Analytic Philosophy

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

Analytic Philosophy PHILOSOPHY & THE ANALYTIC TURN All the Ivy League universities, all the leading state research universities, all the University of California campuses, most of the top liberal arts colleges, most of the flagship campuses of the second-tier state research universities boast philosophy departments that overwhelmingly self- identify as “analytic”: it is hard to imagine a “movement” that is more academically and professionally entrenched than analytic philosophy. — Brian Leiter, “The Philosophical Gourmet Report” Without exception, the best philosophy departments in the United States are dominated by analytic philosophy, and among the leading philosophers in the United States, all but a tiny handful would be classified as analytic philosophers. — John Searle An important background issue related to the advent of analytic philosophy: British idealism Analytic philosophy—more precisely, what I called ‘programmatic analytic philosophy’—can be understood as an outgrowth of two concerns: to deal with worries concerning (i) problems in mathematics and the semantics of both natural and formal languages, and (ii) recent trends in epistemology and metaphysics, especially a rejection to the dominant school of philosophy at the time, namely, British idealism. Concerning the latter, analytic philosophy was bolstered by the philosophical reactions by G.E. Moore and Bertrand Russell to the dominant school of thought in the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries, namely, British idealism. • British idealism comes in two varieties: absolute idealism and subjective idealism. We’ll only focus on the former type. • Two very influential advocates of absolute idealism: F.H. Bradley (Appearance and Reality) and J.M.E. McTaggart (The Nature of Existence). • According to the absolute idealists, all reality is mental and this reality is a unified singular entity, an integrated system of interdependent minds. The former makes the view a form of idealism; the latter makes the view a form of monism. Why did they think that absolute idealism is true? There are many important theses used to justify the truth of absolute idealism. Let us consider the following: On the impossibility of thinking of a mind-independent existence. One of the first steps in the case for idealism is negative: to call into question the coherence and justification of competing metaphysical views. According to the British idealists, the main competing view—metaphysical realism—is actually a conceptually incoherent view. What is metaphysical realism? It is the view that MP-REALISM: There’s at least one thing T such that T has one or more properties mind- independently. The British idealists argued that MP-REALISM is incoherent given that it is impossible to make theoretical sense of the very concept of a thing having the property exists mind-independently. Note that the idealist does not deny that it is prima facie true that we can make sense of such a state of being—it seems hard to imagine otherwise!—she simply argues that, if we are careful to examine whether we can actually do so, we will discover immediately that we cannot. Why does the idealist think that the concept of a mind-independent world is actually incoherent? According to idealist, IMI: It is not possible to think/imagine/conceive of a property, relation or object as existing mind-independently.1 If (IMI) is true, the implication is that the very concept of a thing’s existing mind-independently cannot be made coherent since it is not even possible to conceive of such a state. Argues the idealist, the coherence of metaphysical realism—of any variety—requires that a person be able to think of a thing having the property not being thought of. Yet, that is impossible! No person can think of a thing existing in the state not being thought of. So, argues the idealist, metaphysical realism is conceptually incoherent at “the ground level.” Of course, we should ask the following: does (IMI) imply there is no such thing as a mind- independent world, or merely that we cannot think/imagine/conceive of such a thing? Notice that these are two very different claims. The former is a claim about the nature of reality; the latter is a claim about the psychology of cognitive beings. It would seem that (IMI), at most, warrants the latter claim. If the idealist countenances that there may be a mind-independent world, but it is something of which we can neither cognitively access nor have any justification for thinking is there, then we presumably have a very different thesis than the idealist wants.2 This is an important