1 the Stereotypical Picture of the Russell/Bradley Dispute

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

1 the Stereotypical Picture of the Russell/Bradley Dispute Notes 1 The Stereotypical Picture of the Russell/Bradley Dispute 1 The Order of Merit is restricted to 24 members at anyone time, plus addi­ tional non-UK recipients. At the time of writing there have only been 168 ordinary members of the Order (honorary appointments of figures outside the Commonwealth are additional). 2 Bradley's College Fellowship, obtained in December 1870 and terminable only on marriage or death, had no teaching duties attached. In June 1871 he suffered a severe inflammation of the kidneys which appears to have had permanent effects. It has been suggested, possibly with malice, that the Bradleys in general were disposed to hypochondria; be that as it may, he was prone thereafter to be incapacitated by cold, physical exhaustion or anxiety; hence his retired life. He took an active part in the running of his college, but avoided public occasions. Collingwood records of Bradley in his Autobiography, '[AJlthough I lived within a few hundred yards of him for sixteen years, I never to my knowledge set eyes on him.' But although the history of Bradley's public life is largely that of his books and articles, it is clear that his was not a narrowly bookish existence. To protect his health, he frequently escaped the damp chill of Oxford winters for the kinder weather of southern English and Mediterranean seaside resorts, where company perhaps more congenial than that of an all-male Oxford common room was available. 3 See, for instance, Hylton (1990), p. 1 and the title of Candlish (1998). 4 Recently there have appeared two collections of essays devoted to the philo­ sophy of F.H. Bradley and largely sympathetic in their treatment of it (Bradley J., ed., 1996; Mander, ed., 1996). It is striking that philosophers at Canadian universities supplied nearly all the material for the first of these volumes. Admittedly it arose from a conference held in Canada. But they also supplied nearly half of that for the second. And this arose from one held in England, at which the Canadian contingent was the largest national group. My conjec­ ture is that this persistence of interest is probably traceable to a much earlier filling of Canadian university positions by Scottish migrants; whatever the explanation, the phenomenon is as much social as philosophical. 5 The application of these terms, especially 'realism', has varied over the years. Some philosophers, for example, think that there can be realist idealists and that the proper contrast with idealism is materialism. I stick here with the idealist/realist contrast as that is in keeping with my epigraph. As that epi­ graph shows, it has certainly been standard at times to think this way. For illustration, see Russell (1924), CP9 p. 170; LK p. 333; also quoted in Chapter 6, p. 144, and Paton (1956), pp. 341, 347. 6 Some hint of why this change should have come about can be gained from Stroud 1979. 189 190 Notes to pp. 8-22 7 For examples of this phenomenon in (once) widely used textbooks, see Warnock (1958), pp. 2-3; Ayer (1971), p. 25. To point this out is not to deny that more judicious historians have generally treated this matter with greater delicacy (for example, Passmore 1957, p. 59). 8 There is a well-informed and sensitive discussion in chapter 8 of Mander (1994). 9 Some philosophers say that Russell had a great deal of respect for Bradley. This may be true. Certainly in their private correspondence he is polite, even deferential. However, his published remarks are, as we shall see, often very different in tone. 10 Text books and contributions to standard works of reference which fit this description include the following: Bonjour (1995); Dancy (1985), p. 110; Haack (1978), p. 86; Hamlyn (1970), p. 123; Kirkham (1998); O'Connor and Carr (1982), p. 166 (Bradley is here identified only by implication); Richards (1978), p. 139; Sprigge (1995); White (1967), p. 132; Woozley (1949), pp. 125 and 150. It would be very easy to add to this list. 11 For example: Blackburn (1984a), p. 235, and (1984b), pp. 155-6; Candlish (1981), p. 252, n. 6; Candlish (1984), p. 254; Candlish (1986), p. 245; Manser (1983), p. 133; Passmore (1957), p. 116; Walker (1985), p. 2; White (1971), p. 109; Wollheim (1959), p. 171; Wollheim (1969), p. 167. 12 For example, Acton (1967), p. 362; Wollheim (1959), p. 74 (1969), p. 7l. In Wollheim's case what Russell calls an 'unintentional' confusion is pre­ sented as a deliberate though inexplicit Bradleian commitment. 13 Allard (2005). More general recent accounts of Bradley, both of them clear and well informed, are Mander (1994) and Basile (1999). 