red-ly,square-ly)-ly isintended tobe reductively analyzed as being inastate typically caused in normal observers under normal

27.Tye restricts his discussion to the visual field, andthen only to versions of Jackson’s problemsarising fromits spatial structure. But,of course,the visual field has also atemporal structure (there is also apparentmovement), and most sensoryfields haveonly temporal structure. Jackson’s problemscan be trivially restated onthe basis ofthe temporal structures ofappearance.Sensing a violin middle Csucceededby acello Acannotbe conflatedwith sensing acello middle Csucceededby aviolinA, asunmodifiedadverbialism wouldentail, norlead us to concludethat the subject is bothsensing andnot sensing (“cellish-ly”). 40 circumstances by something which is both red and square . Asfar as Ican see, this proposal requires that reductive analyses be forthcoming for all phenomenal features in terms ofcorrespond- ing immediately perceptible properties ofmaterial things: not only of (primed) spatio-temporal phenomenal features, butalso ofany other phenomenal features without which the spatio-temporal fea- tures cannot becharacterized. Perceiving acomplex of sounds has a temporal dimension; the same applies toperceiving acomplex pain- ful condition of one’s ownbody .This temporally felt structure gives rise to counterparts of the two problems for adverbial accounts pre- sented by Jackson. Now,for asolution along the lines of Tye’s to work, areduction ought to be available not only ofthe temporal ex- perienced features interms oftemporal properties ofmaterial events perceptually accessed incanonical circumstances. Areduction must also be possible of the, respectively,specifically sonorous and “paining”properties which in each particular case, asitwere, “fill up”that temporal structure. Like any other reductive analysis of the phenomenal qualities, this will not do, essentially for the two rea- sons indicated atthe end of section 3. Inparticular, while the first re- duction –the one for primary properties –sounds feasible, Ithink we should discard the possibility ofthe second one, without which the first does not suffice. Arguments making this clear include those given byAkins (1996) for the “narcissistic”character of some phenomenal features. The main difficulty she raises has the following form. She starts from a class of properties reasonably counted as objective; for instance, temperatures, as classified and measured by physicists. Then she shows that the system ofthermal sensations in humans cannot be taken to represent properties inthe presupposed class (see particu- larly her arguments against the “appeal to signal information”, pp. 356-359). Two different temperatures can give rise to the same sen- sation, and the same temperatures can give rise todifferent sensa- tions indifferent parts of the skin. In addition tothis, the structure of temperatures and the structure of thermal sensations differ also in that changes of temperature ofthe same amount are felt as differing in intensity,depending onthe initial temperature. These disparities, moreover, reflect the specific interest of the organism incorporating the representational system. Facts like these are not specific to the 41 thermal receptors; wecould find them for most sensory systems (in- cluding some representing “primary”properties like spatial posi- tions, see the example ofthe sense of balance onp.369). 28 In view of problems like these, Tye should tell us how he expects to be able to reduce, say,feelings oftemperature to physical conditions.

(ii) The object s-d(E) is the immediate object ofthe perceptual state.

As before with (i), (ii) per se isnotincompatible with the claims dis- tinguishing the theory of appearing. Any account of perception will require adistinction between mediate, orindirect, and immediate, or direct, objects of the conscious awareness involved in perception. Instances of phenomenal properties may be taken tobe the immedi- ate objects ofawareness in perception even by the supporter of the theory of appearing, because for him the only particulars involved are the perceived instances of material manifest properties. The way ofdescribing the mediate/immediate distinction men- tioned here may sound slightly strained. Amore straightforward for- mulation would simply distinguish mediate from immediate objects of perception, instead of the conscious awareness involved in per- ception.IfInonetheless avoid the more straightforward formulation it is because Idonot think itproper tocount the immediate objects of perception –mental sense data onthe present view –as themselves perceived; this isone point atwhich Idepart from Jackson. In are- cent penetrating discussion, Shoemaker (1994) has given good rea-

28.See in additionthe argumentsby Perkins (1983),already mentioned in this connection.I shouldsay that, while Itake these considerations to put reductivist accountsin jeopardy,against Akins’own conclusion they do notseem to meto affect aviewsuch as the oneIamdeveloping.The obvious reaction to Akins’examples is to take the properties representedby qualia to becharacter- ized essentially in relation to qualia themselves (to be“narcissistic properties”, in herterms), andto accept that herexamples showthat those properties cannot beidentified with physical properties.There is nometaphysical problemwith this, becauseany sensible physicalism shouldbe understoodas arequirementof ,not one of reduction;and, as Akinsacknowledges, the facts she mentions are compatible with the requireddependence of narcissistic properties onphysical properties. 42 sons not to count introspective access to our own occurrent mental states asaform ofperception; and, by my own lights, experiencing sense data counts as such. Shoemaker’s considerations are much richer, butfor present purposes wecan reduce them tothe following point. Perception isacognitive achievement; inany particular case, the actual achievement could have turned out tobeinstead an unsuc- cessful attempt at cognitively accessing the perceived object. This is not the case for experience and its phenomenal objects. In the first place, attention is enough to experience concrete sense data; addi- tionally,experiencing sense data guarantees their existence. 29 In the second place, in experiencing sense data we cannot be grossly mis- taken about their character.(This iscompatible with alimited ad- mission ofcorrigibility.)Given these differences, itwould be wrong to count introspective access to phenomenal features asaform of perception. Iassume that claims such asthe following will not bedisputed: When we see both Venus and abright speck of light inthe nightly sky,we see Venus in virtue of seeing abright speck of light. When we see both the orange and an orange spherical shape of such-and- such size, wesee the former invirtue of seeing the latter. Jackson of- fers an in myview insufficient elaboration onthis relation of per- ceiving something in virtue of perceiving some related thing . He then goes ontoexplain the idea of immediacy byappealing to it. A mediate object of perception isone perceived at atime invirtue of perceiving at that very time adifferent, related object; and immedi- ate object of perception is aperceived object which is not mediate (see Jackson 1977, 15-22 for this explication). In his explication of the “in virtue of”relation, Jackson stead- fastly refuses to invoke epistemic notions traditionally appealed to in the account ofthe immediacy at stake. This iswhy Isay that his explication isinsufficient; for, although Itake itto be correct, as far as it goes, Ithink that itrequires further elucidation. Jackson’s ab- stract explication provides only anecessary butinsufficient elabora- tion of the “invirtue of”relation holding inour case. The additional

