FOREWORD to the PRINCETON CLASSICS EDITION Politics And

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

FOREWORD to the PRINCETON CLASSICS EDITION Politics And FOREWORD TO THE PRINCETON CLASSICS EDITION ••• Politics and Vision: Continuity and Innovation in Political Thoughtis both one and two books, written by both one and two political theorists. A changed world and changed thinker divides the 1960 edition from the 2004 expanded edition, the latter now ap- pearing as a Princeton Classic. First published when Sheldon S. Wolin was a young Berkeley professor, Politics and Vision quickly rose to prominence for its luminous interpretations of canoni- cal theorists and probing reflections on the shifting meaning and status of politics and political theory across Western history. A scholarly work of breathtaking scope composed in accessible literary cadences, it was exemplary of what Wolin would term “political theory as a vocation” in his 1969 essay by that name.1 Intentionally recalling Max Weber’s stipulations for scholarship and political leadership in his “Vocations” essays, and especially Weber’s contrast between career and calling, Wo- lin’s formulation of theory as a vocation distinguished political theory’s classic value from current disciplinary conventions. He sought especially to reestablish political theory’s longstanding concerns with res publicae and res gestae—concerns he termed as “irreducible and natural to the political theorist as a concern for health is to the physician.”2 With its immense erudition and close readings trained on the problematic of “the political,” Politics and Vision embodied Wolin’s insistence on political theory as “pri- marily a civic and secondarily an academic activity…a critical engagement with col- lective existence and with the political experiences of power to which it gives rise.”3 This tasking of political theory invites the sort of reading Wolin frequently performed when he taught. Here is how we might open up that formulation as Wolin did with phrases from Plato, Machiavelli, and Hobbes: Political theory is primarily civic, mean- ing “of or belonging to a city,” and “related to citizenship.” It is thus not only about but for the polity, informing citizenship and itself a certain practice of citizenship. Political theory does not describe, quantify, model, or predict behaviors and makes no pretense to objectivity. Rather, it is critically engaged with its particular object, “collec- tive existence and the political experiences of power to which it gives rise.” Here power is not an independent substrate, reducible to a unified, let alone consistent, concept, nor is it simply won or lost, held or wielded. Rather, power is generated by particular xvi FOREWORD TO THE PRINCETON CLASSICS EDITION (historical) human collectivities and, for that reason, has protean and diverse forms and faces. More than a tool or force, power is also politically experienced—whether as order, democracy, authority, subordination, capacity, possibility, or containment. Wolin’s performative account of political theory thus moves against dominant schol- arly trends by staking its engaged nature and emphasizing the historically molten and power-saturated qualities of its object, political life.4 Only against the backdrop of political theory’s predicaments in the two eras in which Wolin authored both the original and the expanded edition of Politics and Vi- sion can we fathom the radicalism of this brief for political theory as a shape-shifting activity—critically, actively engaging the historically generated and generative powers of organized collective life. The first edition led political theory back to politics; the second back to critique. Both sought to renew the vitality, complexity, historical illu- mination, and poetics of political theory for students, teachers, scholars, and educated citizens. In 1960, political theory as a domain of inquiry and approach to political un- derstanding was a candidate for the dustbin of history. In the social sciences, its bid for knowledge through historical and philosophical reflection was displaced if not disputed by growing positivism, empiricism, and behaviorism in the social sciences. Philosophy was speedily consolidating into its analytic and Continental branches, and the former—which governed in the English-speaking world—withdrew sharply from inquiry that was either historically conscious or concerned with the distinct problem- atic of political power rather than morality. The quivering remains of a genre of in- sight