14 A good, though somewhat unwieldy, example of the genre is Sprigge (1993). It is not surprising that the dual focus is rare, for it is likely to con­ front this intractable problem: Nothing short of a cogent account of how it is possible to confront the philosophical past philosophically as well as historically will give us what we need. But such an account will have to explain how one large-scale philosophical standpoint can engage with another in cases where each standpoint embodies its own conceptions of what rational superiority consists of in such a way that there can apparently be no appeal to any neutral and independent standard. (MacIntyre 1984, p. 40) 15 MacIntyre, lac. cit. 2 Finding a Way into Bradley's Metaphysics A similar view is expressed by Locke (1706), Book IV, Chapter XIV, §4, and, with names substituted for ideas, by J.S. Mill (1843), Chapter I §2. 2 Even Hume, who explicitly denied that judgments had to involve more than one idea (1739, Book I, Part III, §VII, fn. 1), conceived ideas in this way. It was essential to the account of reasoning in terms of the association of ideas, an account which Bradley vigorously rejected. Notes to pp. 24-8 191 3 For examples of each, see Leibniz's Discourse on Metaphysics, and Reinhardt Grossmann, Meinong (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1974). A good con­ trast with Leibniz in this respect is Berkeley. 4 For example, even serious scholars (see, for instance, Manser and Stock 1984, p. 26) have thought that Bradley was referring to Leibniz on page 25 of Appearance and Reality when, in criticizing atomism, he mentioned 'the most thorough attempt to build a system on this ground' without appar­ ently thinking it necessary to identify this attempt more explicitly. The name of Leibniz comes naturally to a modern reader in this context but, as Bradley (1897), p. 539 makes clear, he was thinking of Herbart, who is now remembered, if at all, as an educationist. The error is corrected in the 1986 reprint of Manser and Stock (though not in the index). Perhaps it is indirect evidence of how Russellian the modern reader is that Russell himself made the same mistake: see Russell (1900), p. 15 n. 1. 5 I cherish a quotation from a New Statesman review printed inside the dust cover of my copy of Our Knowledge of the External World: 'This brilliant, lucid and amusing book which ... everyone can understand.' 6 In this chapter, whenever a citation date appears without an author's name attached, the name is to be understood as Bradley. 7 Nor is it, pace Wollheim (1959), p. 282 (1969), p. 277, feeling especially pleased about things. 8 Even this will not do ultimately, but 'ultimately' is the point at which his metaphysics reaches complete inexpressibility. Cf. (1883), PL p. 487, and below (p. 42tJ. Bradley came to be dissatisfied with the original 1883 text of this work, which even he described in correspondence as 'badly arranged & unnecessarily difficult', as is illustrated by the combination of the Additional Notes and Terminal Essays in the second edition. On this matter, see the excellent Keene (1999). I have tried not to rely on examples concerning which he changed his mind, unless I am drawing attention to this fact. 9 Contentious not merely in the sense that others readily dispute them, but also in the sense that what they are is itself a matter of dispute, as we shall see. 10 One may think here that in view of Bradley's attribution of the method of ideal experiment to Hegel, one should look to Hegel himself for explana­ tion. But to find such an explanation in Hegel turns out to be even more difficult than finding one in Bradley. The interpretation offered below is corroborated in an entry in the Bradley papers in Merton College Library (Bradley Papers, III B 2, p. 115). 11 The point is complicated by the fact that Bradley's philosophical logic is constantly being undercut by his metaphysics. In this case, for instance, after his drawing of the distinction between the valid and the invalid in rea­ soning, it emerges that he thinks that, ultimately, all inference is invalid (1883, PL p. 588 and 1922, PL p. 621). This adoption of temporary positions is a perennial irritant for one attempting to expound his views, and one can understand how A.R. Manser was led to claim that Bradley (1883) was a book of pure and defensible philosophical logic uncontaminated by the later and mistaken metaphysics (Manser 1983). This claim will be examined in Chapter 6 (p. 145tJ, but that it must be mistaken can be seen from the 192 Notes to pp. 28-37 parenthetical dates earlier in this footnote. Indeed, Bradley's 'later' meta­ physics is evidently influencing his moral philosophy as early as 1876 (Candlish 1978, §8). 12 To find the full story of Bradley's surprising response to this question, see Allard (2005), chapters 6 and 7.