29.Adverbialism ofcourseprovides a nice explanationfor this; in rejecting adverbialism, weare forcedto providea different accountfor the fact. This will notbe attempted here. 43 material is ofanepistemic character.Traditionally ithas been said, for instance, that when something isseen in virtue of seeing some- thing else, the beliefs wehave about the former are inferred from those wehave about the latter; orthat we are less certain regarding the former beliefs than we are regarding the latter.Aspart of his re- fusal to invoke epistemic notions Jackson adopts the view,advo- cated by Dretske (1969), that what the latter calls “simple seeing” (seeing objects, including here events) is analytically more basic than what he calls “epistemic seeing”(seeing that afact obtains). Another integral part of Jackson’s refusal to use epistemic notions in the analysis of the immediacy at stake is his refusal (shared with many other contemporary philosophers, like Evans (1982), for simi- lar reasons) to count perceptual judgments as constitutively in- volved inperception. Aproper discussion of these issues is beyond the scope of this pa- per, but our limited aims do not require it. Let me just indicate the main points tobe developed ina fuller discussion. Firstly,the proper order of analysis isthe opposite to the one that Dretske and Jackson assume; simple seeing is to be explained in terms of epistemic see- ing, seeing that afact obtains. In basic cases, the fact involves the instantiation by the scene before the senses (asituation involvingre- lations with some egocentric condition of the perceiver’s body) ofan array structured temporally and perhaps also spatially of manifest properties. The basic idea for the explication of the simple percep- tion of objects and events in terms ofthe epistemic perception of that type offact is tothink ofsimple perception asaform of de re ascrip- tion. Iwould provide atreatment of de re ascriptions along the lines of the one given by Kaplan (1969) for de re belief reports, without assuming any other ontological category of beliefs than that re- quired to analyze de dicto reports.30 Thus, Sperceives O is to be un-

30.These proposals are sometimes understoodas attempts to reducesingu- lar thoughts,thoughts constitutively involvingparticulars, to purelygeneral de- scriptive thoughts.They do notneedto beunderstoodin that spirit, however,and theyare notso understoodhere. There are twoways in whichthe distinction de dicto/de re might beseen.According to the first interpretation, it is adistinction oftwokinds of thought-(and utterance-) content: singular orobject-dependent content(content essentially involvingparticulars) vs.general content. Accord- ingto the secondinterpretation, it is adistinction oftwokinds of content-ascrip- 44 derstood as condensing something like Sperceives that …?…,and the singular concept ?represents Ofor S .31 Secondly,as is the case in the analysis offered inthe Sellarsian third way,perception consti- tutively involves belief, i.e., perceptual ascriptions conceptually en- tail cæteris paribus belief ascriptions. The usual arguments (includingJackson’ s; op. cit.,38-42) against the view that judgment and belief are constitutively involved in the account of the nature of perceptual experience are based on cases of well-known illusions, like the Müller-L yer illusion; subjects famil- iar with itrefuse totake itat face value. Myreply tothis isbased on a broadly functionalist conception of the mind in general, and of per- ceptual experiences in particular.This functionalism is“ broad”in that it is not reductive; itacknowledges mental properties which, even though they necessarily play afunctional role, cannot beidenti- fied with functional properties as usually understood. Thus, the view is not that perceptual experiences are identical with beliefs, or that whenever they occur, necessarily ajudgement occurs, or that whenever aperceptual judgement occurs, ithas been tion.On the onehand, ascriptions whoseascriber commits himself in partasre- gardsthe natureof the modesof presentation in the ascribed content,but do not needto involveexistential commitments. Onthe other,ascriptions whose ascriber commits himself tothe existence ofentities whichhe refers to in orderto partially characterize the ascribed content,while hedoesnot need to commit himself to the modesof presentation relative to whichthe entity is presentedin the ascribed content.It is accordingto the first interpretation that aKaplanian proposalis intendedas areductionof singular contents to generalcontents. The interpretation favoredhere is the second,however. My ownview is that there are irreducible singular contents,including contents constituting the phenomenal character ofperceptualexperiences. 31.A viewof this kindcan be foundin RoxbeeCox (1971). An important differencebetween us is that RoxbeeCox is attempting toprovide a reductive analysis ofperceptionin terms ofthe causation ofbelief. Therefore,he avoids mentioningexperiences. Although, in contrast with Jackson,I believe that per- ceptionconstitutively involvesbelief (i.e.,perceptual ascriptions conceptually entail ceteris paribus belief ascriptions), contra RoxbeeCox and other philoso- phersI donotthink that perceptioncan be reducedto belief. Thatis to say,I do notthink that anybelief ascriptions notinvolving concealed appeal to experi- ences canbe sufficient forperceptual ascriptions, forreasons givenby Jackson (1977,42-48). 45 generated byacorresponding perceptual experience. Firstly,certain general conditions for judging should be in place for anexperience to generate acorresponding judgment. Judgment and belief are, I take it, conceptual affairs; tomake judgements requires the capacity to give reasons for them, and that means that the content of judg- ments and beliefs is conceptualized content. Attention tothe con- sciously experienced features is one more general condition re- quired for an experience to generate abelief. When S suddenly real- izes that there is– and has been for some time –adeafening pneu- matic drill digging up the street, previous to the realization he was already having the experience of the sound. He was not judging that there was that sound, though, because hewas not attending tothe rel- evant phenomenal features he was (inattentively) experiencing. 32 Consider now circumstances (knowledgeable subjects con- fronted with the Müller-L yer figure, say) inwhich aperceptual ex- perience does not give rise to the corresponding judgment. The broadly functional character of the proposal makes this compatible with the view that belief is constitutively involvedin experience. For, insuch cases, certain collateral information ispresent, invirtue of which the subject refrains from taking the experience at face value. Hence, default canonical cases are possible in which the col- lateral information isabsent, and inthose cases the subject would make the judgment. 33 Similarly,in some cases the perceptual belief can beformed without the causal operation ofthe perceptual experi- ence (say,areliable source informs the subject of the fact, while the subject would not have taken his experience at face value inthe cir-