question; for idealism is a metaphysical view about what exists, one that denies the reality of a mind-independent world. So, if (IMI) at most warrants a claim about cognitive beings, much more needs to be said in order to demonstrate that metaphysical realism is false. There may be grounds to which they will appeal to make the case, e.g., there may be justification for thinking any such thing is not there given the argument from Ockham’s Razor (alternatively: the principle of parsimony), but that needs further teasing out. The doctrine of reality and existential significance of internal relations. Let us turn to the absolute idealist’s case for monism. According to the absolute idealist, monism follows from the very important thesis called the doctrine of reality and existential significance of internal relations. Let us understand this doctrine according to the following principle: 1 The famous early modern philosopher, Bishop George Berkeley, was an idealist his being committed to something very similar to (IMI). 2 This is very much similar to the position that Kant attempts to demonstrate in Critique of Pure Reason (A [1781]; B [1787]). According to Kant, we are not capable of accessing the things-in-themselves, only the things-as-they-appear. Interestingly, when many of his contemporaries argued that this made him an idealist à la Berkeley, Kant argued that that was a mistaken reading of his view. He did not deny the reality of things-in-themselves; he denied our ability to access them. To paraphrase Kant, there is something that exists, the necessary ground of experience, but it is to us an unknown x. RIR: For any object O1, there is some set of objects {O2, O3, O4, …, On}, such that the nature and existence of O1 is dependent on the nature and existence of O2 through On and vice-versa. According to (RIR), had any one entity differed in its nature, every other entity would be different. Even worse, (RIR), in its strongest form, implies that if any entity lacked even one of its actual properties, the universe would not have existed. Why did the British idealists think that (RIR)—of any strength—is true? Two closely related reasons: 1. Let us understand by the term ‘property’ any quality that can be predicated truly of an object. Among the set of properties of that an object has are the properties of standing in relation to other objects, where the latter objects have certain properties. For instance, I have the property of being a philosophy professor who spends (an inordinate amount of) time rock and ice climbing. Accordingly, you have the property of taking a class from a philosophy professor who spends (an inordinate amount of) time rock and ice climbing. Call these properties ‘R’ and ‘T’, respectively. So, your having one of your properties—namely, T—is entirely dependent upon one of my properties—namely, R. Generalized, we get the following principle: RP: For any object O and property F possessed by O, there are relational properties FS and FD (where ‘FS’ and ‘FD’ abbreviate to the properties being similar to O in possession of F and being dissimilar to O in a lack of possession of F). With (RP) and the following further theses RIR-1: For any object O1, there is some set of objects {O2, O3, O4, …, On}, such that if O2, O3, O4, …, On have some property F and O1 has F, then O1 also has FS and vice versa, RIR-2: For any object O1, there is some set of objects {O2, O3, O4, …, On}, such that if O2, O3, O4, …, On have some property F and O1 lacks F, then O1 also has FD and vice versa, and RIR-3: For any object O1, if O1 has some property F, but at some point loses F, then for any set of objects {O2, O3, O4, …, On}, if O2, O3, O4, …, On have F, then either O2, O3, O4, …, On would lose FS and gain FD or O2, O3, O4, …, On lose F, we get the effect of change on an entity’s nature that is stated in (RIR). That is, given the conjunction of (RP), (RIR-1), (RIR-2) and (RIR-3), we can see that CN: For any two objects O1 and O2, if O1 has some property F, then either O1 does not lose F or O1 loses F and O2 loses FS and gains FD (or vice-versa), the claim that an object’s nature is affected by the nature of any other object is true. But what about the existence component of (RIR), that is, that an object’s existence depends on the existence of any other object? To show this, the absolute idealist brings our attention to another thesis. 2. According to the absolute idealists, every property is an essential property. That is, ESSENTIAL: For any object O and property F, if O is F, then O is essentially an F. Thus, ESSENTIAL¢: For any object O and property F, if O is F, then either O does not lose F or O loses F and ceases to exist.
