Bernstein on the Pragmatic Conception of Objectivity

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Bernstein on the Pragmatic Conception of Objectivity Six RELATIVISM, GOOD AND BAD: BERNSTEIN ON THE PRAGMATIC CONCEPTION OF OBJECTIVITY Ángel M. Faerna George Santayana once condemned “the modern scramble of philosophies” for not having learned enough of one another.1 Once a philosopher has gained mastery of a particular system, method, or vocabulary, it becomes difficult for her to grasp, let alone to appreciate, the value of alternative approaches to similar problems. Moreover, she also quickly forgets how strange or whimsical the ideas she wholeheartedly endorses and promotes may sound to philosophers of a different breed. The more she tries to refine those ideas from within her own frame of thought, the more abstruse they seem to those who consider them from outside. Richard Bernstein is a noteworthy exception to this predicament of contemporary philosophy. On one hand, he staunchly upholds the tradition of American pragmatism and is an authoritative interpreter of its classic and more recent developments. On the other hand, he has developed the rare ability to cross the borders and grasp the wider picture because of his acquaintance with all the major thinkers of the twentieth century. That vantage point allows Bernstein to discern the continuity between pragmatism and other apparently disconnected trends in philosophy, which admittedly is one of his perdurable contributions. However, this “peripheral vision” also benefits Bernstein’s case for pragmatism in another way, since it enables him to identify the pragmatic notes that unfamiliar ears often find dissonant just because they are played in a harsh, confrontational key. Bernstein is convinced that the spirit of pragmatism is much more constructive than “deconstructive,” and that pragmatist motives and themes are more apt to fertilize rather than disrupt philosophical conversations if those notes are cleverly downplayed or re-phrased. Thus, by smoothing over the friction between alternative vocabularies Bernstein’s work lends an invaluable service to the philosophic community and fosters a dialog where different traditions can learn more from each other. In these pages I shall comment briefly on one of the topics on which Bernstein has made a serious effort to make the pragmatist views fully understandable, namely, the objectivism/relativism debate. The impression that pragmatism is somehow incompatible with the idea of “objectivity” has 96 ÁNGEL M. FAERNA been prevalent among its critics since the very beginning. In the early years of the movement the issue used to be stated in metaphysical terms to suggest that pragmatists denied the existence of objects external to our experience of them.2 Thereafter the discussion turned mainly epistemological, so that the objectivism/idealism opposition was replaced by the opposition of objectivism/relativism. Another important difference is that, while James protested that none of his pragmatist fellows (such as Dewey and Schiller) incurred the reprehensible idealism that their critics imputed to them, in the present day the house seems to be divided against itself. Some contemporary versions of pragmatism, notably Rorty’s, are seen by other reputed members of the school —not only by those who utterly repudiate the pragmatic approach— as openly relativist. Other versions, such as Putnam’s, try to emphasize their objectivist commitment but raise criticism for being timid or too concessive.3 In “Pragmatism, Objectivity, and Truth,”4 Bernstein puts aside these local quarrels and addresses the central point: how is “objectivity” to be conceived in pragmatic terms? This is not to ignore the fact that pragmatism “encompasses a variety of different and conflicting positions”5 —therefore the existing disagreements will largely remain within it— nor is it expected that recalcitrant critics of pragmatism will be content with the type of objectivity that pragmatism is ready to offer. Bernstein’s concern, as I take it, is only to show that being a pragmatist is not a matter of refusing to use terms such as “objectivity” or “truth” —though, of course, some pragmatists may prefer to avoid them for different reasons—, but is a matter of explaining in a certain way what we mean when we use them. After all, pragmatism was introduced by Peirce as a method only to make our ideas clear. Now, pragmatists are persuaded that, once the clarification is made it will become evident that the opposition of objectivism/relativism is confusing in some fundamental ways. In the light of this, one can recommend dropping it altogether or, less provocatively, one can decide to preserve it in the hope that its confusing connotations have finally been eradicated. The fact that Bernstein himself has rehearsed both strategies at different times without falling into contradictions shows that the choice is essentially innocuous.6 For one thing, the opposition between objectivism and relativism is confusing because it overlooks the fact that there are good as well as bad forms of relativism. By “bad relativism,” Bernstein means “the sort of relativism that claims that there is really no truth (except truth for me or my group), no objective facts, and no universal validity claims.”7 But —Bernstein adds— “there are many positive ways to speak about the relativity of contexts, justifications, and language that are not controversial and do not entail the consequences of ‘bad relativism.’”8 That something can be both objective and relative can hardly be denied. For instance, length and weight are objective properties of things, and still they can only be described .