fundamentally oriented by canonical political theory could be found only in the cloistered hermeneutics of Leo Strauss and the dry history of ideas of George Sabine. Onto this parched landscape came Politics and Vision, with its insistence that “po- litical theory is not so much interested in political practices, or how they operate, but in their meaning” (7), that it posts “warnings” rather than “predictions” (14), and that it is at once a theorist’s interpretation of the world and an imaginative project of seeing beyond facticity in order to build a complex “political metaphysic” (16). Imagination, Wolin argued, “is the theorist’s means for understanding a world he can never ‘know’ in an intimate way” (19). In addition to challenging the reigning proposition that such a world could be understood through quantitative measurement, Wolin took aim at the fact/norm distinction governing political science: imagination is also “the medium for expressing the fundamental values of the theorist…the means by which the politi- cal theorist has sought to transcend history” (19). Above all, Politics and Vision insisted on political theory as characterized by the perennial yet always historically configured problematics of power, order, authority, political change, conflict, law, and citizenship. When, forty-five years later, the revised and expanded edition of Politics and Vision appeared, political theory was a robust but almost wholly academic industry.5 Rescued from neglect, now its promise of worldly illumination and radical critique was choked by scholastic professionalism and two dominant frames: Skinnerian historicism for FOREWORD TO THE PRINCETON CLASSICS EDITION xvii interpreting theorists of the past, and Rawlsian analytics for contemplating (and often muting) the challenges of the present. If Skinner insisted on adducing history to read theory rather than theory to read history, Rawls lifted political philosophy from his- torical, cultural, and socio-economic context altogether. Combined, the two schools severed the history of political thought from contemporary political theory and es- tablished a governing conceit of objectivity for interpreting works of the past (and a tacit bar against using them to illuminate the present) and of rational normativity for political theories of the present (and a tacit elimination of theory as critique). Histori- cism aimed to cage the political thought of other epochs in their time, and analytic liberal theory was resolutely unhistorical and detached from concerns with power in its pursuit of normative arguments bound to neo-Kantian moral justifications. Into this scholarly orbit came Wolin’s expanded Politics and Vision, now supplement- ing examinations of the ancients, Christians, early moderns, and utilitarians with new chapters on Marx, Nietzsche, Popper, Dewey, Rawls, and theorizations of novel breeds of power that Wolin took to generate the predicaments of the contemporary epoch. The expanded edition, however, offered more than splendid new objects of interpretation by one of the great thinkers of the twentieth century; Wolin’s own vision had changed, something that was evident in the tone as well as the arguments. If the original volume was meditative, measured, and even melancholy in the warning its final chapters sound- ed about citizenship and political society disappearing into the “age of organization,” there was no such diagnostic restraint or mute on his warning bell in the 2004 volume. We are now, he insisted, in the era of Superpower, inverted totalitarianism, democracy destroyed by the corporate state, empire, the dangling citizen, deregulated markets com- bined with scandalous incarceration rates, a demos massively manipulated and “ham- mered into resignation” (578), all sealed with the irony of the ascent of Rawlsian liberal thought “just as the political fortunes of liberalism began to wane” (538). Here we are reminded that the original and expanded versions of Politics and Vision were distinguished not only by the scholarly paradigms they contested or the think- ers and problems they studied. They emerged from and spoke to disparate political eras, especially in the United States, which endured as Wolin’s main and unabashed political referent notwithstanding his familiarity with European languages, literatures, and histories. There was the Cold War versus the war on terrorism, the bureaucratic- administrative state versus the corporate-imperial state, a complacent citizenry versus a managed electorate, anxiety about a recent totalitarian past versus the “ingrafting of elitism and empire upon popular sovereignty” (599, 600). Yet there was also Wolin’s own marked intellectual-political shift between the two volumes, which he termed “a journey from liberalism to democracy” and from a concern with “interpreting the past… [to] analyzing the present,” but which also might be characterized as a journey from political theory as interpretation to political theory as critique. This journey, echoing faintly that of Tocqueville between the two volumes ofDe - mocracy in America, is as profound as it is understated by Wolin himself. Wolin re- xviii FOREWORD