Recommended publications
  • A Defense of FH Bradley's Philosophy of Experience Against William James' Criticisms By
    The Experience of the Absolute: A Defense of F.H. Bradley’s Philosophy of Experience Against William James’ Criticisms By: Kyle Barbour Thesis submitted to the School of Graduate Studies in partial fulfillment of the requirements for the degree of Master of Arts in Philosophy Department of Philosophy Memorial University August 2019 St. John’s, Newfoundland Page | 1 Abstract This thesis addresses the debate between two of the most important philosophers at the turn of the 20th century: F.H. Bradley and William James. Their debate centered around the priority that each philosopher assigned to experience in terms of a starting point for metaphysical inquiry and the subsequent understanding of logical relations which each philosopher developed based upon their conception of experience. This thesis will consider James’ “radical empiricism” as a response and critique of Bradley’s philosophy. As such, through an investigation of each philosopher, this thesis will argue that James’ critique of Bradley is flawed due to his misreading of Bradley’s philosophy and will conclude that Bradley’s philosophy holds the potential to answer the difficulties found within James’ radical empiricism and, though it contains undeniable flaws of its own, holds within it the seeds for future philosophical development that exceeds Bradley and James’ debate. Page | 2 Acknowledgements This thesis would not have been possible without the support of a number of people from both my personal and academic life. I would first like to thank Dr. Suma Rajiva and Dr. Seamus O’Neill for being constant supports throughout my entire time as a philosophy student at M.U.N.
    [Show full text]
  • Notes and References
    NOTES AND REFERENCES I CATEGORIAL DESCRIPTION 1. Aristotle, Categories 1b25: the quotation is taken from the translation, with notes, by J. L. Ackrill, Aristotle's Categories and De Interpretatione (Oxford University Press, 1963), p. 5. 2. J. L. Ackrill, op. cit., p. 78. 3. I. Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, 2nd edn (J. F. Hartknoch, Riga, 1787). These categories are listed in the first chapter of the section called 'Analytic of Concepts'. 4. Ibid. 5. R. G. Collingwood, Essay on Metaphysics (Oxford University Press, 1940). 6. I. Kant, op. cit., 'Analytic of Principles'. 7. P. F. Strawson, Individuals (Methuen, London, 1959) p. 9. 8. Ibid., pp. 9-10. 9. Ibid., p. 10. 10. I. Kant, op. cit., 'Analytic of Concepts'. II. R. Descartes, Meditations on First Philosophy (Paris, 1641). References are to the translation of the 2nd edition ( 1642) included in E. Anscom be and P. T. Geach, translators and editors, Descartes: Philosophical Writings (Nelson, London, 1964). 12. R. Descartes, ibid., p. 67. 13. B. Williams, Descartes: The Project of Pure Enquiry (Penguin, Harmondsworth, 1978) p. 112. 14. R. Descartes, op. cit., p. 61. 15. R. Descartes, op. cit., p. 114. 16. E. Anscombe and P. T. Geach, op. cit., pp. 193-4. 17. A category account of facts is presented in D. W. Hamlyn, 'The Correspondence Theory of Truth', Philosophical Quarterly, XII ( 1962), pp. 193-205. 18. G. E. Moore, Principia Ethica (Cambridge University Press, 1903). 2 SUBSTANCE I. Aristotle, Categories 2a II: J. L. Ackrill, op. cit., p. 5. 2. This interpretation is taken inj. L. Mackie, Problems from Locke (Oxford University Press, 1976), pp.