32.The examplecomes fromBlock (1995, 234), andthe remarkon attention is intendedto refute Block’s claim that the exampleestablishes the possibility of aformof ,what he calls ‘phenomenalconsciousness’ , whichun- like whathe calls ‘access consciousness’does not havea functional/representa- tional nature.Block’ s claim is aformof the internalism aboutphenomenal fea- tures that Ireject here. 33.See also Mulligan (1999).In responseto this sort ofproposalJackson (1977,41) makes the boldempirical claim that evenin the default situation peo- ple wouldrefuse to take the appearanceprovoked by Müller-Lyer figures at face value,abstaining frommaking the correspondingjudgments. Our disagreement herecould in principle beresolvedon the basis ofthe results ofcarefully de- signedexperiments. 46 cumstances). But, again, these cases involve collateral information. Hence, there are possible canonical cases inwhich the collateral in- formation is absent, and in them the perceptual belief would begen- erated by the experience. In summary,aperceptual experience that p constitutively causes, cæteris paribus (relative to conditions existing in some canonical circumstances), aperceptual judgment with acorresponding con- tent, and rationalizes it. 34 The present view therefore contrasts both with Jackson’s views and with those ofthe classical sense data theo- rist. For them, at the basic level of analysis sense data are objects of states without propositional content. Ishould point out that this is the only sense data theorist whose views Sellars presents and aptly criticizes in the first section of “Empiricism and the ”. For the more sophisticated fellow whose views we are sup- porting here, experiences involving sense data are, atthe most basic level, propositional. 35 Toexplicate the distinction mediate/immediate only the percep- tion of facts istherefore relevant. Afact isperceived invirtue of per- ceiving (or being consciously aware of) another fact ifand only if the following two conditions obtain. Firstly, cæteris paribus (relative to canonical circumstances), asubject could not perceive the former without perceiving (or being consciously aware of) the latter. Sec- ondly,he could perceive (or be consciously aware of) the latter, without perceiving the former.On the present sense data theory,in- stances of the manifest properties (material properties placed in Sellars’qualitative space) are the objects we most directly perceive; but we indirectly perceive facts involving them, by being con- sciously aware of facts involving instances of sense data. 36 These re- marks do notadd uptoa fully-fledged definition ofthe intended me-

34.In speakingof “corresponding”content, I am skippingover thorny issues that havetodo with the alreadypointed out fact that the contentof perceptualex- periences is non-conceptual, while the contentof judgmentsbased on them is conceptualizedcontent. 35.For a state to bepropositional,in myview,is forthat state to havepossi- ble-worldtruth-conditions, as determinedby modesofpresentation.It is not,ob- viously,to haveconceptual content, or possible-world truth-conditions deter- minedby conceptualmodes of presentation. 36.See Perkins (1983,p. 16)for similar suggestions aboutimmediacy. 47 diation, nor to ajustification that applies to the cases atstake –which could only be given as aresult of amore elaborate discussion –but I hope that they are sufficiently indicative of the view.

(iii) The properties of s-d(E) (the sensuous sides of qualia) are correctly characterized by means ofpredicates for the corre- sponding manifest features of perceived objects (their inten- tional sides: shapes, colors, etc), this characterization being essentially analogical. Phenomenal properties have thus two aspects, sensuous and intentional.

This was explicated in the previous section, in connection with Sellars’views. The sense data theory Idefend uses exactly the same account that we have seen inSellars’proposal (involving the loca- tion of qualia inaqualitative space) according to which predicates for the manifest properties and their corresponding primed corre- lates attribute related properties. Hence, todistinguish the manifest properties Iwould appeal to Sellars’idea that there isa structural similarity between some prop- erties we perceive inmaterial things, and the sensuous sides ofphe- nomenal features. Wehave elucidated this structural similarity ear- lier byappealing tothe view that phenomenal properties constitute a qualitative space. The sense data account coincides thus with the Sellarsian third way in counting as essential features ofsensuous properties of experiences both the fact that they cause judgments in canonical circumstances, and that they are caused in canonical cir- cumstances by material properties corresponding tothem in ananal- ogous qualitative space. Itisthe second constitutive aspect that we need for the definition of the manifest properties: they are, by defini- tion, those constituting the space corresponding to the qualitative space in which sensuous sides ofphenomenal features are placed. Wewill also appeal to it below,to characterize the nature of the causal relation which causal theories of perception appeal to. The representationalist claim that ascriptions of phenomenal fea- tures constitutively entail stating that manifest proper- ties cause the corresponding primed properties under normal condi- tionsin normal circumstances isdisputed by Jackson ( op. cit., 35-39) on three counts. First, there is Hume’s notoriousmissing shade of 48 blue; that istosay,phenomenal features that are experienced, but have not been caused byany instance of the corresponding observ- able property.The account in terms ofqualitative spaces deals satis- factorily with this objection; the fact that the relations defining the phenomenal qualitative space are consciously experienced by sub- jects allows for extrapolation based on qualities whose instances have been involved in genuine cases of perception. Second, there is the problem of explaining “normal conditions”non-circularly; the adoption of ateleological explanation will deal with this difficulty. 37 Finally,Jackson points out well-known difficulties for counterfac - tual accounts provoked by“finkish”dispositions: “Consider aworld created by aCartesian evil demon who hates red things buttolerates non-red things looking red on odd occasions. Perhaps he has re- solved todestroy the world if any red things come into existence. In this world, things look red onodd occasions, but nothing looks the way red things would if there were any; for ifthere were any,nothing would look any way toanyone”( op. cit.,35). The reply to this is that, in contrast with reductive representationalist views, the present pro- posal is not to reduce categorical claims regarding the instantiation of sensuous properties to counterfactual claims involving potential instantiations of their material correlates, but only that the latter are constitutively entailed by the former.On the contrary,Itake the counterfactual claim entailed by an ascription of aprimed property tobe explainable relative to the categorical bases implicitly ascribed in the attribution, such as neurological properties with which sensu- ous properties can be identified aposteriori. 38 This second partial agreement with the Sellarsian third way is what the moderate externalism of the present sense data theory and its own form of disjunctivism –both mentioned at the end ofthe first section –comes to. Consider anascription of phenomenal character, it looks MtoS (where M is any manifest property). Under the present