Recommended publications
  • The John U. Nef Committee on Social Thought 1
    The John U. Nef Committee on Social Thought 1 The John U. Nef Committee on Social Thought Department Website: http://socialthought.uchicago.edu Chair • Robert Pippin Professors • Lorraine Daston • Wendy Doniger • Joel Isaac • Hans Joas • Gabriel Lear • Jonathan Lear • Jonathan Levy • Jean Luc Marion • Heinrich Meier • Glenn W. Most • David Nirenberg • Thomas Pavel • Mark Payne • Robert B. Pippin • Jennifer Pitts • Andrei Pop • Haun Saussy • Laura Slatkin • Nathan Tarcov • Rosanna Warren • David Wellbery Emeriti • Wendy Doniger • Leon Kass • Joel Kraemer • Ralph Lerner • James M. Redfield • David Tracy About the Committee The John U. Nef Committee on Social Thought was established as a degree granting body in 1941 by the historian John U. Nef (1899-1988), with the assistance of the economist Frank Knight, the anthropologist Robert Redfield, and Robert M. Hutchins, then President of the University. The Committee is a group of diverse scholars sharing a common concern for the unity of the human sciences. Their premises were that the serious study of any academic topic, or of any philosophical or literary work, is best prepared for by a wide and deep acquaintance with the fundamental issues presupposed in all such studies, that students should learn about these issues by acquainting themselves with a select number of classic ancient and modern texts in an inter- disciplinary atmosphere, and should only then concentrate on a specific dissertation topic. It accepts qualified graduate students seeking to pursue their particular studies within this broader context, and aims both to teach precision of scholarship and to foster awareness of the permanent questions at the origin of all learned inquiry.
    [Show full text]
  • Of Citizenship in the Age of Waning Democracy: Wolin and Balibar on Citizenship, the Political and Dedemocratization
    Citizenship Studies ISSN: 1362-1025 (Print) 1469-3593 (Online) Journal homepage: http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/ccst20 The ‘I’ and the ‘we’ of citizenship in the age of waning democracy: Wolin and Balibar on citizenship, the political and dedemocratization Robin Rodd To cite this article: Robin Rodd (2018): The ‘I’ and the ‘we’ of citizenship in the age of waning democracy: Wolin and Balibar on citizenship, the political and dedemocratization, Citizenship Studies To link to this article: https://doi.org/10.1080/13621025.2018.1449812 Published online: 12 Mar 2018. Submit your article to this journal View related articles View Crossmark data Full Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at http://www.tandfonline.com/action/journalInformation?journalCode=ccst20 CITIZENSHIP STUDIES, 2018 https://doi.org/10.1080/13621025.2018.1449812 The ‘I’ and the ‘we’ of citizenship in the age of waning democracy: Wolin and Balibar on citizenship, the political and dedemocratization Robin Rodd Discipline of Anthropology, James Cook University, Townsville, Australia ABSTRACT ARTICLE HISTORY Despite drawing on different historical traditions and philosophical Received 16 September 2017 sources, Sheldon Wolin and Étienne Balibar have come to see Accepted 18 February 2018 citizenship and democracy in fundamentally similar ways. However, KEYWORDS the work of one has not been considered alongside that of the other. In Balibar; Wolin; citizenship; this paper, I examine some of their key texts and draw out three areas of democratization; common concern: the historical specificity of the political, citizenship dedemocratization; demos; as a dialectical process and dedemocratization. The significance of equality Wolin and Balibar’s writing on citizenship and democracy lies in a set of proposals for the eternal rebirth of the citizen as democratic agent between action and institution, hierarchy and equality, individual and community, difference and the universal.