Recommended publications
  • 1The Strengths and Limits of Philosophical Anarchism
    THE STRENGTHS AND LIMITS OF 1 PHILOSOPHICAL ANARCHISM THE BASIC DEFINITION of state legitimacy as the exclusive right to make, apply, and enforce laws is common, clearly visible in Max Weber and contemporary political philosophy and found less explicitly in the classical contract thinkers.1 A. John Simmons, drawing on Locke, writes that “A state’s (or government’s) legitimacy is the complex moral right it possesses to be the exclusive imposer of binding duties on its sub- jects, to have its subjects comply with these duties, and to use coercion to enforce the duties” (Simmons 2001, 130). Similar definitions—whether vis-à-vis legitimacy or authority—with slight alterations of terms and in conjunction with a series of other ideas and conditions (for example, “authoritativeness,” background criteria, the difference between force and violence) can be found in Robert Paul Wolff (1998, 4), Joseph Raz (2009), Richard Flathman (1980), Leslie Green (1988), David Copp (1999), Hannah Pitkin (1965, 1966), and others. The point is that the justification of state legitimacy and the (corresponding) obligation to obey involve, more often than not, making, applying, and enforcing laws: political power. Often left out of these discussions—with important exceptions—are the real practices of legitimate statehood, and perhaps for good reason. What philosophers who explore the question of legitimacy and authority are most often interested in—for a variety of reasons—is the relation of the individ- ual to the state, that is, whether and to what extent a citizen (or sometimes a noncitizen) has an obligation to obey the state. As Raz notes, part of the explanation for this is that contemporary philosophical interest in questions of political obligation emerged in response to political events in the 1960s (Raz 1981, 105).
    [Show full text]
  • Jay: an Intimate Martyr of Objectivism Jordan Miller
    First Class: A Journal of First-Year Composition Volume 2017 Article 5 Spring 2017 Jay: An Intimate Martyr of Objectivism Jordan Miller Follow this and additional works at: https://ddc.duq.edu/first-class Recommended Citation Miller, J. (2017). Jay: An Intimate Martyr of Objectivism. First Class: A Journal of First-Year Composition, 2017 (1). Retrieved from https://ddc.duq.edu/first-class/vol2017/iss1/5 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by Duquesne Scholarship Collection. It has been accepted for inclusion in First Class: A Journal of First-Year Composition by an authorized editor of Duquesne Scholarship Collection. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Honors Program Second Prize Essay JAY: AN INTIMATE MARTYR OF OBJECTIVISM By Jordan Miller Instructor: Dr. Matthew Ussia “At the dawn of our lives, we seek a noble vision of man’s nature and of life’s potential” (“Introduction”). According to Ayn Rand, Russian-American novelist and philosopher, Objectivism is that vision. This credo rests in the foundation that reality exists and one must discover its nature with an audacious approach of self-serving ambition. Although it has received a fair amount of following, praise, and success, Rand’s philosophy has also sourced the demise of many individuals through broken promises and mental pandemonium. The life and mental state of Jay, a broken man from the novel Intimacy by Hanif Kureishi, serves to thoroughly exemplify the philosophy’s imperfections and the reasoning behind one’s downfall on the path of Objectivism. Throughout the novel, his character development, or lack thereof, constitutes as the paradigm for an Objectivist breakdown.