37.See forinstance Millikan 1984,but disregardany suggestion of biologi- cal reductivism. 38.See Lewis (1997)for a generalaccount of finkish dispositions compati- ble with the sort ofnon-reductiveline takenhere for the examplementioned by Jackson.In this case, there are ofcoursein additionthe specific problemscon- cerningthe relation betweenphenomenal qualities andbrain states. Myline here wouldbe essentially that defendedby Loar(1997). 49 proposal, its truth-conditions incur ontological commitments. Firstly,to the existence ofan instance ofacorresponding sensuous property, M .Secondly,to the existence of canonical cases inwhich other instances of the same type are caused by instances of M. In contrast to TA,the analysis does not require the existence of an in- stance of M,perceived bymeans of the experienced instance of M . It thus overcomes the difficulties of TA,to be elaborated onin the next section. But the analysis does entail the existence of cases of M (or, at least, cases of other manifest properties in the space corre- sponding tothe qualitative one). As David Lewis puts it, according to the view,when philosophically explicated it turns out that “folk psychology includes folk psychophysics”(Lewis 1994, 416). This leaves open whether primed properties, intheir turn, have natures which can be fully analyzed interms of the manifest properties that cause them incanonical circumstances. Against the reductivism of the Sellarsian third way,the view defended here has itthat this can- not bedone, inview ofthe possibility (and, Iwould say,the actual existence) of secondary properties. Thus, while manifest primary properties are constitutively prior to their corresponding primed properties, manifest secondary properties and their corresponding primed properties are constitutively on the same level. Traditional sense data theories, like those weassociated with the British empiricists, are Cartesian. They take phenomenal features to be fully intrinsic properties, and represent perception as the result of arisky inference (in the ordinary case, ofcourse, one involving at least apremise constituting tacit knowledge). This isnot the case in the proposal advanced here. Against the extreme relationalism re- presented bythe theory of appearing, Ihave contended that aphilo- sophically correct analysis of perceptual experiences requires usto separate two sides of phenomenal features. On the one hand, the constitutively merely intentional instances of the material properties perceived invirtue of an awareness of them, and, on the other, the ac- tual instances ofcorresponding sensuous properties. As tradition- ally contended, this isneeded to account for the commonalities be- tween cases ofhallucination and the corresponding veridical cases. But the requirement can be met while essentially considering hallu- cinations asparasitic on veridical cases. It can be met while refusing to offer an analysis involving non-factive states common toveridical 50 cases and hallucinations. This is what the present externalism about phenomenal features suggests. It isimportant toemphasize this, because itis strict internalism about phenomenal features that isresponsible for what iscorrect in criticisms of some sense data accounts, beginning with the pri- vate-language considerations. Friends of the questionable form of disjunctivism associated with the theory ofappearing typically sad- dle their opponents with internalism. 39 Wehave seen that itisnot mandatory.It isalso relevant tomention that the best-known con- temporary proponent of the causal theory of perception, Grice, far from embracing internalism, endorsed amoderate view such as the one supported here. 40

(iv) If S perceives O,aspecific event concerning O, s(O) (a “manifest scene concerning O”) causes in S the perceptual

39.See, for instance, Snowdon1990, pp. 128 and 125, and Hyman 1992, p. 283. 40.A longquotationmight perhapsbe justified: “(1)… it is quite incorrect to describe manyof myperceptualbeliefs …as“inferences”of anykind, if this is to betakento imply that it wouldbe incumbentupon me, on demand,to justify by anargument … the contentionthat whatappears to me to bethe case actually is the case …(2)Theallegedly ‘fundamental’case …inwhich a perceptualclaim is to beestablishable purelyon the basis ofsome set ofsense datumstatements, is amyth; anyjustification ofaparticular perceptualclaim will rely onthe truth of oneormorefurtherpropositions about the material world… (3)It might beques- tionedwhether, given that Iaccept the existence of M onthe evidenceof certain sense-impressions, andgiven also that Ithinkthat M is causally responsible for those sense-impressions, it follows that Iaccept the existence of Monthe grounds that its existence is requiredin order to account for the sense-impressions. (4)… Thenon-contingent character ofthe propositionthat the presenceof ared(or round)object tends tomake it lookto particular peopleas if there weresome- thingred (or round)before them doesnot, of course,in itself precludethe partic- ular fact that it looksto measif there weresomething red beforeme frombeing explainedby the presenceof aparticular redobject; it is anon-contingentmatter that corrosivesubstances tendto destroysurfaces to whichthey are applied; butit is quite legitimate to accountfor a particular case ofsurface-damageby saying that it wascausedby some corrosivesubstance. In each case the effect might have comeabout in some otherway” (Grice 1961,245-7).The present viewboth elab- orates upon,and endorses, each of these contentions. 51

experience E involved in S’sperceiving O.

For reasons given in the first section, the causal explanation in(iv) of the relation between sense data and perceived material objects makes the account incompatible with TA,which takes the relation of appearing to be primitive inaphilosophical explication. Anotorious problem for defenders ofthe causal theory of percep- tion has been to provide anadequate characterization ofthe intended causal relation, inamanner that iscapable of handling the two kinds of cases which Lewis (1980) accurately describes as veridical hallu- cinations and prosthetic vision .41 Ithink that Jackson (1977) ison the right track here; this infact constitutes one of the main consider- ations in favor ofclaim (iii), that the sensuous sides of phenomenal properties are (analogically) square, green, hot and so on. According to Jackson’s proposal, what is crucial “iswhat Icall the functional spatialdependence of the sense datum on the object, adependence which isconsequent on the causal connection between the object and the sense datum. Suppose, to illustrate, thatI am lookingat an orange. There are four spatial properties at issue:shape, size, distance (away), and (relative) direction. If, say,all of these except size are keptfixed, what happens? Well, if the orange doublesin size, the sense datum doubles in size (approximately); if the orange halves, thesense datum halves, and so on. Thus, thesize of the sense datum isa function of that of the material object. Likewise, if the orange changes direction while remaining constant in the other spatialrespects, asimilarde- pendence willbe exhibited”(Jackson 1977, 170-1). There isan important qualification that Jackson makes, which ex- plains the reference in(iv) to a“manifest scene involving O”. As Jackson puts it, “Iam correctly said to see someone inatent dress, though mysense datum may be invariant to considerable changes in that person’s shape …we need to distinguish three entities seen and

