Center for Thomistic Studies Report 2011-2012

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Center for Thomistic Studies Report 2011-2012 Center for Thomistic Studies Report 2011-2012 § From the Director: “Every scholar whose learning is of the kingdom of heaven must be like a rich man who knows how to bring both old and new things out of his treasure house.” We, at the Center for Thomistic Studies, have followed this academic prescription this year, welcoming old friends, like Papal biographer and Center Advisory Board member George Weigel and Fr. Joseph Koterski, Fordham University as well as first-time visitors, like Dr. Matthew Levering, University of Dayton, who was this year’s Aquinas Lecturer, and Angela Bello, Professor Emeritus of History of Contemporary Philosophy at Lateran University in Rome and an expert on Edith Stein. We had two successful Ph.D. defenses and graduated four MAs, including our first BA/MA student. This year also marked the beginning of collaboration with the Pontifcal Academy of St. Thomas Aquinas and the planning for our joint conference in Houston for 18–19 October 2013 on the theme of Thomas Aquinas: Teacher of Humanity". The 1ST US conference of the Pontifical Academy of St. Thomas Aquinas 18 - 19 October 2013 University of St. Thomas (Houston) Thomas Aquinas: Teacher of Humanity Co-sponsored by the Center for Thomistic Studies and The John Paul II Forum “Doctor Humanitatis is the name we give St. Thomas Aquinas because he was always ready to receive the values of all cultures. [H]is assertions on the dignity of the human person and the use of his reason, in perfect harmony with the faith, make St. Thomas a teacher for our time.” John Paul II, Address to the 8th International Thomistic Congress, 13 September 1980 Thomas Aquinas: Teacher of Humanity will explore the significance for the 21st century of Thomas Aquinas’ teaching on humanity. Is it still meaningful to talk about “humanity” or “inhumanity”? What challenges do evolution, eugenics and the trans-humanist movement present for a concept of “humanity”? Is the “human” a viable standard in a world with many cultures and traditions? This conference is a part of the Pontifical Academy of St. Thomas Aquinas’s new initiative on the Thomistic legacy of Blessed John Paul II. The honor of hosting this unprece- dented event comes in recognition of the unique partnership between the Center for Thomistic Studies and the John Paul II Forum. We are honored that the Academy under its Secretary, Bishop Marcelo Sanches Sorondo, has chosen Houston’s University of St. Thomas as the site of its first U.S. conference. § 2012 Aquinas Lecture: Dr. Matthew Levering, Professor of Religious Studies at the University of Dayton, delivered this year’s Aquinas Lecture on January 26 in Jones Hall. He spoke on the issue of whether or not we can know God by examining the created world. Can we know God’s existence and attributes by reflec- tion upon the good things that we see around us? If we can know God in this way, why do we also need to know him through his self-revelation in Jesus Christ? Put another way, is the God of the Greek phi- losophers the same God whom we encounter in Jesus, and if the God that we know in these two ways is indeed the same, can we make do with one way alone? Dr. Levering speculated on the idea that believ- ers in the incarnate Son of God have little stake in also holding that we can know God through natural reason, especially now that relatively few philosophers think that philosophical labors can attain to knowledge of the living God. Dr. Levering argued that Christians should hold that God’s existence, along with certain other attrib- utes, can be demonstrated by natural reason on the basis of material things. Dr. Ivany introduces Dr. Levering Michele Malloy, last year’s Aquinas Medal at dinner in Dr. Levering’s honor. recipient, discusses Dr. Levering’s lecture with him. § John Paul II Forum: The Center for Thomistic Studies continued its relation- ship with the John Paul II Forum, whose director, Dr. John Hittinger, is on the Center faculty. The Center co- sponsored a number of events with the Forum in 2011- 12. Particularly noteworthy was the visit of George Weigel on February 12. Mr. Weigel, the papal biographer of Pope John Paul II and Distinguished Senior Fellow of the Ethics and Public Policy Center, spoke on the topic, “Blessed John Paul II and Pope Benedict XVI: Two Popes, One Mis- sion.” On June 13 the Center for Thomistic Studies and the John Paul II Forum also co-sponsored Fr. Joseph Koterski, S.J., Associate