    [Show full text]
  • Introduction to the 2017 Edition
    Introduction to the 2017 Edition Sheldon Wolin was our most important contemporary political theorist. He gave us a modern vocabulary to describe our decayed democracy and the poi- sonous effects of empire. He was a scholar who detested orthodoxies, rooted his understanding of democracy in the ancient concept of the Athenian demos and believed, like Max Weber, that politics was a vocation. Ralph Nader gave me Democracy Incorporated: Managed Democracy and the Specter of Inverted Totalitarianism when it first came out in 2008. Nader, who has been fighting the abuse of corporate power longer and with perhaps more success than any other American, called it a “masterpiece.” Wolin cap- tured the political mutations caused by neoliberalism and coined the term “inverted totalitarianism” for the novel political and economic system it had spawned. He foresaw that this system of inverted totalitarianism would, as it has, eventually crush or hollow out our democratic institutions and give rise to an authoritarian or even totalitarian regime. Inverted totalitarianism is different from classical forms of totalitarianism. It does not find its expression in a demagogue or charismatic leader but in the faceless anonymity of the corporate state. Inverted totalitarianism pays out- ward fealty to the facade of electoral politics, the Constitution, civil liberties, freedom of the press, the independence of the judiciary, and the iconography, traditions and language of American patriotism, but it has effectively seized all of the mechanisms of power to render the citizen impotent. “Unlike the Nazis, who made life uncertain for the wealthy and privileged while providing social programs for the working class and poor, inverted totali- tarianism exploits the poor, reducing or weakening health programs and social services, regimenting mass education for an insecure workforce threatened by the importation of low- wage workers,” Wolin wrote.
    [Show full text]
  • Democratic Theory
    Democratic Theory Government 6645 (Spring 2016) Professor Jason Frank Cornell University White Hall 307 W 4:30-6:30 [email protected] White Hall 114 Office Hours: W 1:30-3:30 Course description Democracy, once commonly derided as the worst of all regimes, is now just as often proclaimed the universal source of modern political legitimacy. There is little agreement, however, over what democracy means or how it is best embodied in state institutions and law. This seminar will attempt to bring these disagreements into conceptual focus by introducing students to select debates in contemporary democratic theory over the meaning of democracy and the normative scope and limitations of contemporary democratic practice. Beginning with the early modern history of popular sovereignty and ending with contemporary debates over democracy and neoliberalism, we will explore (but not limit ourselves to) the following questions: How do democratic theorists and democratic actors negotiate the paradoxes of collective self-rule? Is democratic theory an empirical or normative inquiry, or does it destabilize this very opposition? Who is the agent of democratic politics? How should we understand the interaction between formal democratic institutions and political culture? What is the relationship between liberalism and democracy? Do rights (as protections of individual liberty not subject to revision by majority rule) suspend democracy or establish its necessary preconditions? Is democracy premised on a unitary political identity and, if so, how does it accommodate or recognize difference? Is democracy best understood as a form of government or a practice of resistance to domination? What do we expect from democratic theory and how should we understand the relationship between democratic theory and democratic practice? Course Requirements This is a political theory graduate seminar.
    [Show full text]
  • The Promise of Mourning
    University of Massachusetts Amherst ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst Doctoral Dissertations Dissertations and Theses March 2015 The Promise of Mourning Samantha Rose Hill University of Massachusetts Amherst Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.umass.edu/dissertations_2 Part of the Political Theory Commons Recommended Citation Hill, Samantha Rose, "The Promise of Mourning" (2015). Doctoral Dissertations. 304. https://doi.org/10.7275/6461835.0 https://scholarworks.umass.edu/dissertations_2/304 This Open Access Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Dissertations and Theses at ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst. It has been accepted for inclusion in Doctoral Dissertations by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks@UMass Amherst. For more information, please contact [email protected]. THE PROMISE OF MOURNING A Dissertation Presented by SAMANTHA ROSE HILL Submitted to the Graduate School of the University of Massachusetts Amherst in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY February 2015 Department of Political Science © Copyright by Samantha Rose Hill 2015 All Rights Reserved THE PROMISE OF MOURNING A Dissertation Presented by SAMANTHA ROSE HILL Approved as to style and content by: _________________________________________ Nicholas Xenos, Chair _________________________________________ Angelica Bernal, Member _________________________________________ Jonathan Skolnik, Member _________________________________________ Thomas Dumm, Member _________________________________________ Brian F. Schaffner, Department Chair Department of Political Science For Isabel Rose ACKNOWLEDGMENTS I am grateful to my dissertation chair Nicholas Xenos for his constant support, for telling me that I could not write a dissertation on Hannah Arendt, and for introducing me to Jean Jacques Rousseau and Walter Benjamin, who will always remain with me. I am very thankful to Thomas Dumm for his generous mentorship, guidance, and encouragement.