41.Cases ofveridical hallucination are cases suchthat, say, S has anexperi- enceas if there werea redsphere before his eyes,there actually is sucha sphere beforehis eyes,but S’sexperiencehas beencaused independently of the pres- enceof the sphere.A case ofprosthetic vision is onewhere S hasanexperienceas if there werea redsphere before his eyes,there is sucha sphereactually causing S’sexperience,but the causal mechanism is substantially different fromthe one typically operatingin normalhuman beings. 52 two relations. When Isee areasonably sized opaque material thing, I see: (i) the sense datum, (ii) the thing’s facing surface, and (iii) the thing. Now,the relation between the facing surface and the thing is common ground inthe …[the account in terms offunctional dependence] is designed to elucidate only the controversial relationship –that between sense data and the surfaces of material things …when Isee aperson in atent dress, the relation [which the account] isintended tocapture is not that between the person’s body and the dress, but that between the facing surface of the dress and the sense datum”(Jackson 1977, 172). The relation “between the facing surface and the thing”is the one tobe explained by the form ofmediation not tobe disputed by anybody (like that ob- taining between the perception of Venus and the perception ofthe bright luminous speck). It is just the mediation of the perception of the instantiation of manifest properties inthe perceived scene bythe consciously awareness of sensory features in the experienced sense datum that wewant toexplain incausal terms. Isaid of the suggestion by Jackson only that it is “on the right track”because the proposal Ibelieve to beentirely correct is some- what different. Inorder tocharacterize that functional dependence of perception on sensory awareness, Ithink weshould invoke all manifest relations among the manifest properties (chromatic rela- tions like brightness, acoustic relations like loudness, and so on), not just the spatial ones. Wetake thus full advantage ofthe Sellarsian way in which we have explained the likeness of sensory and mani- fest sides ofphenomenal features. Wecan see awhite sphere byex- periencing apink, egg-shaped sense datum. It is the white sphere that is the perceptual object, in that variations in the shape and color of the sphere would give rise to corresponding variations in the sense datum. Invokingin this way all manifest relations, instead of merely the spatial ones, is the only way Ienvisage to generalize the account to cases of perception where spatial properties are not involved; for instance, perceiving asound which one cannot locate inspace ex- cept inthe vaguest terms. Thus, following Jackson’s account ( op. cit.,171) Iwill say,more precisely,that inexperiencing s-d(E) S perceives ascene involving material object O just if (i) s(O) causes s-d(E),and (ii) the sensuous properties of s-d(E) are functionally dependent on the correspond- 53 ing manifest properties of s(O),as aconsequence of the manner in which s(O) causes the having of s-d(E).42 Weare ina better position nowto understand the sense in which, according tothe present view,the manifest properties can be applied to sense data. Consider the most controversialcase, the three-dimen- sional spatial properties. The intentional objects ofsome perceptual states are tobe characterized inspatial terms: say,as an instance of a given shape. Our ability torepresent objects ofthat kind is system- atic, productive. Anybody able to represent an instance ofagiven shape would be able to represent also instances of the same shape in different sizes, in different directions and distances before him, and so on. This can only be explained by assuming that we bring to bear a tacitly possessed systematic knowledge of those properties –anaive geometry,acomponent of the naive physics psychologists ascribe to us. Now,wecan indirectly perceive instances of some spatial prop- erties (the three-dimensional shape ofyour armchair) by less indi- rectly perceiving the spatial properties of others (the two-dimen- sional drawing you made for me). The representational relation in cases like the latter involve the tacitly known functional dependence of the more indirectly represented spatial properties onthe spatial properties less indirectly represented. Wetacitly understand that the several different spatial properties we would have been equally able toidentify inthe drawing (by bringing thus tobear our tacitly known geometry) would have indicated different spatial properties we could have been equally able toattribute tothe room. The sense data account that Iamsupporting here contends that something like this obtains in any case of apparent perception, this time involving our conscious awareness ofspatial (and other) prop- erties of sense data. These properties are spatial inthat we bring to bear, inrecognizing them and in locating them intheir proper place inqualitative space, ageometrical tacit knowledge. It is geometrical in that itshares relevant features with the knowledge by means of

42.The present proposalis closely related to the onebyLewis (1980,283); wheneversomeone perceives the scene beforehis senses accordingto the present account,he perceives it, accordingto Lewis,although not the otherway around. Focussingon the counterfactualdependence of primedproperties ofexperiences ontheir correspondingmanifest properties providesfurther precision, of which Lewis’proposal is in myviewneeded. 54 which werecognize, and place in their own undeniable space, the spatial properties instantiated inthe material scenes we doperceive in canonical circumstances. The spatial properties of sense data are more specifically three-dimensional (in contrast with the two-di- mensional ones ofthe previous example) in that the tacitly known geometrical knowledge we bring to bear is, more specifically,ofthe kind involved in representing tous perceptually three-dimensional properties ofmanifest objects.

(v) The object s-d(E) is mental.

This follows from the preceding consideration, byelimination of al- ternative possibilities. Sense data could only be material things (in cases ofperception and misperception) if weaccepted the claims of the theory of appearing; butnot after rejecting it and subscribing the causal claim before. Sense data are mental in that as concrete tokens (not just the sensuous types they instantiate) they could not exist without the existence of asubject, potentially consciously aware of them. Inthis they differ from the tokens of manifest properties per- ceived by means of them. Even in the case of secondary properties, any particular token could exist without being the object of the per- ceptual conscious awareness of anybody; and each concrete token could be the object of the perceptual conscious awareness of more than one mind.