Recommended publications
  • A Defense of FH Bradley's Philosophy of Experience Against William James' Criticisms By
    The Experience of the Absolute: A Defense of F.H. Bradley’s Philosophy of Experience Against William James’ Criticisms By: Kyle Barbour Thesis submitted to the School of Graduate Studies in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts in Philosophy Department of Philosophy Memorial University August 2019 St. John’s, Newfoundland Page | 1 Abstract This thesis addresses the debate between two of the most important philosophers at the turn of the 20th century: F.H. Bradley and William James. Their debate centered around the priority that each philosopher assigned to experience in terms of a starting point for metaphysical inquiry and the subsequent understanding of logical relations which each philosopher developed based upon their conception of experience. This thesis will consider James’ “radical empiricism” as a response and critique of Bradley’s philosophy. As such, through an investigation of each philosopher, this thesis will argue that James’ critique of Bradley is flawed due to his misreading of Bradley’s philosophy and will conclude that Bradley’s philosophy holds the potential to answer the difficulties found within James’ radical empiricism and, though it contains undeniable flaws of its own, holds within it the seeds for future philosophical development that exceeds Bradley and James’ debate. Page | 2 Acknowledgements This thesis would not have been possible without the support of a number of people from both my personal and academic life. I would first like to thank Dr. Suma Rajiva and Dr. Seamus O’Neill for being constant supports throughout my entire time as a philosophy student at M.U.N.
    [Show full text]
  • Notes and References
    NOTES AND REFERENCES I CATEGORIAL DESCRIPTION 1. Aristotle, Categories 1b25: the quotation is taken from the translation, with notes, by J. L. Ackrill, Aristotle's Categories and De Interpretatione (Oxford University Press, 1963), p. 5. 2. J. L. Ackrill, op. cit., p. 78. 3. I. Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, 2nd edn (J. F. Hartknoch, Riga, 1787). These categories are listed in the first chapter of the section called 'Analytic of Concepts'. 4. Ibid. 5. R. G. Collingwood, Essay on Metaphysics (Oxford University Press, 1940). 6. I. Kant, op. cit., 'Analytic of Principles'. 7. P. F. Strawson, Individuals (Methuen, London, 1959) p. 9. 8. Ibid., pp. 9-10. 9. Ibid., p. 10. 10. I. Kant, op. cit., 'Analytic of Concepts'. II. R. Descartes, Meditations on First Philosophy (Paris, 1641). References are to the translation of the 2nd edition ( 1642) included in E. Anscom be and P. T. Geach, translators and editors, Descartes: Philosophical Writings (Nelson, London, 1964). 12. R. Descartes, ibid., p. 67. 13. B. Williams, Descartes: The Project of Pure Enquiry (Penguin, Harmondsworth, 1978) p. 112. 14. R. Descartes, op. cit., p. 61. 15. R. Descartes, op. cit., p. 114. 16. E. Anscombe and P. T. Geach, op. cit., pp. 193-4. 17. A category account of facts is presented in D. W. Hamlyn, 'The Correspondence Theory of Truth', Philosophical Quarterly, XII ( 1962), pp. 193-205. 18. G. E. Moore, Principia Ethica (Cambridge University Press, 1903). 2 SUBSTANCE I. Aristotle, Categories 2a II: J. L. Ackrill, op. cit., p. 5. 2. This interpretation is taken inj. L. Mackie, Problems from Locke (Oxford University Press, 1976), pp.