    [Show full text]
  • Dewey and the Project of Critical Social Theory*
    ..··:.:r.·.'· , DEWEY AND THE PROJECT OF CRITICAL ·,····.·.,·,·.·,1··,···",::·' :~ F. ~. r SOCIAL THEORY* ·',:1: ROBERT J. IZENT University of Kansas Social Thought & Research, 2000, Vol. 23, 1&2 Abstract The project of critical social theory shares with progressive (bllt not classical, free 1Harket) liberalism a value-orientation composed ofan egalitarian conception of socialjustice; a positive, delJelopmental vie1v of libertY as selfrealization; and a participatory notion of democracy. Differentiating critical theory fro»: all strains of liberalism is the comsction that capitalism cannot StljJport theinstitutionalieation of this value-orientation, and that tinder modern conditions onlY some form of democratic socialism can. Given thisualue-orientation, thispaperoutlines the mission and struaur: of theproject of critical theory. In its RJOSt recent retreat to the academy, practitioners have losttoud: not onlY 1vith its mission but also lvith the level ofhistorical specificity at wbicb the project can RIOSt effectivelY bepracticed. TIl/O proposals aresuggestedfor recoverilJg and executing its mission. Thefirst is to address citizens in particular societies about the mora! and political significance of contemporary social change. The second is that theory, description, critique, and vision should proceed at a level ofabstraction I callregi1lle analYsis. Here the object ofanalYsis is a specific society with its own history, institutionalfeatures; and cultura! identity. It is suggested that John Dewey': proposals for the retitalization of philosophy are relevant to the recovery of theproject of critical social theory. Following Dewf!Y j • For theirpatience and support over the years I wish to thank my friends Tom Skrtic, Bob Antonio, Mohamed El-Hodiri, Bardwell Smith, and the late Clifford Griffin. This work was supported in part by Grant No.
    [Show full text]
  • In Socialism's Twilight: Michael Walzer and the Politics of the Long New
    In Socialism’s Twilight: Michael Walzer and the Politics of the Long New Left David Marcus Submitted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Doctor of Philosophy in the Graduate School of Arts and Sciences COLUMBIA UNIVERSITY 2019 ©2019 David Marcus All Rights Reserved Abstract “In Socialism’s Twilight: Michael Walzer and the Politics of the Long New Left” David Marcus In Socialism’s Twilight is a study of the thought and politics of Michael Walzer and the travails of “democratic socialism” in the second half of the twentieth century. Using the methods of intel- lectual and political history, it situates Walzer’s political theory and criticism in the context of what might be called the “long New Left,” the overlapping generations of radicals that stretched from the beginning of the Cold War to its end and that supplemented the left’s traditional com- mitments to socialism with a politics of national liberation, radical democracy, and liberalism. By doing so, the dissertation hopes to trace the development not only of Walzer’s own commit- ments but also those of the socialist left. Caught in a period of frequent defeat and bitter contro- versy, socialists found themselves forced into a state of constant revision, as they moved from the libertarian socialism of the 1950s and 60s to the social democratic coalitions of the 1970s and 80s to the liberalism and humanitarianism of the 1990s and 2000s. Opening with the collapse of the Popular Front after World War II, the study follows Walzer’s search for a new left with radi- cals around Dissent and through his involvement in civil rights and antiwar activism.