4. The Downfall of the Theory of Appearing

The form ofasense data account of perception that has been just out- lined is, Isubmit, not easy torebut onthe basis oftraditional consid- erations. Toconclude mydefense of the account, let menowshow the implausibility of the remaining rival, the theory of appearing. Robinson (1985, 1990) provides an argument that can befurther de- veloped soas to provide the decisive consideration against TA.He points out that neurophysiology might well find acommon cause (or, better, aconstitutive basis) for cases like Sellars’(a)-(c) of veridical perception, misperception and hallucination. According to the disjunctivist theory ofappearing, the first and the third cases are, 55 however, ontologically apart; the first involves arelation with ama- terial object, the hallucinatory case something else. Robinson ar- gues against this byinvoking a“same cause, same effect”(or “same constitutive basis, same constituted state”, as Iwould rather put it) principle. Onthe assumption that neurology finds acommon physi- cal constitutive basis for phenomenal states constituting perceptions and hallucinations, the principle would entail, against the theory of appearing, that the phenomenal states themselves have also acom- mon ontological nature. Emphasizing the distinction between facts about perception knowable by philosophical reflection, and facts knowable only a posteriori, Langsam (1997) plausibly retorts that the principle at stake only applies tointrinsic properties ofthe events discussed. Ac- cording to TA,however, phenomenal features as discerned at the personal, philosophical level are relational at least incases of veridical perception and misperception, and so extrinsic. Langsam (op. cit.,41-48) then goes onto provide convincing examples in- volving relational properties to which the principle that Robinson appeals tointuitively does not apply. This response works essentially incombination with the consid- eration concerning the proper level of theorizing atwhich the nature of phenomenal features isdiscussed. The issue of the nature of per- ceptual experiences concerns their status as postulated at the per- sonal level of rationalizing, ultimately folk-psychological explana- tions. Tothe extent that the only plausible account ofphenomenal features of experiences, at this level, is the one provided by TA, Langsam’s response is correct. Atthat level, the phenomenal fea- tures involved inperception would be ta-extrinsic properties; Robin- son’s principle would not then apply tothem. Onthe assumption that neurology does find acommon factor to Sellars’cases (a)-(c), the principle would only entail that there issome ta-intrinsic property common to the three cases playing an explanatory role at some em- pirical level ofexplanation. This isnot incontradiction to the main tenet characterizing the theory of appearing. Langsam’s response, however, sets into relief the most striking problem for the theory of appearing; itcan then easily be seen that his argument backfires. When weclassify two events asfalling un- der a common ta-extrinsic property (say,the two occur acentury af- 56 ter Hastings), we do not expect that they are thereby tobe classified as falling under acommon intrinsic property for purposes of placing them ina causal structure. Correspondingly,we do not have any ten- dency to feel our ta-extrinsic classification confirmed by finding out that the two events can be thus classified for such purposes of causal explanation. When we classify two events as falling under different ta-extrinsic properties (one occurs acentury after Hastings, the other two centuries after Hastings), wesimilarly lack any tendency to be thereby surprised ifthey are classified as falling under acommon in- trinsic property for purposes ofcausal explanation. It isaltogether different inthe case we are discussing. Wefind the suggestion on which Robinson’s argument rests –that neurology will find acommon factor to the likes ofSellars’cases (a)-(c) –emi- nently plausible; this iswhat we expect, this isthe prediction we– ignorant of the scientific facts –would nonetheless make. Both the Sellarsian third way and our sense data theory provide anexplana- tion for this expectation. What accounts for our expectation is that, at the proper folk-psychological level of rationalizing explanation, we feel itis appropriate to posit intrinsic (or ta-intrinsic anyway) commonalities tocases corresponding toSellars’(a)-(c). Weare dis- posed to this independently of any consideration having to do with the constitutive, physical (neurological) basis of the ta-intrinsic states weposit. The basis for our disposition must beinthe assump- tions constituting folk-psychological explanation, thus inthe source of our relevant apriori intuitions. This prima facie inclination tofind Robinson’s principle of application tothe posits of folk-psychologi- cal explication in cases corresponding to Sellars’(a)-(c) counts also as aprima facie indication that the ontology ofthe theory of appear- ing iswrong. Igrant Langsam that this isonly aprima facie consid- eration, which does not straightforwardly refute the theory of ap- pearing. However, the prima facie consideration proves atleast the following. Tothe extent that there isa coherent story whose ontol- ogy fits with our inclination tofind the principle “same constitutive physical basis, same constituted psychological state”of application to the likes of cases (a)-(c), that alternative explication is tobe pre- ferred to TA. There are cases inwhich, from asubjective point ofview,itis im- possible totell whether the experience one ishaving isveridical, il- 57 lusory,or plainly hallucinatory. 43 Ifthe experience is hallucinatory, and the subject istaken in by it, wewould expect the same kind of behavior asin the corresponding veridical case, and would provide folk-psychological, rationalizing explanations of his behavior on that assumption by means of “appearance”talk. The prima facie correct explication isthat there are explanatory commonalities, pos- ited atthe required personal level. Again, consider the case of asub- ject who has an overriding intention to touch ared sphere, has before his eyes ared sphere, and still remains undecided whether ornot to move his arm. The reason, we would say,is that he is undecided whether his experience is the one hewould have in acase ofpercep- tion, orthe one he would have in acase ofhallucination. This expla- nation adverts to acommonality at the personal level in the two cases. It isprovided independently of neurological knowledge, but leads us to expect acommon neurological basis, whose finding would confirm our folk-psychological explanations. It isprospects regarding neurological findings such asthis which suggest that the ontological nature of the phenomenal features weposit in providing explanations like those in the examples isatodds with TA.They are much better explained by accounts like the one provided by the Sellarsian third way orthe sense data theory,which, against the main tenet of the theory of appearing, ascribe the same ontological nature to corresponding phenomenal features in perception, illusion and hallucination. The force ofthis version of Robinson’s argument is strengthened by appreciating itsmodesty; this can be seen byrealizing that no similar considerations could be given to support aclaim that phe- nomenal features are, not just ta-intrinsic aswe have argued that they are, but absolutely intrinsic as internalists want them tobe. Part of the Sellarsian third way,Ihave suggested, isessentially right. What is right is the claim that an appearance-ascription entails the kind of relationality contemplated bySellars; i.e., that that kind of relation-