    [Show full text]
  • Virtual Worlds , Fiction, and Reality
    Virtual worlDs, Fiction, anD reality mundos virtuales, fiCCión y realidad ILkkA mAuNu NIINILuOTO University of Helsinki, Finland. [email protected] RECIbIDO EL 13 DE juLIO DE 2011 y APRObADO EL 30 DE AGOSTO DE 2011 resumen abstract Mi objetivo en este artículo es plantear My aim in this paper is to raise and discuss y discutir algunas de las preguntas some philosophical questions about Virtual filosóficas sobre la Realidad Virtual (RV). Reality (VR). The most fundamental El problema fundamental se refiere a problem concerns the ontological nature of la naturaleza ontológica de la realidad VR: is it real or fictional? Is VR comparable virtual: ¿es real o ficticia? ¿La RV es to illusions, hallucinations, dreams, comparable a ilusiones, alucinaciones, or worlds of fiction? Are traditional sueños, o mundos de ficción? ¿Son todas philosophical categories at all sufficient to las categorías filosóficas tradicionales give us understanding of the phenomenon suficientes para darnos la comprensión of VR? In approaching these questions, I del fenómeno de la RV? Para abordar shall employ possible world semantics estas cuestiones, emplearé como mis and logical theories of perception and herramientas filosóficas la semántica de imagination as my philosophical tools. My mundos posibles y las teorías lógicas main conclusion is that VR is comparable de la percepción y la imaginación. Mi to a 3-D picture which can be seen from conclusión principal es que la RV es the inside. comparable a una imagen en 3-D que puede ser vista desde el interior. palabras claVe Key worDs Ficción, alucinación, imaginación, Fiction, hallucination, imagination, percepción, realidad, realidad virtual.
    [Show full text]
  • Bradley's Account of the Self As Appearance: Between Kant's Transcendental Idealism and Hegel's Speculative Idealism
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Christ University Bengaluru: Open Journal Systems Tattva-Journal of Philosophy 2018, Vol. 10, No. 1, 1-18 ISSN 0975-332X│https://doi.org/10.12726/tjp.19.1 Bradley’s Account of the Self as Appearance: Between Kant’s Transcendental Idealism and Hegel’s Speculative Idealism Damian Ilodigwe* Abstract The constitutive activity of the self and the ground of the unity of the self are two important aspects of understanding the self. This paper attempts to delineate these considerations, tracing their use, function and implications in Bradley‟s thesis on the self. The article argues that for Bradley, the focalization is on the understanding of the self and the relation of thought to reality. Furthermore, the article attempts to locate Bradley‟s account of the self as appearance as a middle course between Kant‟s transcendental idealism to Hegel‟s speculative idealism to demonstrate the overlaps, ruptures, and evolution of the philosophical journey of the concept of the self, its nature, and its expressions. Keywords: Self, Bradley, Transcendental Idealism, Speculative Idealism Preamble Two types of considerations arise in connection to the understanding of the unity of the self. One concern pertains to the constitutive activity of the self–an insight exemplified by Kant‟s doctrine of transcendental unity of apperception. The other relates to the question of the ground of the unity of the self. In accordance * Ss Peter and Paul Major Seminary and University of Ibadan, Nigeria; [email protected] 1 Tattva-Journal of Philosophy, Vol.