    [Show full text]
  • Virtual Worlds , Fiction, and Reality
    Virtual worlDs, Fiction, anD reality mundos virtuales, fiCCión y realidad ILkkA mAuNu NIINILuOTO University of Helsinki, Finland. [email protected] RECIbIDO EL 13 DE juLIO DE 2011 y APRObADO EL 30 DE AGOSTO DE 2011 resumen abstract Mi objetivo en este artículo es plantear My aim in this paper is to raise and discuss y discutir algunas de las preguntas some philosophical questions about Virtual filosóficas sobre la Realidad Virtual (RV). Reality (VR). The most fundamental El problema fundamental se refiere a problem concerns the ontological nature of la naturaleza ontológica de la realidad VR: is it real or fictional? Is VR comparable virtual: ¿es real o ficticia? ¿La RV es to illusions, hallucinations, dreams, comparable a ilusiones, alucinaciones, or worlds of fiction? Are traditional sueños, o mundos de ficción? ¿Son todas philosophical categories at all sufficient to las categorías filosóficas tradicionales give us understanding of the phenomenon suficientes para darnos la comprensión of VR? In approaching these questions, I del fenómeno de la RV? Para abordar shall employ possible world semantics estas cuestiones, emplearé como mis and logical theories of perception and herramientas filosóficas la semántica de imagination as my philosophical tools. My mundos posibles y las teorías lógicas main conclusion is that VR is comparable de la percepción y la imaginación. Mi to a 3-D picture which can be seen from conclusión principal es que la RV es the inside. comparable a una imagen en 3-D que puede ser vista desde el interior. palabras claVe Key worDs Ficción, alucinación, imaginación, Fiction, hallucination, imagination, percepción, realidad, realidad virtual.
    [Show full text]
  • 1 the Stereotypical Picture of the Russell/Bradley Dispute
    Notes 1 The Stereotypical Picture of the Russell/Bradley Dispute 1 The Order of Merit is restricted to 24 members at anyone time, plus addi­ tional non-UK recipients. At the time of writing there have only been 168 ordinary members of the Order (honorary appointments of figures outside the Commonwealth are additional). 2 Bradley's College Fellowship, obtained in December 1870 and terminable only on marriage or death, had no teaching duties attached. In June 1871 he suffered a severe inflammation of the kidneys which appears to have had permanent effects. It has been suggested, possibly with malice, that the Bradleys in general were disposed to hypochondria; be that as it may, he was prone thereafter to be incapacitated by cold, physical exhaustion or anxiety; hence his retired life. He took an active part in the running of his college, but avoided public occasions. Collingwood records of Bradley in his Autobiography, '[AJlthough I lived within a few hundred yards of him for sixteen years, I never to my knowledge set eyes on him.' But although the history of Bradley's public life is largely that of his books and articles, it is clear that his was not a narrowly bookish existence. To protect his health, he frequently escaped the damp chill of Oxford winters for the kinder weather of southern English and Mediterranean seaside resorts, where company perhaps more congenial than that of an all-male Oxford common room was available. 3 See, for instance, Hylton (1990), p. 1 and the title of Candlish (1998). 4 Recently there have appeared two collections of essays devoted to the philo­ sophy of F.H.
    [Show full text]
  • Bradley's Account of the Self As Appearance: Between Kant's Transcendental Idealism and Hegel's Speculative Idealism
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by Christ University Bengaluru: Open Journal Systems Tattva-Journal of Philosophy 2018, Vol. 10, No. 1, 1-18 ISSN 0975-332X│https://doi.org/10.12726/tjp.19.1 Bradley’s Account of the Self as Appearance: Between Kant’s Transcendental Idealism and Hegel’s Speculative Idealism Damian Ilodigwe* Abstract The constitutive activity of the self and the ground of the unity of the self are two important aspects of understanding the self. This paper attempts to delineate these considerations, tracing their use, function and implications in Bradley‟s thesis on the self. The article argues that for Bradley, the focalization is on the understanding of the self and the relation of thought to reality. Furthermore, the article attempts to locate Bradley‟s account of the self as appearance as a middle course between Kant‟s transcendental idealism to Hegel‟s speculative idealism to demonstrate the overlaps, ruptures, and evolution of the philosophical journey of the concept of the self, its nature, and its expressions. Keywords: Self, Bradley, Transcendental Idealism, Speculative Idealism Preamble Two types of considerations arise in connection to the understanding of the unity of the self. One concern pertains to the constitutive activity of the self–an insight exemplified by Kant‟s doctrine of transcendental unity of apperception. The other relates to the question of the ground of the unity of the self. In accordance * Ss Peter and Paul Major Seminary and University of Ibadan, Nigeria; [email protected] 1 Tattva-Journal of Philosophy, Vol.