    [Show full text]
  • Winds and Tigers: Metaphor Choice in China's Anti-Corruption Discourse
    Jing-Schmidt and Peng Lingua Sinica (2017) 3:2 DOI 10.1186/s40655-016-0017-9 RESEARCH Open Access Winds and tigers: metaphor choice in China’s anti-corruption discourse Zhuo Jing-Schmidt* and Xinjia Peng * Correspondence: [email protected] Abstract University of Oregon, Eugene ’ 97403, OR, USA This article examines metaphor choice in China s official anti-corruption discourse. Drawing on corpus data, we analyze the metaphors used by the Chinese Communist Party and its flagship newspaper, the People’s Daily, to frame the anti-corruption campaign and influence public perception. It is found that both embodied experience and cultural models are recruited as the metaphoric vehicles or source domains for the strategic profiling of different aspects of corruption and anti- corruption actions as the target domain. Additionally, metaphor choice is systematically different in the Chinese and the English versions of the party newspaper, reflecting that metaphor use is sensitive to sociocultural context, especially to the knowledge base within an epistemic community. Keywords: China, Anti-corruption campaign, Metaphor choice, Political discourse 1 Background During the transition from a planned economy to a market economy in the last three decades, China has experienced what many scholars call an “economic miracle.” At the same time, Chinese society is faced with “an extraordinary and serious epidemic of cor- ruption” (Meng 2014: 33). There seems to be a consensus among China scholars that the reforms that brought about liberalization and commercialization, and fueled the economic boom, also drove the surge of corruption by providing fertile soil for its rampant growth (Gong 2002, 2006; Guo 2008).
    [Show full text]
  • Objectivism/Subjectivism in Scientific Articles of Different Areas: the Heterogeneity of Academic Writing
    OBJETIVISMO/SUBJETIVISMO EM ARTIGOS CIENTÍFICOS DAS DIFERENTES ÁREAS: A HETEROGENEIDADE DA ESCRITA ACADÊMICA Ângela Francine FUZA* ▪ RESUMO: A existência do discurso que postula a homogeneização da escrita acadêmico- científica no processo de constituição do texto é a problemática que desencadeou esta pesquisa. Nesse sentido, o objetivo deste estudo é analisar artigos científicos brasileiros de periódicos A1 das diferentes áreas do conhecimento a partir dos elementos que constituem os gêneros, forma composicional, estilo e temática, delimitando aspectos que tendem ao objetivismo e ao subjetivismo nos textos. O trabalho se pauta nos pressupostos dialógicos do Círculo de Bakhtin, no tocante aos gêneros, ao objetivismo e subjetivismo, e nas pesquisas desenvolvidas segundo os princípios dos Novos Estudos do Letramento. Os resultados apontam que: a) todo enunciado é constituído de elementos subjetivos e objetivos; b) os aspectos que evidenciam objetividade e subjetividade marcam-se predominantemente na forma composicional (e arquitetônica) e no estilo dos textos, em diálogo com a temática; c) os artigos das diferentes áreas se assemelham, ao tratar de elementos que tendem à objetividade, como forma composicional e recursos linguísticos; d) os artigos diferem quando apresentam aspectos que, embora estejam na materialidade verbal, encontram significação no contexto extraverbal, perpassando a subjetividade, como escolha temática; variação no número de autores no texto etc.; e) a existência de nuances de objetividade e de subjetividade permite caracterizar a escrita nas áreas de forma heterogênea. ▪ PALAVRAS-CHAVE: Objetivismo. Subjetivismo. Escrita acadêmica. Artigo científico. Introdução A escrita acadêmico-científica tem sido um tema amplamente discutido no meio acadêmico por pesquisadores do campo dos estudos da linguagem em seus vários âmbitos e perspectivas metodológicas.
    [Show full text]
  • Aristotle and Kant on the Source of Value
    Aristotle and Kant on the Source of Value The Harvard community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters Citation Korsgaard, Christine. 1986. Aristotle and Kant on the source of value. Ethics 96(3): 486-505. Published Version http://dx.doi.org/10.1086/292771 Citable link http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:3164347 Terms of Use This article was downloaded from Harvard University’s DASH repository, and is made available under the terms and conditions applicable to Other Posted Material, as set forth at http:// nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:dash.current.terms-of- use#LAA Aristotle and Kant on the Source of Value* ChristineM. Korsgaard THREE KINDS OF VALUE THEORY In this paper I discuss what I will call a "rationalist" account of the goodness of ends. I begin by contrasting the rationalist account to two others, "subjectivism' and "objectivism.' Subjectivism identifies good ends with or by reference to some psychological state. It includes the various forms of hedonism as well as theories according to which what is good is any object of interest or desire. Objectivism may be represented by the theory of G. E. Moore. According to Moore, to say that something is good as an end is to attribute a property, intrinsic goodness, to it. Intrinsic goodness is an objective, nonrelational property of the object, a value a thing has independently of anyone's desires, interests, or pleasures. The attraction of subjectivist views is that they acknowledge the connection of the good to human interests and desires.