    [Show full text]
  • The Problem of Meaning in Nishida's Early Writings Miikael-Adam Lotman
    The Problem of Meaning in Nishida’s Early Writings Miikael-Adam Lotman JSPS Research Fellow, Kyoto University Abstract: This paper revisits a traditional problem in Nishidian scholarship regarding the link between Nishida Kitarō’s maiden work An Inquiry into the Good (1911) and his next major treatise Intuition and Reflection in Self-Consciousness (1917). In this paper I will show that the problem of fact vs. meaning, which is explicitly treated in Intuition and Reflection in Self-Consciousness, is influenced by the writings of Motora Yūjirō. I make the case that Nishida’s adoption of Royce’s thought experiment of “the perfect map of England” as a model for “self-consciousness” was instrumental in his attempt to explain the entirety of reality. In the first section, I show that Nishida’s earliest ambition of explaining everything with the concept of pure experience accommodates his contemporaries’ understanding of the scope and task of philosophy. However, Nishida developed his own explanation of philosophy’s task. According to Nishida, philosophy arises in response to a sense of anguish one feels after contemplating on the meaning of the world. In the second section, I explain why Nishida believed that a reflection on the world’s meaning causes philosophical anguish. This is due to an incompatibility between Nishida’s metaphysical views and a criterion of meaning that he inherited from Motora. This combination left Nishida with a dilemma: either the world has no meaning, or everything has meaning but the world does not exist as a single entity. In the last section, I argue that Royce’s “perfect map of England” offered resolved this dilemma, by showing how the world as a single entity can have meaning in relation to its proper parts.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy in a Meaningless Life
    9781474247702_Fm_Final_txt_prf.indd vi 8/26/2015 5:20:44 PM Philosophy in a Meaningless Life 9781474247702_Fm_Final_txt_prf.indd i 8/26/2015 5:20:41 PM Also available from Bloomsbury Th e Bloomsbury Companion to Heidegger , edited by Francois Raff oul and Eric S. Nelson Nietzsche, Nihilism and the Philosophy of the Future , edited by Jeff rey Metzger Nothingness and the Meaning of Life , Nicholas Waghorn Time, Creation and the Continuum , Richard Sorabji Truth and Method , Hans-Georg Gadamer 9781474247702_Fm_Final_txt_prf.indd ii 8/26/2015 5:20:44 PM Philosophy in a Meaningless Life A System of Nihilism, Consciousness and Reality James Tartaglia Bloomsbury Academic An imprint of Bloomsbury Publishing Plc LONDON • OXFORD • NEW YORK • NEW DELHI • SYDNEY 9781474247702_Fm_Final_txt_prf.indd iii 8/26/2015 5:20:44 PM Bloomsbury Academic An imprint of Bloomsbury Publishing Plc 50 Bedford Square 1385 Broadway London New York WC1B 3DP NY 10018 UK USA www.bloomsbury.com BLOOMSBURY and the Diana logo are trademarks of Bloomsbury Publishing Plc First published 2016 Paperback edition first published 2016 © James Tartaglia, 2016 James Tartaglia has asserted his right under the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act, 1988, to be identified as the Author of this work. All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording, or any information storage or retrieval system, without prior permission in writing from the publishers. No responsibility for loss caused to any individual or organization acting on or refraining from action as a result of the material in this publication can be accepted by Bloomsbury or the author.
    [Show full text]
  • Understanding Philosophy of Science
    UNDERSTANDING PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE ‘This is the best introduction to philosophy of science I have read. I will certainly use it. The writing is wonderfully clear without being sim- plistic. It is not at all too difficult for second and third year students. Many of my philosophy of science students have no background in philosophy, and I’m sure they will find the book accessible, informa- tive, and a pleasure to read. I read this manuscript with my students in mind. This is the book we’ve been looking for.’ Peter Kosso, Northern Arizona University Few can imagine a world without telephones or televisions; many depend on computers and the Internet as part of daily life. Without scientific theory, these developments would not have been possible. In this exceptionally clear and engaging introduction to the philosophy of science, James Ladyman explores the philosophical questions that arise when we reflect on the nature of the scientific method and the knowledge it produces. He discusses whether fundamental philosophical questions about knowledge and reality might be answered by science, and considers in detail the debate between realists and antirealists about the extent of scientific knowledge. Along the way, central topics in the philosophy of science, such as the demarcation of science from non-science, induction, confirmation and falsification, the relationship between theory and observation, and relativ- ism, are all addressed. Important and complex current debates over under- determination, inference to the best explanation and the implications of radical theory change are clarified and clearly explained for those new to the subject. The style is refreshing and unassuming, bringing to life the essential ques- tions in the philosophy of science.