    [Show full text]
  • The Problem of Meaning in Nishida's Early Writings Miikael-Adam Lotman
    The Problem of Meaning in Nishida’s Early Writings Miikael-Adam Lotman JSPS Research Fellow, Kyoto University Abstract: This paper revisits a traditional problem in Nishidian scholarship regarding the link between Nishida Kitarō’s maiden work An Inquiry into the Good (1911) and his next major treatise Intuition and Reflection in Self-Consciousness (1917). In this paper I will show that the problem of fact vs. meaning, which is explicitly treated in Intuition and Reflection in Self-Consciousness, is influenced by the writings of Motora Yūjirō. I make the case that Nishida’s adoption of Royce’s thought experiment of “the perfect map of England” as a model for “self-consciousness” was instrumental in his attempt to explain the entirety of reality. In the first section, I show that Nishida’s earliest ambition of explaining everything with the concept of pure experience accommodates his contemporaries’ understanding of the scope and task of philosophy. However, Nishida developed his own explanation of philosophy’s task. According to Nishida, philosophy arises in response to a sense of anguish one feels after contemplating on the meaning of the world. In the second section, I explain why Nishida believed that a reflection on the world’s meaning causes philosophical anguish. This is due to an incompatibility between Nishida’s metaphysical views and a criterion of meaning that he inherited from Motora. This combination left Nishida with a dilemma: either the world has no meaning, or everything has meaning but the world does not exist as a single entity. In the last section, I argue that Royce’s “perfect map of England” offered resolved this dilemma, by showing how the world as a single entity can have meaning in relation to its proper parts.
    [Show full text]
  • Philosophy in a Meaningless Life
    9781474247702_Fm_Final_txt_prf.indd vi 8/26/2015 5:20:44 PM Philosophy in a Meaningless Life 9781474247702_Fm_Final_txt_prf.indd i 8/26/2015 5:20:41 PM Also available from Bloomsbury Th e Bloomsbury Companion to Heidegger , edited by Francois Raff oul and Eric S. Nelson Nietzsche, Nihilism and the Philosophy of the Future , edited by Jeff rey Metzger Nothingness and the Meaning of Life , Nicholas Waghorn Time, Creation and the Continuum , Richard Sorabji Truth and Method , Hans-Georg Gadamer 9781474247702_Fm_Final_txt_prf.indd ii 8/26/2015 5:20:44 PM Philosophy in a Meaningless Life A System of Nihilism, Consciousness and Reality James Tartaglia Bloomsbury Academic An imprint of Bloomsbury Publishing Plc LONDON • OXFORD • NEW YORK • NEW DELHI • SYDNEY 9781474247702_Fm_Final_txt_prf.indd iii 8/26/2015 5:20:44 PM Bloomsbury Academic An imprint of Bloomsbury Publishing Plc 50 Bedford Square 1385 Broadway London New York WC1B 3DP NY 10018 UK USA www.bloomsbury.com BLOOMSBURY and the Diana logo are trademarks of Bloomsbury Publishing Plc First published 2016 Paperback edition first published 2016 © James Tartaglia, 2016 James Tartaglia has asserted his right under the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act, 1988, to be identified as the Author of this work. All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying, recording, or any information storage or retrieval system, without prior permission in writing from the publishers. No responsibility for loss caused to any individual or organization acting on or refraining from action as a result of the material in this publication can be accepted by Bloomsbury or the author.