    [Show full text]
  • Extended Notes for Toward Democracy
    NOTES TO INTRODUCTION 1 EXTENDED NOTES FOR TOWARD DEMOCRACY Note to Readers The following notes, prepared with the help of Abigail Modaff of Harvard University, contain fuller documentation for James T. Kloppenberg, Toward Democracy: The Struggle for Self-Rule in European and American Thought, published by Oxford University Press in June, 2016. Page references within these notes refer to the print version of the book. As is indicated on p. 711 of that edition, many of the notes in this document contain a greater range of references and commentary than are available in the book. Readers will, however, find that a few of the notes that are followed by an asterisk in the print version do not differ from the notes in this document; those asterisks will be removed, and typographical errors corrected, in later printings of Toward Democracy. Introduction 1. See the UNESCO report edited by Richard McKeon, Democracy in a World of Tensions (Chicago, 1951), 522. Influential assessments of the universality of democracy at the turn of the twenty-first century include Amartya Sen, “Democracy as a Universal Value,” Journal of Democracy 10 (1999): 3–17; and the widely circulated report by Freedom House, Democracy’s Century: A Survey of Political Change in the Twentieth Century (New York, 1999), which reported that the number of democratic nations had mushroomed from a mere handful in 1900 to over 60 percent by the end of the century. Although those nations contained less than 40 percent of the world’s population, the report confidently predicted that the further expansion of democracy, now praised if not NOTES TO INTRODUCTION 2 yet practiced everywhere, was only a matter of time.
    [Show full text]
  • The Space of Politics: Voegelin, Arendt, and Wolin Compared
    The Space of Politics: Wolin, Voegelin, and Arendt Compared. Thomas Heilke Department of Political Science University of Kansas Prepared for the Annual Meeting of the American Political Science Association, Chicago, August 29-Sept. 2, 2007. © 2007 by Thomas Heilke. Do not cite without express permission of author. For electronic copies or other inquiries, please email: [email protected]. 1. Introduction In January, 2000, a 10 year-old boy stood on the stage of the amphitheater in Fiesole, a small Etruscan-era hill-top town in the Italian province of Tuscany, and recited “In Flanders’ Fields,” the well-known paean to the dead at the second Battle of Ypres in 1915. A physician and second in command of the 1st Brigade Canadian Field Artillery, Dr. John McCrae, wrote the poem during the second week of the battle, upon the death of his friend, Lieutenant Alexis Holmer.1 McCrae was killed in action on 28 January, 1918. The poem reads as follows: In Flanders fields the poppies blow Between the crosses, row on row, That mark our place; and in the sky The larks, still bravely singing, fly Scarce heard amid the guns below. We are the Dead. Short days ago We lived, felt dawn, saw sunset glow, Loved and were loved, and now we lie In Flanders fields. Take up our quarrel with the foe: To you from failing hands we throw The torch; be yours to hold it high. If ye break faith with us who die We shall not sleep, though poppies grow In Flanders fields.2 The poem is not, perhaps, intended to be “political” in the precise sense of motivating its audience to common action toward a common cause: the background of the poem is the death of a soldier, and it is written by another soldier who was a close friend.