    [Show full text]
  • Liberalism and the Objectivity of Ethics - Beyond Subjective Morality: Ethical Reasoning and Political Philosophy
    Louisiana Law Review Volume 47 | Number 5 Student Symposium: Conflict of Laws in Louisiana May 1987 Liberalism and the Objectivity of Ethics - Beyond Subjective Morality: Ethical Reasoning and Political Philosophy. By James S. Fishkin.* New Haven : Yale University Press, 1984. Pp. vii, 201. $14.95. George C. Freeman III Repository Citation George C. Freeman III, Liberalism and the Objectivity of Ethics - Beyond Subjective Morality: Ethical Reasoning and Political Philosophy. By James S. Fishkin.* New Haven : Yale University Press, 1984. Pp. vii, 201. $14.95., 47 La. L. Rev. (1987) Available at: https://digitalcommons.law.lsu.edu/lalrev/vol47/iss5/15 This Book Review is brought to you for free and open access by the Law Reviews and Journals at LSU Law Digital Commons. It has been accepted for inclusion in Louisiana Law Review by an authorized editor of LSU Law Digital Commons. For more information, please contact [email protected]. BOOK REVIEW LIBERALISM AND THE OBJECTIVITY OF ETHICS Beyond Subjective Morality: Ethical Reasoning and Political Phi- losophy. By James S. Fishkin.* New Haven : Yale University Press, 1984. Pp. vii, 201. $14.95. George C. Freeman, III** "What is the aim of your philosophy?-To show the fly the way out of the bottle." Ludwig Wittgenstein' James Fiskin's latest book, Beyond Subjective Morality, focuses on a question of profound significance: "Independent of particular religious and metaphysical assumptions-assumptions among which a modern lib- eral state must presumably maintain a certain neutrality-can there be a
    [Show full text]
  • Objectivism: Ayn Rand's Personal Philosophy
    Objectivism: Ayn Rand’s Personal Philosophy These notes are taken from The Reader’s Guide to the Writings and Philosophy of Ayn Rand found at the end of Centennial Editions of Anthem. Ayn Rand provides a nutshell version of Objectivism by describing four aspects of it: Metaphysics the philosophy of what constitutes REALITY (How do we know what reality is?) Epistemology the philosophy of knowledge (How do we know what we know?) Ethics the philosophy of how we determine what is right vs. wrong, fair vs. unfair Politics the philosophy of how we govern groups of people Objectivism holds the following ideas: Metaphysics Objective Reality Epistemology Reason Ethics Self-Interest Politics Capitalism A further exploration of the ideas: Metaphysics Objective Reality Rand agrees with Naturalism in that reality is observable and measurable. There is one reality. She disagrees with Modernism in that Modernists believe in Subjective Reality, the idea that humans CREATE reality through their perceptions. Rand says that our only ability is to perceive reality, not create it. “facts are facts” This believe precludes (makes impossible) a belief in the supernatural. Epistemology Reason Rand agrees with the Enlightenment that we should use reason to achieve our goals. She holds that reason is man’s highest virtue. Other ways of “knowing what we know” is through faith, tradition, and intuition, none of which she would deem valid methods of “knowing.” Ethics Self-Interest Rand believes wholly in acting upon one’s self-interest. No one should sacrifice himself for others or sacrifice others for himself. This idea would preclude any altruistic acts.