    [Show full text]
  • Understanding Philosophy of Science
    UNDERSTANDING PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE ‘This is the best introduction to philosophy of science I have read. I will certainly use it. The writing is wonderfully clear without being sim- plistic. It is not at all too difficult for second and third year students. Many of my philosophy of science students have no background in philosophy, and I’m sure they will find the book accessible, informa- tive, and a pleasure to read. I read this manuscript with my students in mind. This is the book we’ve been looking for.’ Peter Kosso, Northern Arizona University Few can imagine a world without telephones or televisions; many depend on computers and the Internet as part of daily life. Without scientific theory, these developments would not have been possible. In this exceptionally clear and engaging introduction to the philosophy of science, James Ladyman explores the philosophical questions that arise when we reflect on the nature of the scientific method and the knowledge it produces. He discusses whether fundamental philosophical questions about knowledge and reality might be answered by science, and considers in detail the debate between realists and antirealists about the extent of scientific knowledge. Along the way, central topics in the philosophy of science, such as the demarcation of science from non-science, induction, confirmation and falsification, the relationship between theory and observation, and relativ- ism, are all addressed. Important and complex current debates over under- determination, inference to the best explanation and the implications of radical theory change are clarified and clearly explained for those new to the subject. The style is refreshing and unassuming, bringing to life the essential ques- tions in the philosophy of science.
    [Show full text]
  • The Ghost of Terror in French Thought a DISSERTATION SUBMITTED to the FACULTY of the GRADUATE SCHOOL of TH
    Modernity and Ethics: The Ghost of Terror in French Thought A DISSERTATION SUBMITTED TO THE FACULTY OF THE GRADUATE SCHOOL OF THE UNIVERSITY OF MINNESOTA BY Mira Reinberg IN PARTIAL FULFILLMENT OF THE REQUIREMENTS FOR THE DEGREE OF DOCTOR OF PHILOSOPHY Bruno Chaouat August 2010 © Mira Reinberg 2010 i Acknowledgements It is perhaps befitting to describe the accomplishment of a dissertation in terms of negative comparison. When climbing a high mountain, studying a difficult text, learning a new language, one can feel a sense of achievement and fulfillment even if one does not consummate the task at hand to a point of mastery. Halting the climb before reaching the summit, putting down the text before its end or resting along the process of absorbing a language do not impede the enjoyment and gratification we draw from these actions. Partial as the process may ultimately be, the distance travelled is sufficiently vast to inspire the traveler with a continuously replenished sense of pride. Writing a dissertation is a different charge. The process takes place on multiple levels; it is as much an exercise in rigorous academic writing as an inquest of our creative ability. Probed and appraised, our thought processes track alongside intellectual, emotional, and physical integrity in the ongoing challenge. Eventually we must reach an endpoint for the work to provide the insight of a finished task. As students, dissertation writers fluctuate between feelings of insufficiency and enthusiasm. A long breath is the categorical imperative. I owe numerous people for their help in sustaining this long breath. Pascale Crépon, Stéphanie Bérard, Muisi Krosi, Kathy Rider, Madeleine Craig, Anna Cavell, Greta Bliss, Becky Halat, Robert St.
    [Show full text]
  • Russell' S Critique of Bradley
    International Journal of Philosophy and Social Sciences. Volume 9, Number 1 (2019), pp. 1-19 © Research India Publications http://www.ripublication.com Russell’ S Critique of Bradley Damian Ilodigwe SS Peter and Paul Major Seminary and University Of Ibadan, Nigeria. E-Mail Address: [email protected] Abstract In the years following Russell’s break with idealism, Russell’s strategy in attacking idealism consists in focusing attention on the whole development from Kant to Hegel relative to the question of the purported transformation of logic into ontology. Russell will not only reject the psychologism of the Kantian and Hegelian paradigms, but he will also radicalize his critique of this procedure, extending it to Hegel’s entire heritage; indeed the idealist tradition as a whole and Bradley in particular. This paper argues that Russell’s rejection of Bradley’s philosophy is a child of Russell’s attitude towards idealism. The assumption that all of idealism is irredeemably psychologistic is a key element in Russell’s treatment of Bradley’s theory of judgement as a species of subject-predicate logic as well as his reception of Bradley’s claim regarding the ‘unreality’ of relations. As a counter point to the assumed psychologism that infects the whole of idealism, Russell will advance his theory of logical atomism, a theory of proposition which dispenses with the role of the mind in judgement. The move to exclude the subject from the epistemological process is presumably a service to the ideal of objectivity; and, to this extent, is continuous with Russell’s anti-idealism. Whereas the whole of idealism tries to secure objectivity by configuring it in terms of subjectivity, Russell’s alternative route for securing objectivity is to de-configure objectivity from subjectivity.