    [Show full text]
  • Politics and Vision
    1 Politics and Vision WILLIAM E. CONNOLLY Political Theory and the Political To study political theory in 1960 was to participate in an enterprise widely thought to be moribund. The air was thick with funeral orations. Because a new science of politics was on the verge of consolidation,political theory in the “normative” or “traditional” sense had become unnecessary. The old theory was speculative and impressionistic,while the new science would be rigorous and testable; the old mixed the descriptive and the nor- mative,while the new would separate them rigorously; the old was too historical in focus,while the new science of lawful regularities tied to pre- dictable events would be drawn from observable evidence in the present. Some interesting questions in the venerable texts might be convertible into testable hypotheses,but in the main and for the most part political theory was in the way and on the way out. Sure,the shape of the future science was still marked by uncertainty. Several “models” competed for hege- mony. There was public choice theory,decision-making theory,systems theory,power theory,communications theory,structural-functionalism, and so on. But,as David Easton put it in a formulation marked by his typical politeness,these perspectives were united in their opposition to traditional theory and bound together by precepts conveyed best by the word behavioralism: The behavioral approach testifies to the coming of age of theory in the social sciences as a whole,wedded,however,to a commitment to the assumptions and methods of empirical science. Unlike the great traditional theories of past political thought,new theory tends to be analytic,not substantive,explanatory rather than ethical,more general and less particular.
    [Show full text]
  • Sheldon Wolin, Hannah Arendt, and Jacques Rancière on Democracy
    Georgia State University ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University Political Science Theses Department of Political Science Spring 4-5-2012 Achieving Genuine Moments from Ordinary Origins: Sheldon Wolin, Hannah Arendt, and Jacques Rancière on Democracy Grant Yarbrough Georgia State University Follow this and additional works at: https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/political_science_theses Recommended Citation Yarbrough, Grant, "Achieving Genuine Moments from Ordinary Origins: Sheldon Wolin, Hannah Arendt, and Jacques Rancière on Democracy." Thesis, Georgia State University, 2012. https://scholarworks.gsu.edu/political_science_theses/42 This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Department of Political Science at ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. It has been accepted for inclusion in Political Science Theses by an authorized administrator of ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University. For more information, please contact [email protected]. ACHIEVING GENUINE MOMENTS FROM ORDINARY ORIGINS: SHELDON WOLIN, HANNAH ARENDT AND JACQUES RANCIÈRE ON DEMOCRACY by GRANT HENDRICKS YARBROUGH Under the Direction of Dr. Mario Feit ABSTRACT This paper grapples with the differences between genuine and ordinary democracy within the political thought of Jacques Rancière, Sheldon Wolin, and Hannah Arendt. Each discusses the problems of ordinary democracy and offer solutions in terms of what I call genuine democracy. Ordinary democracy is the established norm of liberal democracy celebrated as the stable and a desired “end” of political action. It is what happens when politics as usual becomes the norm and shuts the people from the halls of power. Genuine politics exist within the structure ordinary democracy and seeks to achieve the continuous re-establishment of democratic processes while in the process speeding up and disrupting “politics as usual”.
    [Show full text]
  • Undoing the Demos : Neoliberalism's Stealth Revolution
    ZONE BOOKS NEAR FUTURES SERIES Edited by Wendy Brown and Michel Feher Reckoning with the epochal nature of the turn that capitalism has taken in the last three decades, the editors of Near Futures seek to assemble a series of books that will illuminate its mani- fold implications — with regard to the production of value and values, the missions or disorientations of social and political institutions, the yearnings, reasoning, and conduct expected of individuals. However, the purpose of this project is not only to take stock of what neoliberal reforms and the dictates of finance have wrought: insofar as every mode of government generates resistances specific to its premises and practices, Near Futures also purports to chart some of the new conflicts and forms of activism elicited by the advent of our brave new world. UNDOING THE DEMOS Undoing the Demos: Neoliberalism’s Stealth Revolution Wendy Brown near futures © 2015 Wendy Brown zone Books 633 Vanderbilt street, Brooklyn, new York 11218 All rights reserved. A version of Chapter six was previously published as “The end of educated Democracy” in Representations, Volume 116 (Fall 2011) no part of this book may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted in any form or by any means, including electronic, mechanical, photocopying, microfilming, recording, or otherwise (except for that copying permitted by sections 107 and 108 of the U.s. Copyright Law and except by reviewers for the public press), without written permission from the Publisher. Printed in the United states of America. Distributed by The MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts, and London, england.
    [Show full text]