    [Show full text]
  • A Philosophical Approach to Business Education
    The Canadian Journal of Higher Education, Vol. XXII-2, 1992 La revue canadienne d'enseignement supérieur, Vol. XXII-2, 1992 A Philosophical Approach to Business Education JAANA WOICESHYN * Abstract Business education has been blamed for deficiencies in the leadership, decision- making and ethical conduct of business managers. The quantitative and analyti- cal orientation in business school curricula and the consequent lack of humani- ties-based courses have been identified as reasons. The fundamental reason, however, lies in the philosophy of business research and education which shapes the curricula, teaching methods, and ultimately the graduates' ability to handle various managerial functions. The most commonly recognized philosophical basis of business research is empiricism. The argument presented here is that pragmatism, which shares ele- ments with empiricism, has also significantly shaped business education. This paper is an attempt to show why empiricism, together with pragmatism, are the root causes of the above deficiencies. Supplementing business school curricula with humanities courses, a strategy often recommended to correct for the defi- ciencies, is not sufficient. As an alternative solution, an objective philosophical approach is evaluated, along with its practical implications for business educa- tion. Résumé La formation en administration est souvent blâmée pour les lacunes rencon- trées chez les gentionnaires en regard des habiletés de chef de file et de prise de décision, et par-rapport à l'éthique professionelle. On attribue généralement ces lacunes à l'orientation strictement quantitative et analytique des pro- grammes d'études et à l'absence de contenus provenant des disciplines des let- tres et des sciences humaines. Cette communication, cependant, suggère que ces lacunes s'expliquent avant tout par la philosophie sous-jacente à la recherche en administration et en éducation sur laquelle reposent les pro- grammes d'etudes, les méthodes d'enseignement, et utimement, les habiletés des * University of Calgary.
    [Show full text]
  • Pragmatism, Constructivism and Socratic Objectivity: the Pragmatist Epistemic Aim of Philosophy for Children
    Pragmatism, constructivism and Socratic objectivity: The pragmatist epistemic aim of Philosophy for Children CLINTON GOLDING University of Melbourne Abstract It will be shown in this paper that the epistemic aim of Philosophy for Children should be understood in pragmatist terms. It argues that Philosophy for Children, as a practice of dialogical inquiry, falls in the middle of a continuum from constructivist through to Socratic objectivist epistemic aims. Philosophy for Children shares the constructivist aim of creation but it also shares the Socratic aim of discovery. The epistemic aim of P4C however, is not to discover the objective truth or to construct subjectively acceptable views, but to discover and create tentative, fallible views that make sense of philosophical problems we currently face. As such, Philosophy for Children is best described as pragmatist. The epistemic aim of Philosophy for Children is to create and discover views that work to resolve philosophical problems. This paper explores what type of philosophical knowledge students obtain from Philosophy for Children classes. I call this the epistemic aim of Philosophy for Children. Philosophy for Children starts with philosophical questions problematic for, and often generated by, students. The epistemic aim is to resolve these problems. I will argue that this aim can be situated in the middle of the continuum from constructivist to objectivist epistemological aims. I base my analysis on the description of constructivism and Socratic inquiry by Boghossian (2006), in a recent paper in Educational Philosophy and Theory. Although Boghossian seems to see these as two distinct positions, it is better to see them as the ends of the spectrum from subjective through to objective epistemic aims, from creation through to discovery.
    [Show full text]
  • Ralph Raico: Champion of Authentic Liberalism Daniel P
    State University of New York College at Buffalo - Buffalo State College Digital Commons at Buffalo State History Theses History and Social Studies Education 12-2012 Ralph Raico: Champion of Authentic Liberalism Daniel P. Stanford [email protected] Advisor Gary Marotta, Ph.D., Professor of History First Reader Gary Marotta, Ph.D., Professor of History Second Reader John D. Abromeit, Ph.D., Assistant Professor of History Department Chair Andrew D. Nicholls, Ph.D., Professor of History To learn more about the History and Social Studies Education Department and its educational programs, research, and resources, go to http://history.buffalostate.edu/. Recommended Citation Stanford, Daniel P., "Ralph Raico: Champion of Authentic Liberalism" (2012). History Theses. Paper 13. Follow this and additional works at: http://digitalcommons.buffalostate.edu/history_theses Part of the European History Commons, Intellectual History Commons, and the United States History Commons Ralph Raico: Champion of Authentic Liberalism by Daniel P. Stanford An Abstract of a Thesis in History Submitted in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of Master of Arts December 2012 College at Buffalo State University of New York Department of History 1 ABSTRACT OF THESIS Ralph Raico: Champion of Authentic Liberalism This paper explores the intellectual life and writings of Professor Emeritus in History at Buffalo State College, Ralph Raico. The central thesis seeks to portray Professor Raico as the great modern libertarian revisionist historian, and the great modern champion of historical, classical liberalism. More broadly, the work attempts to solidify Professor Raico’s reputation as a major figure in the modern American libertarian movement. Raico’s intellectual foundations are fully developed, beginning from grade school at Bronx High School of Science, to his attendance of Ludwig von Mises’s New York University seminar, to his P.h.D.