Professor of Philosophy at Fordham University and Editor-in-Chief of Inter- national Philosophical Quarterly who spoke to a receptive crowd on “Thinking with the Church: Les- sons from the Life of Avery Cardinal Dulles, S.J.” The JPII Forum also sponsored a summer workshop on Veritatis Splendor led by Fr. Joseph Koterski. § Aquinas and the Arabs: The CTS was again active in the “Aquinas and the ‘Arabs’ International Working Group.” Dr. R. Edward Houser attended and read papers at the Fall 2011 Meeting hosted by Universidad Panamericana, Mexico City. He also attended the Spring 2012 Meeting, hosted by the CNRS and the Université de Paris 1: Pantheon Sorbonne. UST is scheduled to host the Fall Conference in 2013. § Center Colloquia: Under the care of Dr. Thomas Osborne, the Colloquia featured a mixture of students, Center Faculty, UST Faculty, and illustrious invited guests. Here is the line-up of speakers: August 25 Rev. Prof. Robert A. Gahl, Jr., Pontifical University of the Holy Cross, Rome, Italy spoke on “Contemporary psychology (3rd wave CBT/ACT/mindfulness) and its rela- tionship to Aristotelian-Thomistic moral psychology.” Sept. 1 Daniel De Haan, Graduate Student, Center for Thomistic Studies, UST spoke on "Dysordered Acquired Appetites and the Ratio of Addiction: A Thomistic Analysis.” Sept. 15 John F.X. Knasas, Philosophy Professor at the Center for Thomistic Studies, UST spoke on "Comments on Brian Davies, The Reality of God and the Problem of Evil.” Sept. 29 R. Edward Houser, Bishop Wendelin J. Nold Chair in Graduate Philosophy, Center for Thomistic Studies, UST spoke on “Is God’s existence self-evident?, In Sententiis 1.d.3.1.2.” Oct. 6 Domenic D’Ettore, Graduate Student, Center for Thomistic Studies, UST spoke on “The Concept Representing God and Creatures: An Analysis of John Capreolus’ Doc- trine of Analogy." Oct. 14 Alexander Pruss, Associate Professor of Philosophy, Baylor University spoke on "Evil and the Problem of Anomaly." Oct. 20 Steven Jensen, Assistant Professor of Philosophy at the Center for Thomistic Studies, UST spoke on "Double Effect, Proportionality, and Allowing Harm." Nov. 11 Peter Casarella, Director, Center for World Catholicism & Intercultural Theology, DePaul University spoke on “Facing the Verbal Likeness: St. Augustine, Nicholas of Cusa, and Pope John Paul II on the Analogy of the Word.” Nov. 17 Theodore George, Associate Professor of Philosophy, Texas A&M University spoke on “Kindness toward What Is: Heidegger on Being, Art, and the 'Guiding Measure' of Conduct.” Nov. 22 Timothy Madigan, Assistant Professor of Philosophy at St. John Fisher College spoke on “W. K. Clifford and The Ethics of Belief .” March 29 Bruce Marshall, Lehman Professor of Christian Doctrine, Director, Graduate Program in Religious Studies Southern Methodist University spoke on “Is Nature a Barrier to Grace?: Aquinas, Scotus, and the Modern Debate about the Supernatural.” April 12 Carol Gardosik, Philosophy for Children Research Group, Graduate Student, Center for Thomistic Studies, UST spoke on “Socrates in the Schools: From Clackmannshire, Scotland to Huntsville,Texas.” April 18 Joseph Graham, Professor of Philosophy, UST spoke on “Science and Principles.” April 19 John F.X. Knasas, Professor of Philosophy, Center for Thomistic Studies, UST spoke on “The ‘Suppositio’ of Motion’s Eternity and the Interpretation of Aquinas’ Motion Proofs for God.” April 27 Dr. Luca Oliva, Visiting Professor, Salem State University spoke on “Fixing Kant's Epistemology.” § Endowed Chairs: Dr. R. Edward Houser is the current occupant of the Bishop Wendelin J. Nold Chair in Graduate Philosophy, named for the Most Reverend Wende- lin Nold (1900-1981), fifth bishop of the Diocese of Galveston-Houston (1950-1975), who, among his other accomplishments, ordered the integra- tion of Catholic schools in 1961. Dr. Houser was recently reappointed to the Chair. Dr. John Deely holds the Frank A. Rudman Chair in Philosophy at the Center for Thomistic Studies, which memorializes the contributions of Frank A. Rudman to Catholic education and the University of St. Tho- mas, where he served on the Board from 1953-59. Both these chairs were endowed through the generosity of the Scanlan Foundation. CENTER FACULTY § John Deely PhD 1967 Aquinas Institute School of Philosophy MA 1966 Aquinas Institute School of Philosophy BA 1965 Aquinas Institute School of Philosophy Publications: "The Semiosis of Mathematical Thought", forthcoming in Semiotics, Cognitive Science and Mathemat- ics, ed. Marcel Danesi et al. (Munich, Germany: Lincom Europa). "Updating