43.At least onedefenderof disjunctivism hasdeniedthat “the psychological episodes whichoccur when I hearor see somethingand those whichoccur when Iamsubject to the corresponding‘ total illusion’resemble eachother perfectly” (Hyman1992, 285-7). This is aboldempirical claim; Ithinkwe alreadyhave enoughevidence to reject it (see the phospheneexample in Jackson, op. cit., 75). 58 ality is a necessary (in fact, constitutive) condition for the truth of an appearance-ascription. Ithus reject the Cartesian claim that phe- nomenal qualities are, conceptually speaking, strictly intrinsic, purely internal affairs. This internalist view of qualia has been de- fended recently bywriters such as Block (1995), Chalmers (1996), Loar (1997) and Peacocke (1983), butremains deeply problematic. Now,could not an argument like the one deployed inthis section against the theory of appearing beused against my proposal, given that italso makes phenomenal properties relational, even though not ta-extrinsic? Idonot think so. Such an argument could not appeal to equally forceful intuitions regarding the kind offolk-psychological, rationalizing explanations concerning perfectly ordinary cases cor- responding to Sellars’(a)-(c), and the expectations that those expla- nations create for the physical properties underwriting them. It would have to appeal tounfamiliar cases (brains inavat, and soon). It is not obvious that wehave sufficiently clear-cut intuitions con- cerning the required situations, incompatible with the modest form of extrinsicness which myproposal does support. This concludes mycase for sense data. Essentially,the argument reproduces the one givenby Jackson ( op. cit.,96-99), which Langsam (op. cit.,56, fn. 7) disregards. Against the main claim of TA,wehave good reasons to provide ananalysis of“looks”state- ments which finds acommon factor in cases like those discussed by Sellars. Sellars provides acommon intentional factor, and a“sensu- ous”one at the subpersonal level of scientific explanation. But find- ing the common sensuous factor atthat level isnot enough. It exists also at the personal level of(philosophically explicated) folk-psy- chological rationalizing explanation. This iscorroborated byour ex- pectations regarding the applicability to the cases at stake of the “same constitutive physical basis, same constituted folk-psycholog- ical state”principle. In sum, Ihave presented aversion of asense data approach toper- ception, Ihave distinguished itfrom well-known versions like Jack- son’s, and Ihave offered an argument toshow that itimproves sub- stantially on alternative theories of perception like TA,disjunctive approaches ingeneral and reductive representationalist approaches. The form of the sense data theory Ihave advanced has four features which distinguish itfrom alternative theories, and allow us to count 59 itas aversion of sense data theories. (i) Perception involves experi- ences, conceived as states relating subjects to mental particulars (event-tokens). (ii) Those particulars are analogically butcorrectly characterized as possessing the manifest properties ofmaterial par- ticulars which wealso access inperception, like colors, shapes and so on. (iii) Perception ofan object occurs when itand the perceiving subject are causally connected in such away that some manifest properties of the object cause corresponding properties in the expe- rience ofwhich the subject isaware, and variations inthe manifest properties along their manifest relations would cause corresponding variations in the experienced properties. (iv) Experiences provide a fundamental rational justification for our empirical knowledge. Other features of traditional sense data theories are abandoned. Thus, itis also suggested, against tradition, (i) that experiences have propositional correctness conditions, (ii) whose constitutive charac- terization involves “local ”(in Peacocke’s (1992) sense), and in particular (iii) relations with the material world.

REFERENCES

Akins,Kathleen (1996):“ OfSensory Systems and the ‘Aboutness’of Mental States”, Journalof Philosophy xciii, 337-372. Alston,William 1999:“Back tothe Theoryof Appearing”,in Philosophi- calPerspectives 13: ,J.Tomberlin(ed.), Malden, Mass.: Blackwell. Block,Ned (1990): “InvertedEarth” , inJ. Tomberlin(ed.), Philosophical Perspectives, 4:Action Theoryand Philosophy of Mind ,Atascadero, California: RidgeviewPub. Co. —(1995):“ OnaConfusionabout a Functionof Consciousness”, Behav- ioraland Brain Sciences 18,227-247. Bonjour,Laurence (1998): InDefense ofPureReason ,Cambridge:Cam- bridge U.P. Brewer,Bill (1996):“ Internalismand Perceptual Knowledge”, European Journalof Philosophy 4, 259-275. Broad,C. D.(1965):“ TheTheory of Sensa” , inR. Swartz (ed.), Per- ceiving, Sensingand Knowing ,85-129,Los Angeles: University of 60

California Press.(A selection fromhis Scientific Thought , Routledge &KeganPaul, London, 1923.) Burge,T yler(1977): “Belief deRe”, Journal of Philosophy 74,338-362. —(1993):“ContentPreservation” , Philosophical Review 102,457-488. Chalmers, David(1996): TheConscious Mind ,Oxford:Oxford Univer- sity Press. Child,William (1992):“ Visionand Experience: the Causal Theoryand Disjunctive Conception”, PhilosophicalQuarterly 42,297-316. Chisholm,Roderick M. (1950):“ TheTheoryof Appearing”,in M. Black (ed.), PhilosophicalAnalysis ,Ithaca: Cornell Univ.Pr., 102-18. Also inR. Swartz (ed.), Perceiving, Sensingand Knowing Universityof Cal- iforniaPress, Los Angeles, 168-186. — (1957): Perceiving: APhilosophicalStudy. Ithaca, NewY ork:Cornell U.P. Clark,Austen (1993): SensoryQualities ,Oxford:Clarendon Press. Dretske,Fred (1969): Seeingand Knowing ,London:Routledge and Kegan Paul. — (1995): Naturalizingthe Mind ,Cambridge,Mass.: MITPress. García-Carpintero, Manuel (1998):“ Indexicalsas Token-Reflexives”, Mind 107(1998), pp. 529-563. —(1999):“ Searle onPerception”, Teorema 18/1,19-41. Grice, H.P.(1961):“ TheCausal Theoryof Perception”, Proceedingsof the Aristotelian Society ,35.Alsoin Grice, H.P ., Studiesin The Waysof Words,Cambridge,Mass.: HarvardU.P .,1989,224-248, from where I quote. Harman,Gilbert (1989):“ TheIntrinsic Quality ofExperience” , inJ. Tomberlin(ed.), PhilosophicalP erspectives, 4:Philosophy of Mind andAction Theory ,Atascadero,California: RidgeviewPub. Co., pp. 31-52. Hyman,John (1992): “ TheCausal Theoryof Perception”, Philosophical Quarterly 42,277-296. Jackson,Frank (1977): Perception.A Representative Theory .Cambridge: CambridgeU.P . Johnston,Mark (1992): “ Howto Speak of the Colors”, Philosophical 61