    [Show full text]
  • Josiah Roycels Philosophy of Loyalty
    HISTORY OF PH ILOSO ph Y QUARTERLY Volume 26, Number 1, January 2009 AMERICAN INTERPRETATIONS OF HEGEL: JOSIAH Royce’s PHILOSOPHY OF LOYALTY John Kaag 1. INTRODUCTION here are three kinds of bookshelves in Robbins Library, located on the Tsecond floor of Emerson Hall. There are those that Harvard students use frequently; these are almost always picked over, leaving only a few copies of Rawl’s A Theory of Justice and Russell’s Philosophical Essays behind. There are those that are seldom used, save the few days during exams when students are forced to revisit the history of philosophy. And then there are those that remain largely neglected; these hold the works of American pragmatism. Next to this shelf, in a truly forgotten corner of Robbins, is a very old-looking collection. This collection con- sists of the generous gifts from the personal libraries of the university’s faculty. George Santayana, for example, donated his copies of William James’ Varieties of Religious Experience and Josiah Royce’s The World and the Individual. Royce bequeathed his personal copies of Kant’s first critique, the Metaphysics of Morals, and James Martineau’s A Study of Religion. In many instances, the notable owners of these volumes used them as makeshift notebooks, providing commentary and translations that demonstrate important turns in their thinking. Such is the case with two volumes that will serve as the focus of this article: Royce’s cop- ies of Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit and Logik. On the flysheets and in the margins of the books, Royce provided a detailed interpretation of these texts, the study of which dramatically alters the chronology and study of Royce’s concepts of loyalty and communities of interpretation.
    [Show full text]
  • F. H. Bradley's Neoplatonic Turn in Ethical Studies
    Angles New Perspectives on the Anglophone World 6 | 2018 Experimental Art F. H. Bradley’s Neoplatonic Turn in Ethical Studies (1876) Jean-Paul Rosaye Electronic version URL: http://journals.openedition.org/angles/1077 DOI: 10.4000/angles.1077 ISSN: 2274-2042 Publisher Société des Anglicistes de l'Enseignement Supérieur Electronic reference Jean-Paul Rosaye, « F. H. Bradley’s Neoplatonic Turn in Ethical Studies (1876) », Angles [Online], 6 | 2018, Online since 01 April 2018, connection on 28 July 2020. URL : http://journals.openedition.org/ angles/1077 ; DOI : https://doi.org/10.4000/angles.1077 This text was automatically generated on 28 July 2020. Angles. New Perspectives on the Anglophone World is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution- NonCommercial-ShareAlike 4.0 International License. F. H. Bradley’s Neoplatonic Turn in Ethical Studies (1876) 1 F. H. Bradley’s Neoplatonic Turn in Ethical Studies (1876) Jean-Paul Rosaye 1 According to a persistent interpretation, Francis Herbert Bradley was a major representative of a neo-Hegelian trend that spread in Britain in the late-Victorian period and consolidated into a British Idealist movement. It also insists that this philosophical experiment was short-lived, as it was overwhelmed at the beginning of the 20th century by a philosophical revolution initiated by Bertrand Russell and George Edward Moore. However, this interpretation has been wholly reconsidered since the 1980s following the formidable reassessment not only of Bradley’s metaphysics but also of the impact of the whole movement in British philosophy and politics.1 Russell’s importance as a philosopher has not been undermined in this revision, but it is now accepted that Bradley’s philosophy and the Idealist movement were not a mere transition filling the gap between the old empiricist school of the mid-19th century and the new analytical philosophy of the early 20th century (Rosaye 2012a).
    [Show full text]