the Classical Idea of 'Rational Animal' ," in the Proceedings of the World Congress of Catho- lic Universities, held 12-14 August 2011 at the University of Avila, Spain. "Semiotic Entanglement": The Concepts of Environment, Umwelt, and Lebenswelt in Semiotic Perspec- tive”, forthcoming in Semiotica (Berlin, Germany: Mouton de Gruyter). "Postmodernity as the unmasking of objectivity: Identifying the positive essence of postmodernity as a distinct new era in the history of philosophy", Semiotica 183-114 (2011), 31-57. "Taking Faith Seriously", Revue roumaine de philosophie, tome 55, issue 2 (December, 2011), 391–415. How Science Enriches Theology, co-authored with Fr. Benedict Ashley, O.P. (South Bend, IN: St. Augustine's Press, 2012). Semiotics Continues to Astonish. Thomas A.
Recommended publications
  • Epistemic Humility, Arguments from Evil, and Moral Skepticism
    Jonathan L. Kvanvig c02.tex V1 - June 4, 2009 11:16am Page 17 2 Epistemic Humility, Arguments from Evil, and Moral Skepticism Daniel Howard-Snyder Many arguments from evil at least tacitly rely on something like the following line of thought: The Inference. On sustained reflection, we don’t see how any reason we know of would justify God in permitting all the evil in the world; ¹ FN:1 therefore, there is no reason that would justify God. The conclusion is frequently more nuanced: ‘‘it is very likely that there is no such reason’’ or ‘‘more likely than not’’ or ‘‘more likely than it otherwise would be’’. Some critics reject the premise: we do see how some reason would justify God. These are the theodicists. Others accept the premise but reject the conclusion: the evidence or non-evidential warrant for God’s existence is much better than the evidence for no justifying reason. These are the natural theologians and Reformed epistemologists. Some critics, however, insist that even if the premise is true and even if there isn’t better evidence or non-evidential warrant for God’s existence, we should For comments on previous drafts, I thank Michael Almeida, Nick Beckstead, Michael Bergmann, Rebecca Copenhaver, Trent Dougherty, Robert Epperson, Frances Howard- Snyder, Hud Hudson, Shieva Kleinschmidt, Christian Lee, Wes Morriston, Michael Murray, Robert Pasnau, Alexander Pruss, Michael Rea, John Schellenberg, Michael Tooley, Ryan Wasserman, Dennis Whitcomb, and three anonymous referees. ¹ Three notes in one. (1) The theistic God is the God in question here. At a minimum, this God has enough power and knowledge to prevent evil, and is unsurpassable in moral goodness.
    [Show full text]
  • ABSTRACT Ut Omnes Unum Sint: Examining the Presence of The
    ABSTRACT Ut Omnes Unum Sint: Examining the Presence of the Catholic Intellectual Tradition at a Baptist University Carmen M. Galvan Director: Dr. Barry Hankins, Ph.D. of History This research collected firsthand accounts of faith and teaching from both Catholic and non-Catholic faculty at Baylor University in order to prove that Baylor has intentionally sought and hired additional Roman Catholic faculty in order to strengthen the university’s religious identity. The appeal of Catholics was found to be the Catholic intellectual tradition, which holds that faith be integrated with learning in all aspects of academia. The research revealed four major commonalities of Baylor’s Catholic hiring: 1) the university hiring process, 2) the integration of faith and learning in the classroom, 3) the positive and/or negative experiences faculty have had at Baylor, and 4) the faculty’s perspective of Baylor 2012 and its future. UT OMNES UNUM SINT: EXAMINING THE PRESENCE OF THE CATHOLIC INTELLECTUAL TRADITION AT A BAPTIST UNIVERSITY By Carmen M. Galvan Waco, Texas May 2012 TABLE OF CONTENTS PREFACE ……………………………………………………………………………. iii ACKNOWLEDGMENTS …………………………………………………………… iv DEDICATION ………………………………………………………………………... v Chapter 1. INTRODUCTION ……………………………………………………………. 1 Purpose of Thesis A Rift of Religion 2. METHODOLOGY …………………………………………………………… 12 Selection Process Data Collection, Coding, and Analysis 3. HIRING OF ROMAN CATHOLICS AT BAYLOR UNIVERSITY………… 21 Administrative Interviews Commitment to Faith 4. CATHOLIC INTELLECTUAL TRADITION AT BAYLOR UNIVERSITY .. 32 Tradition of Faith in the Classroom Catholic Faculty in a Baptist Environment Conclusion BIBLIOGRAPHY…………………………………………………………………….... 45 ii PREFACE “But you’re Catholic … why are you going to a Baptist university?” Right after my choice of major, this question of spiritual identity was one of the most common I heard as an entering freshman at Baylor University.