    [Show full text]
  • The Ghost of Terror in French Thought a DISSERTATION SUBMITTED to the FACULTY of the GRADUATE SCHOOL of TH
    Modernity and Ethics: The Ghost of Terror in French Thought A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE FACULTY OF THE GRADUATE SCHOOL OF THE UNIVERSITY OF MINNESOTA BY Mira Reinberg IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY Bruno Chaouat August 2010 © Mira Reinberg 2010 i Acknowledgements It is perhaps befitting to describe the accomplishment of a dissertation in terms of negative comparison. When climbing a high mountain, studying a difficult text, learning a new language, one can feel a sense of achievement and fulfillment even if one does not consummate the task at hand to a point of mastery. Halting the climb before reaching the summit, putting down the text before its end or resting along the process of absorbing a language do not impede the enjoyment and gratification we draw from these actions. Partial as the process may ultimately be, the distance travelled is sufficiently vast to inspire the traveler with a continuously replenished sense of pride. Writing a dissertation is a different charge. The process takes place on multiple levels; it is as much an exercise in rigorous academic writing as an inquest of our creative ability. Probed and appraised, our thought processes track alongside intellectual, emotional, and physical integrity in the ongoing challenge. Eventually we must reach an endpoint for the work to provide the insight of a finished task. As students, dissertation writers fluctuate between feelings of insufficiency and enthusiasm. A long breath is the categorical imperative. I owe numerous people for their help in sustaining this long breath. Pascale Crépon, Stéphanie Bérard, Muisi Krosi, Kathy Rider, Madeleine Craig, Anna Cavell, Greta Bliss, Becky Halat, Robert St.
    [Show full text]
  • Russell' S Critique of Bradley
    International Journal of Philosophy and Social Sciences. Volume 9, Number 1 (2019), pp. 1-19 © Research India Publications http://www.ripublication.com Russell’ S Critique of Bradley Damian Ilodigwe SS Peter and Paul Major Seminary and University Of Ibadan, Nigeria. E-Mail Address: [email protected] Abstract In the years following Russell’s break with idealism, Russell’s strategy in attacking idealism consists in focusing attention on the whole development from Kant to Hegel relative to the question of the purported transformation of logic into ontology. Russell will not only reject the psychologism of the Kantian and Hegelian paradigms, but he will also radicalize his critique of this procedure, extending it to Hegel’s entire heritage; indeed the idealist tradition as a whole and Bradley in particular. This paper argues that Russell’s rejection of Bradley’s philosophy is a child of Russell’s attitude towards idealism. The assumption that all of idealism is irredeemably psychologistic is a key element in Russell’s treatment of Bradley’s theory of judgement as a species of subject-predicate logic as well as his reception of Bradley’s claim regarding the ‘unreality’ of relations. As a counter point to the assumed psychologism that infects the whole of idealism, Russell will advance his theory of logical atomism, a theory of proposition which dispenses with the role of the mind in judgement. The move to exclude the subject from the epistemological process is presumably a service to the ideal of objectivity; and, to this extent, is continuous with Russell’s anti-idealism. Whereas the whole of idealism tries to secure objectivity by configuring it in terms of subjectivity, Russell’s alternative route for securing objectivity is to de-configure objectivity from subjectivity.
    [Show full text]
  • Josiah Roycels Philosophy of Loyalty
    HISTORY OF PH ILOSO ph Y QUARTERLY Volume 26, Number 1, January 2009 AMERICAN INTERPRETATIONS OF HEGEL: JOSIAH Royce’s PHILOSOPHY OF LOYALTY John Kaag 1. INTRODUCTION here are three kinds of bookshelves in Robbins Library, located on the Tsecond floor of Emerson Hall. There are those that Harvard students use frequently; these are almost always picked over, leaving only a few copies of Rawl’s A Theory of Justice and Russell’s Philosophical Essays behind. There are those that are seldom used, save the few days during exams when students are forced to revisit the history of philosophy. And then there are those that remain largely neglected; these hold the works of American pragmatism. Next to this shelf, in a truly forgotten corner of Robbins, is a very old-looking collection. This collection con- sists of the generous gifts from the personal libraries of the university’s faculty. George Santayana, for example, donated his copies of William James’ Varieties of Religious Experience and Josiah Royce’s The World and the Individual. Royce bequeathed his personal copies of Kant’s first critique, the Metaphysics of Morals, and James Martineau’s A Study of Religion. In many instances, the notable owners of these volumes used them as makeshift notebooks, providing commentary and translations that demonstrate important turns in their thinking. Such is the case with two volumes that will serve as the focus of this article: Royce’s cop- ies of Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit and Logik. On the flysheets and in the margins of the books, Royce provided a detailed interpretation of these texts, the study of which dramatically alters the chronology and study of Royce’s concepts of loyalty and communities of interpretation.