    [Show full text]
  • Absolutism, Utilitarianism, and Moral Military Decision Making. Kristine V
    University of Massachusetts Amherst ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst Masters Theses 1911 - February 2014 1999 Absolutism, utilitarianism, and moral military decision making. Kristine V. Nakutis University of Massachusetts Amherst Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.umass.edu/theses Nakutis, Kristine V., "Absolutism, utilitarianism, and moral military decision making." (1999). Masters Theses 1911 - February 2014. 2554. Retrieved from https://scholarworks.umass.edu/theses/2554 This thesis is brought to you for free and open access by ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst. It has been accepted for inclusion in Masters Theses 1911 - February 2014 by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst. For more information, please contact [email protected]. ABSOLUTISM, UTILITARIANISM, AND MORAL MILITARY DECISION MAKING A Thesis Presented by KRISTINE V. NAKUTIS Submitted to the Graduate School of the University of Massachusetts Amherst in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of MASTER OF ARTS September 1999 Philosophy - ABSOLUTISM, UTILITARIANISM, AND MORAL MILITARY DECISION MAKING A Thesis Presented by KRISTINE VARNUM NAKUTIS Approved as to style and content by: ^7 (— Fred Feldman, Chair i/eth B. Matthews, Member olftn G. Robison, Department Head department of Philosophy TABLE OF CONTENTS CHAPTER Page 1. UTILITARIANISM AND WAR ... 1 Introduction... .. 1 Utilitarianism War ..2 ..5 U.S. Catholic Bishop View of War Combatants versus Non-Combatants 2. NAGEL’S ABSOLUTISM AND UTILITARIANISM Means and Ends 18 Straightforward Utilitarianism 20 What is Absolutism? 22 Technical Matters 26 Absolutist Restriction on Warfare 28 Class of Persons 28 Manner of Attack on Specific Classes of Persons 33 Utilitarianism and Absolutist Conflict 38 3. BRANDT’S RULE-UTILITARIANISM Nagel’s “Absolutism” 43 Morally Justifiable Rules 47 Utilitarian Rules 49 Rules Restricting Military Operations 52 Rules of War and Morality 60 4.
    [Show full text]
  • Vrasidas, C. (2000). Constructivism Versus Objectivism: Implications for Interaction, Course Design, and Evaluation in Distance Education
    International Journal of Educational Telecommunications 1 CONSTRUCTIVISM VERSUS OBJECTIVISM: With the development of new technologies, such as IMPLICATIONS FOR INTERACTION, COURSE DESIGN, interactive television and computer conferencing, distance AND EVALUATION IN DISTANCE EDUCATION. educators can approach the design of courses and delivery of Charalambos Vrasidas curricula following a less objectivist and a more constructivist Center for the Application of information Technologies approach (Dede, 1996; Eastmond & Ziegahn, 1996; Tuckey, Western Illinois University 1993). As Harasim (1996) argued, online education shifts "the Abstract focus from knowledge transmission to knowledge building" (p. This paper discusses the basic philosophical assumptions of objectivism and 205). Computer networks shift the role of the teacher from constructivism including their implications for course design, interaction, knowledge transmitter to that of a facilitator who provides and evaluation in distance education. First, I provide a brief overview of ample opportunities for interaction and meaning-making to all the construct of interaction as it is used in the field of distance education. Second, I address the major philosophical ideas of objectivism and learners. Before discussing the two philosophical paradigms of constructivism as they relate to education. Third, I discuss how curriculum objectivism and constructivism, I will discuss the construct of designers from each paradigm design a distance education course. Finally, interaction as it relates to distance education. I compare and contrast the two approaches to distance education course design and provide suggestions for practitioners. Interaction: A fundamental process for learning Interaction is one of the most important components of any A modified version of this paper has been published in the International learning experience (Dewey, 1938; Vygotsky, 1978) and it has Journal of Educational Telecommunications.
    [Show full text]