    [Show full text]
  • Evolutionary Argument Against Naturalism?” International ​ Journal for Philosophy of Religion 69.3 (2010): 193–204
    1 On Plantinga on Belief in Naturalism1 Troy Cross Introduction Naturalism, according to Alvin Plantinga, is the thesis “that there is no such person as God or anything at all like God” (2011b, 435; see also, 2002a, 1; 2011a, vix), and one ​ ​ could be forgiven for thinking that what Plantinga calls his “Evolutionary Argument Against Naturalism”, or “EAAN”, which he has refined and defended for over two decades, is an argument against that thesis (1991, 1993, 2002a, 2002b, 2011a, 2011b). But that would be a mistake. The conclusion of the EAAN is not about the truth of ​ ​ naturalism but about the rationality of believing naturalism to be true: it is that one cannot ​ ​ rationally and reflectively believe that contemporary evolutionary theory is correct about our origins while also believing that neither God nor anything like God exists.2 The difference between truth and rational belief is important here. Consider Moore’s paradoxical sentence: “I don’t believe it’s raining but as a matter of fact it is” (Moore, 209). Nothing prevents that sentence, or others like it, from being true. If you 1 For instructive conversations on this topic I am indebted to John Bang, George Bealer, Mark Bedau, Eliyah Cohen, Bryan Cross, Augie Faller, Emma Handte, Elad Gilo, Nick Gigliotti, John Hare, Jordan Horowitz, Paul Hovda, Alexander Pruss, Margaret Scharle, Derek Schiller, Mackenzie Sullivan, and Carol Voeller. I also wish to thank audiences at Reed College and the University of Nebraska Omaha where I presented early versions of some of this material. Anthony Nguyen gave me many helpful comments on a draft.
    [Show full text]
  • St. Thomas Summer Seminars in Philosophy of Religion And
    Recent PhDs and current graduate students in philosophy, theology, or religious studies are invited to apply to participate in the 2010 St. Thomas Summer Seminar in Philosophy of Religion and Philosophical Theology. The 2010 St. Thomas Summer Seminar in Philosophy of Religion and Philosophical Theology June 15—July 2, 2010 University of Saint Thomas, Saint Paul, Minnesota TOPICS AND SPEAKERS ORGANIZED BY THE EPISTEMOLOGY OF THE EPISTEMOLOGY OF RELIGIOUS BELIEF DISAGREEMENT Dean Zimmerman Alvin Plantinga (Notre Dame) and Roger White (M.I.T.) and (Rutgers) Richard Feldman (Rochester) Thomas Kelly (Princeton) Michael Rota SCIENCE AND RELIGION REDUCTIONISM AND THE (University of St. Thomas) Alvin Plantinga (Notre Dame) and PHILOSOPHY OF BIOLOGY Elliott Sober (UW-Madison) Alan Love (University of Minnesota) THE COSMOLOGICAL ARGUMENT WRITING FOR AUDIENCES Alexander Pruss (Baylor) and OUTSIDE THE ACADEMY Peter van Inwagen (Notre Dame) Peter Kreeft (Boston College) THE PROBLEM OF EVIL Peter van Inwagen (Notre Dame) and Evan Fales (University of Iowa) http://www.stthomas.edu/philosophy/templeton/project.html Twenty participants will be selected; each will receive a stipend of $2,800 and will be provided with accommodations and meals for the duration of the seminar. CONTACT APPLICATION DEADLINE: Dr. Michael Rota Applications must be received by December 1, 2009 St. Thomas Philosophy of Religion Project For information on how to apply, go to http://www.stthomas.edu/philosophy/templeton/project.html. Department of Philosophy, JRC 241 University of St. Thomas This program is funded by a generous grant from the John Templeton Foundation. 2115 Summit Avenue Saint Paul, MN 55105-1096 Email: [email protected] .