Studies 68,221-263. —(1997):“ Howto Speakof the Colors,Postscript: Visual Experience”, inA. Byrne& D.Hilbert (eds.), Readingsin Color ,vol.1, 172-6. —(1998):“Arethe Manifest PropertiesResponse-Depe ndent?”, The Mo- nist. Kaplan,David (1969), “ QuantifyingIn” , inD. Davidsonand J. Hintikka (eds.) Wordsand Objections ,Dordrecht:D. Reidel PublishingCom- pany,pp. 178-214. Langsam,Harold (1997): “ TheTheory of AppearingDefended” , Philo- sophicalStudies 87, 33-59. Langton,R. &Lewis, D.(1998):“ Defining‘ Intrinsic’” , Philosophyand Phenomenological Research 53,333-345. Lewis, David(1973): Counterfactuals Oxford:Basil Blackwell. —(1980):“ Veridical Hallucination andProsthetic Vision”, Australasian Journalof Philosophy ,58.Alsoin his PhilosophicalP apersvol. 2 , Ox- ford:Oxford U. P.,273-290,to whichI refer. —(1994):“ Lewis, David:Reduction of Mind”, inS. Guttenplan(ed.), A Companionto the Philosophyof Mind ,Oxford:Blackwell, 412-430. —(1997):“FinkishDispositions” , Philosophical Quarterly 47,143-158. Loar,Brian (1997):“ PhenomenalStates” , inN. Block,O. Flanagan& G. Guzeldere(eds.) TheNature of Consciousness ,Cambridge,Mass.: MIT Press. McDowell, John(1982): “ Criteria, Defeasibility andKnowledge” , Pro- ceedingsof the British Academy 68, 455-79. —(1986):“ SingularThoughts and the Extent ofInnerSpace” , inP .Pettit andJ. McDowell (eds.), Subject,Thought and Context ,Oxford:Clar- endonPress, 137-168. — (1994): Mindand W orld ,Cambridge,Mass.: HarvardU.P . —(1995):“ Knowledgeand the Internal,” Philosophyand Phenomeno- logicalResearch 55, 877-93. —(1998):“ Havingthe Worldin View: the WoodbridgeLectures 1997”, Journalof Philosophy 95, 431-91. McGinn,Colin (1989): Mental Content ,Oxford:Basil Blackwell. Millikan, Ruth(1984): Language,Thought and OtherBiological Catego- 62

ries,Cambridge,Mass.: MITPress. Moore,George (1918-9): “ SomeJudgmentsof Perception”, Proceedings ofthe Aristotelian Society 19.Also in Moore, George, Philosophical Studies,London:Routledge and Kegan Paul, and in R.Swartz (ed.), Perceiving, Sensingand Knowing Universityof California Press,Los Angeles,1-28, from which I quote. Mulligan, Kevin(1995): “ Perception”, in TheCambridge Companion to Husserl,B.Smith& D.WoodruffSmith (eds.), Cambridge: Cam- bridge U.P. —(1999):“ Perception,Predicates andParticular”, in Consciousnessand Intentionality:Modes and Modalities ofAttribution ,DenisFisette (ed.),Dordrecht: Kluwer. Peacocke,Christopher (1983): Senseand Content. Experience, Thought, andtheir Relations ,Oxford:Clarendon Press. — (1992): AStudyof Concepts ,Cambridge,Mass.: MITPress. —(1993):“ HowAre A PrioriTruths Possible?” , EuropeanJournal of Philosophy i, 175-199. —(1998):“ ConsciousAttitudes, Attention,and Self-Knowledg e”, inC. Wright,B.C. Smith& C.McDonald(eds.), KnowingOur OwnMinds , 63-98,Oxford: Clarendon Press. — (1999): Being Known,Oxford:Oxford University Press. Perkins,Moreland (1983): Sensingthe World ,Indianapolis:Hackett. Robinson,Howard (1985): “ TheGeneral Formof the Argumentfor Berkeleian Idealism”, inJ. Fosterand H. Robinson(eds.), Essays on Berkeley,163-186,Oxford: Clarendon Press. —(1990):“TheObjects ofPerceptual ExperienceII” , Proceedingsof the Aristotelian Society ,SupplementaryV olume64, 151-66. RoxbeeCox, J. W.(1971):“ AnAnalysisof Perceivingin Termsof the Causation ofBeliefs I”,inF .N.Sibley(ed.), Perception, London: Methuen,23-64. Searle, John(1983): Intentionality ,Cambridge:Cambridge University Press. Sellars, Wilfrid(1963a): “ Empiricism andthe Philosophyof Mind”, in Science, Perception andReality ,London:Routledge and Kegan Paul, 127-196. 63

—(1963b):“ ”,in Science, Perception andReality , Lon- don:Routledge and Kegan Paul, 60-106. — (1967): Science andMetaphysics: V ariationson Kantian Themes , London:Routledge and Kegan Paul. Shoemaker,Sidney (1984): “ TheInverted Spectrum” , inhis Identity, Causeand Mind ,Cambridge:Cambridge University Press. —(1994):“ Self-Knowledgeand‘ InnerSense’ ” , Philosophyand Pheno- menologicalResearch ,54,249-315. Snowdon,Paul (1980-1): “ Perception,Vision and Causation” , Proceed- ingsof the Aristotelian Society 81,175-192. Reprinted in J. Dancy (ed.), PerceptualKn owledge ,Oxford:Ox fordUn iv.Pr., 198 8, 192-208. —(1990):“ TheObjects ofPerceptual ExperienceI” , Proceedingsof the Aristotelian Society ,SupplementaryV olume64, 121-50. Suchting,W .A.(1969):“ Perceptionand the Time-GapArgument” , Philo- sophicalQuarterly 19, 46-56. Tye,Michael (1984):“ TheAdverbial Approach to Visual Experience”, PhilosophicalReview 93,195-225. — (1995): TenProblems of Consciousness ,Cambridge,Mass.: MIT Press. Williamson, Timothy(1995): “ IsKnowinga State ofMind?”, Mind 104, 533-65.