    [Show full text]
  • F. H. Bradley's Neoplatonic Turn in Ethical Studies
    Angles New Perspectives on the Anglophone World 6 | 2018 Experimental Art F. H. Bradley’s Neoplatonic Turn in Ethical Studies (1876) Jean-Paul Rosaye Electronic version URL: http://journals.openedition.org/angles/1077 DOI: 10.4000/angles.1077 ISSN: 2274-2042 Publisher Société des Anglicistes de l'Enseignement Supérieur Electronic reference Jean-Paul Rosaye, « F. H. Bradley’s Neoplatonic Turn in Ethical Studies (1876) », Angles [Online], 6 | 2018, Online since 01 April 2018, connection on 28 July 2020. URL : http://journals.openedition.org/ angles/1077 ; DOI : https://doi.org/10.4000/angles.1077 This text was automatically generated on 28 July 2020. Angles. New Perspectives on the Anglophone World is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution- NonCommercial-ShareAlike 4.0 International License. F. H. Bradley’s Neoplatonic Turn in Ethical Studies (1876) 1 F. H. Bradley’s Neoplatonic Turn in Ethical Studies (1876) Jean-Paul Rosaye 1 According to a persistent interpretation, Francis Herbert Bradley was a major representative of a neo-Hegelian trend that spread in Britain in the late-Victorian period and consolidated into a British Idealist movement. It also insists that this philosophical experiment was short-lived, as it was overwhelmed at the beginning of the 20th century by a philosophical revolution initiated by Bertrand Russell and George Edward Moore. However, this interpretation has been wholly reconsidered since the 1980s following the formidable reassessment not only of Bradley’s metaphysics but also of the impact of the whole movement in British philosophy and politics.1 Russell’s importance as a philosopher has not been undermined in this revision, but it is now accepted that Bradley’s philosophy and the Idealist movement were not a mere transition filling the gap between the old empiricist school of the mid-19th century and the new analytical philosophy of the early 20th century (Rosaye 2012a).
    [Show full text]
  • The New Philosophy and Its Style
    Studies in English Volume 4 Article 11 1963 The New Philosophy and Its Style Dwight Van de Vate Jr. University of Mississippi Follow this and additional works at: https://egrove.olemiss.edu/ms_studies_eng Part of the History of Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Van de Vate, Dwight Jr. (1963) "The New Philosophy and Its Style," Studies in English: Vol. 4 , Article 11. Available at: https://egrove.olemiss.edu/ms_studies_eng/vol4/iss1/11 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the English at eGrove. It has been accepted for inclusion in Studies in English by an authorized editor of eGrove. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Van de Vate: The New Philosophy THE NEW PHILOSOPHY AND ITS STYLE by Dwight Van de Vate, Jr. The absolute idealist movement in British philosophy began with the publication of Hutchinson Stirling’s The Secret of Hegel in 1865. Bernard Bosanquet’s Gifford Lectures of 1911-1912 were its last major production. By the death of F. H. Bardley in 1924 the effective force of the movement had ended. Bradley was its most profound and original member and his Appearance and Reality its most influential book. A sample passage: And hence, for the present at least, we must believe that reality satisfies our whole being. Our main wants—for truth and life, and for beauty and goodness—must all find satisfaction. And we have seen that this consummation must somehow be experience, and be individual. Every element of the universe, sensation, feeling, thought, and will, must be included within one comprehensive sentience.1 The style is grave, heightened, formal, suiting the subject—“the Absolute.” It is impossible to think of Bradley telling a joke.
    [Show full text]