    [Show full text]
  • From Restricted to Full Omniscience
    Religious Studies, Page 1 of 8. f Cambridge University Press 2010 doi:10.1017/S0034412510000144 From restricted to full omniscience ALEXANDERR.PRUSS Baylor University, One Bear Place #97273, Waco, TX 76798-7273 e-mail: [email protected] Abstract: Some, notably Peter van Inwagen, in order to avoid problems with free will and omniscience, replace the condition that an omniscient being knows all true propositions with a version of the apparently weaker condition that an omniscient being knows all knowable true propositions. I shall show that the apparently weaker condition, when conjoined with uncontroversial claims and the logical closure of an omniscient being’s knowledge, still yields the claim that an omniscient being knows all true propositions. Introduction Peter van Inwagen has argued that God does not know what we shall freely do.1 But van Inwagen does not embrace open-future views on which there is no fact of the matter about what we shall freely do. There is such a fact, but on van Inwagen’s view, God does not know it. Nonetheless, van Inwagen holds that God is omniscient, because, roughly speaking, God knows every true proposition that can be known. I shall show, however, that the statement that God knows every knowable truth, as well as the precise statement of van Inwagen’s ‘tentative’ account, have the consequence that God knows every true proposition, as long as we assume that God’s knowledge is closed under conjunction and tautological consequence, together with some uncontroversial claims and, in the case of van Inwagen’s account, the non-triviality claim that the account requires an om- niscient being to now know some contingent truths.
    [Show full text]
  • The Consequence of the Consequence Argument∗
    The Consequence of the Consequence Argument∗ Marco Hausmann Abstract The aim of my paper is to compare three alternative formal reconstructions of van Inwagen's famous argument for incompati- bilism. In the first part of my paper, I examine van Inwagen's own reconstruction within a propositional modal logic. I point out that, due to the expressive limitations of his propositional modal logic, van Inwagen is unable to argue directly (that is, within his formal framework) for incompatibilism. In the second part of my paper, I suggest to reconstruct van Inwagen's argument within a first-order predicate logic. I show, however, that even though this reconstruction is not susceptible to the same objection, this reconstruction can be shown to be inconsistent (given van Inwagen's own assumptions). At the end of my paper, I suggest to reconstruct van Inwagen's argument within a quantified counterfactual logic with propositional quantifiers. I show that within this formal framework van Inwagen would not only be able to argue directly for incompatibilism, he would also be able to argue for crucial assumptions of his argument. Keywords: free will, determinism, consequence argument, counter- factual logic 1 Introduction Incompatibilism, as I understand it, is the view that there is no free will if determinism is true. Peter van Inwagen has developed a much discussed argument for incompatibilism. His argument runs as follows: ∗This paper won the SOPhiA 2019 Best Paper Award at the Salzburg Conference for Young Analytic Philosophy, September 18{20, 2019. Kriterion { Journal of Philosophy, 2020, 34(4): 45{70. http://www.kriterion-journal-of-philosophy.org c 2020 The author 46 KRITERION { Journal of Philosophy, 2020, 34(4): 45{70 If determinism is true, then our acts are the consequences " of the laws of nature and events in the remote past.
    [Show full text]
  • On Two Problems of Divine Simplicity by Alexander Pruss
    7 On Two Problems of Divine Simplicity Alexander R. Pruss I. INTRODUCTION The doctrine of divine simplicity claims that there is no ontological composition in God of any sort, whether of matter and form, or of essence and accident, or of this attribute and that attribute considered as ontologically distinct. The doctrine is a traditional part of Christianity and Judaism, and can be argued to be a reasonable development of the monotheistic ideal of seeing a single entity at the root of reality. Thus Maimonedes (1956: Part I, Chapter 50) wrote that ‘[t]hose who believe that God is One, and has many attributes, declare the unity with their lips, and assume plurality in their thoughts’, which he said was as bad as the case of Christians with their doctrine of the Trinity. While I disagree that the doctrine of the Trinity would violate the basic ideals of monotheism, Maimonedes may be right that the denial of the doctrine of simplicity would. However it is not my point here to argue for the doctrine of divine simplicity, but to defend it against two major objections. For, divine simplicity, like the complementary doctrine of the Trinity, does lead to intellectual difficulties. I want to consider two objections in particular, and argue that thinking in terms of an account of divine simplicity that was introduced by Graham Oppy (2003), and later independently developed by Bergmann and Brower (forthcoming)¹ as well as Pruss I am grateful to the audience for the discussion at my presentation at the Society of Christian Philosophers satellite session at the American Catholic Philosophical Association annual meeting in 2003.
    [Show full text]
  • A Measure of Change Brittany A
    University of South Carolina Scholar Commons Theses and Dissertations Spring 2019 Time: A Measure of Change Brittany A. Gentry Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarcommons.sc.edu/etd Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Gentry, B. A.(2019). Time: A Measure of Change. (Doctoral dissertation). Retrieved from https://scholarcommons.sc.edu/etd/5247 This Open Access Dissertation is brought to you by Scholar Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Scholar Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Time: A Measure of Change By Brittany A. Gentry Bachelor of Arts Houghton College, 2009 ________________________________________________ Submitted in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements For the Degree of Doctor of Philosophy in Philosophy College of Arts and Sciences University of South Carolina 2019 Accepted by Michael Dickson, Major Professor Leah McClimans, Committee Member Thomas Burke, Committee Member Alexander Pruss, Committee Member Cheryl L. Addy, Vice Provost and Dean of the Graduate School ©Copyright by Brittany A. Gentry, 2019 All Rights Reserved ii Acknowledgements I would like to thank Michael Dickson, my dissertation advisor, for extensive comments on numerous drafts over the last several years and for his patience and encouragement throughout this process. I would also like to thank my other committee members, Leah McClimans, Thomas Burke, and Alexander Pruss, for their comments and recommendations along the way. Finally, I am grateful to fellow students and professors at the University of South Carolina, the audience at the International Society for the Philosophy of Time conference at Wake Forest University, NC, and anonymous reviewers for helpful comments on various drafts of portions of this dissertation.
    [Show full text]
  • Marketing Fragment 6 X 10.5.T65
    Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-85531-0 - Alvin Plantinga Edited by Deane-Peter Baker Frontmatter More information Alvin Plantinga Few thinkers have had as much impact on contemporary philosophy as has Alvin Plantinga. The work of this quintessential analytic philosopher has in many respects set the tone for the debate in the fields of modal metaphysics and epistemology, and he is arguably the most important philosopher of religion of our time. In this volume, a distinguished team of today’s leading philoso- phers address the central aspects of Plantinga’s philosophy – his views on nat- ural theology, his responses to the problem of evil, his contributions to the field of modal metaphysics, the controversial evolutionary argument against naturalism, his model of epistemic warrant and his view of epistemic defeat, his argument for warranted Christian belief, his response to the challenge of religious pluralism, and his recent work on mind-body dualism. Also included is an appendix containing Plantinga’s often referred to, but previously unpub- lished, lecture notes entitled “Two Dozen (or so) Theistic Arguments,” with a substantial preface to the appendix written by Plantinga specifically for this volume. Deane-Peter Baker is a Senior Lecturer in the School of Philosophy and Ethics at the University of KwaZulu-Natal (South Africa). He is the author of Tayloring Reformed Epistemology: Charles Taylor, Alvin Plantinga and the De Jure Challenge to Christian Belief. © Cambridge University Press www.cambridge.org Cambridge University Press 978-0-521-85531-0 - Alvin Plantinga Edited by Deane-Peter Baker Frontmatter More information Contemporary Philosophy in Focus Contemporary Philosophy in Focus offers a series of introductory volumes to many of the dominant philosophical thinkers of the current age.
    [Show full text]
  • The Ontological Argument and the Motivational Centres of Lives
    Religious Studies (2010) 46, 233–249 f Cambridge University Press 2010 doi:10.1017/S0034412509990400 The ontological argument and the motivational centres of lives ALEXANDERR.PRUSS Department of Philosophy, Baylor University, One Bear Place #97273, Waco, TX 76798-7273 e-mail: [email protected] Abstract: Assuming S5, the main controversial premise in modal ontological arguments is the possibility premise, such as that possibly a maximally great being exists. I shall offer a new way of arguing that the possibility premise is probably true. Introduction Alvin Plantinga’s maximally great being (MGB) argument (Plantinga (1978), chapter 10) is, essentially: (1) Necessarily, if x is a maximally great being, then x exists in all possible worlds and is perfectly good, omnipotent, omniscient and creator of any and all contingent beings in every world.1 [Premise] (2) It is possible that there exists a maximally great being. [Premise] (3) Therefore, there exists a being that is perfectly good, omnipotent, omniscient and creator of any and all contingent beings in every world. [From (1) and (2) by S5] Assuming a modal logic that includes S5, the argument is valid. The main con- troversial premise is the possibility premise (2). I will now offer a new way to make the possibility premise epistemically probable. If it is epistemically prob- able, then the conclusion of the argument is also epistemically probable, and hence probably there is a maximally great being. For brevity, I shall stipulate the term ‘creator’ for ‘creator of all contingent beings, if there are any’. Thus, a MGB is trivially a creator in worlds where there are no contingent beings.
    [Show full text]
  • A Defense of Intellectualism: Will, Intellect, and Control in Late Thirteenth-Century Philosophy
    A Defense of Intellectualism: Will, Intellect, and Control in Late Thirteenth-century Philosophy by Michael Szlachta A thesis submitted in conformity with the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy University of Toronto © Copyright by Michael Szlachta 2019 A Defense of Intellectualism: Will, Intellect, and Control in Late Thirteenth-century Philosophy Michael Szlachta Doctor of Philosophy Department of Philosophy University of Toronto 2019 Abstract The question of whether our volitions are caused by the activity of our cognitive powers was the subject of tremendous controversy for medieval philosophers. By answering in the affirmative, Thomas Aquinas, Thomas of Sutton and Godfrey of Fontaines, the so-called intellectualists, face what I call the Problem of Control. If my wanting some object is caused by my apprehending it as good through some cognitive act, then it seems that I am not able to will otherwise than I do. For to will otherwise than I do, it would be necessary that I apprehend some other object as good. If, however, I am not able to will otherwise than I do, then I do not seem to have control over my actions. But if I do not have control over my actions, then I do not act freely, since having control over one’s actions is necessary for acting freely. My dissertation addresses the Problem of Control. I first argue that Thomas Aquinas’s notion of “perfect cognition of the end” gives the intellectualists the resources to explain how a human being has control over her actions. Second, I argue that Aquinas does not adequately explain a central feature of his intellectualism, namely, how the will “moves itself” to the exercise of its act, and discuss how the “self-motion” of the will is addressed by Thomas of Sutton and Godfrey of Fontaines.
    [Show full text]
  • Is an Open Infinite Future Impossible? a Reply to Pruss
    Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers Volume 37 Issue 3 Article 6 7-1-2020 Is an Open Infinite uturF e Impossible? A Reply to Pruss Elijah Hess Alan Rhoda Follow this and additional works at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy Recommended Citation Hess, Elijah and Rhoda, Alan (2020) "Is an Open Infinite uturF e Impossible? A Reply to Pruss," Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers: Vol. 37 : Iss. 3 , Article 6. DOI: 10.37977/faithphil.2020.37.3.6 Available at: https://place.asburyseminary.edu/faithandphilosophy/vol37/iss3/6 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Journals at ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. It has been accepted for inclusion in Faith and Philosophy: Journal of the Society of Christian Philosophers by an authorized editor of ePLACE: preserving, learning, and creative exchange. applyparastyle "fig//caption/p[1]" parastyle "FigCapt" applyparastyle "fig" parastyle "Figure" AQ1–AQ5 IS AN OPEN INFINITE FUTURE IMPOSSIBLE? A REPLY TO PRUSS Elijah Hess and Alan Rhoda Alexander Pruss has recently argued on probabilistic grounds that Christian philosophers should reject Open Futurism—roughly, the thesis that there are no true future contingents—on account of this view’s alleged inability to han- dle certain statements about infinite futures in a mathematically or religiously adequate manner. We argue that, once the distinction between being true and becoming true is applied to such statements, it is evident
    [Show full text]