GANDHI and the COW: the ETHICS of HUMAN/ANIMAL RELATIONSHIPS MARK JUERGENSMEYER University of California, Berkeley

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

GANDHI and the COW: the ETHICS of HUMAN/ANIMAL RELATIONSHIPS MARK JUERGENSMEYER University of California, Berkeley GANDHI AND THE COW: THE ETHICS OF HUMAN/ANIMAL RELATIONSHIPS MARK JUERGENSMEYER University of california, Berkeley The COlI is a poem of pity •••• • • the ritually defiling to do so; whereas lower JlDther to millions of Indian man­ caste persons JlDre frequently eat meat, and kind. •• CcM protection to me is sure have as their caste occupations the one of the JlDst wonderful phenanena tarming and preparation of hides. Gandhi's in human evolution. [1] vegetarianism was based on different notions (non-violence and nutritional, rather than It is a source of puzzled embarrassment ritual, purity of the body), and COlI protec­ to many Garrlhian admirers, who otherwise find tion was not a necessary correlation to it. in his thoughts a happy marriage of the JlDre For a time during his wayward youth, Gandhi sensible of Hindu concepts and the JlDre pro­ was a meat-eater, and later on in life he is gressive of western values, that Gandhi was said to have recarrnended eating meat to sure­ not JlDre JTDdest in his affection for the COlI. one undernourished for lack of protein, des­ Yet, it may also be argued, as I intend to pite the vigorous opposition of sane of the do, that Gandhi I s bovine peculiarities are upper caste residents of his Ashram at the integral, perhaps' seminal, to the whole of time. [3] Garrlhi also favored the expansion his ethical stance; and that a richer urx:l.er­ of tarmeries, to utilize the hides of cattle standing of the Gandhian symrol of the COlI which had expired through natural deaths. will lead to a JTDdel of human/animal ethics which may be useful in the west, where the present confusion on that issue is despaired Econanic and Political Reasons by the supporters of animal liberation and exacerbated by the sociobiologists. One may argue that instead of sacredotal and custClTliU}' reasons for venerating the COlI, we make no claim that Gandhi's position Gandhi relies fW1damentally on ethical rea­ is representative of Indian culture, for sane sons. Yet, before this argument may be made, of the JlDre traditional reasons for venerat­ one Trnlst acknowledge that Gandhi also had ing the COlI are absent fran Gandhi's ap­ rather practical reasons for regarding the proach. Despite his enigmatic claim that COlI with sane deference. "the central fact of Hinduism is COlI protec­ tion, "[2] Gandhi's COlI is not an especially One of these practical reasons was eco­ religious beast. He does not linger over nanic. The COlI is a useful and vital part of Krishna's lave for the CCMS, as characterized village econauy, and for Gandhi, COlI protec­ in the Haribamsa and the Puranas; nor does tion meant COlI care, the maintenance of cat­ Gandhi utili,ze the Shaivite irragery of the tle as an important econanic unit. Gandhi scholarly and Ferdinand-like bull, Nandi. might have vieYJed with sure synq;athy the When Gandhi speaks of his "worship" of the efforts of Marvin Harris to make India I s COlI, one should regard this as an alm:>st teeming cattle population appear eCO:lanically metaphorical expression and not expect evi­ advisable. [4] And Gandhi might also have dence of the Mahabna saying prayers and per­ agreed with Alan Heston that the shabby and forming puja in front of cattle or ritually ill-tended CCMS are an econanic nuisance. [5] garlanding them with flowers. Gandhi's veneration of the COlI is also not obviously connected with caste restric­ tions on touching defiled arrl polluted mat­ ter, and eating meat. Ordinarily, In India, PHILOSOPHY PHILOSOPHY upper caste people do not eat Jreat or use leather products, in part because it would be 11 11 In general, Gandhi avoided the issue of whe­ the p:>ssibilities of a Hindu-Muslim alliance ther the CON p:>p.Uation, as presently util­ in Congress. In the 40's, it was the rise of ized, is econanically advantageous or disad­ Muslim nationalism, leading ~ the crea­ vantageous. When Gandhi was presented with tion of Pakistan, and its CO\ID.terpart in the argument, in 1925, by an English writer, militant Hinduism. In both of these instan­ that surplus CXJWS cost Irrlia almost two bil­ ces, Gandhi's camlE!Ilts about CXJWS were meant lion rupees annually, Gandhi admitted that to be words of reconciliation between Hindus there might be an overall public cost to CON and Muslims. Gandhi claimed, for instance, protection, but avowed that "a religious that "it is the Hindus that do OOIo/'""selling senti.Ioont is not worth the name if it is not business, and not the Musalmans," and hence worth paying for. II [6] Gandhi's solution to Hindus are really to blame for <::X)W""-slaugh­ the problem was not to kill off the CXJWS-­ ter. [8] '!be Muslim butcher, Gandhi claimed, which he regarded as being lIOrally rep..1gnant, was simply doing his business, and it was up if not impractical--but, rather, to make the to the Hindu cattle merchant to make the existing CXJWS econanically useful. profession econanically unfeasible. Gandhi was adamantly against the legal ban on CON In fact, the bulk. of Gandhi's writings slaughter, for"it is obviously wrong legally about the CON are essays on the utility of to enforce one's religious practices on those rrcdern dairy techniques, and their feasibili­ who do not share that religion;"[9] rather, ty for Irrlia. Yet, such essays are couched Gandhi urged an improvement in Hindu-Muslim in rhetoric about the sanctity of the CON. relations as the only viable protection of "By every act of cruelty to all" cattle, II the CON. Similar to the econanic issue of Gandhi dis~ God and writes, "we Hinduism•• scientific CON treatment, the p:>litical issue the miserable condition of our cattle." For of Muslim attitudes towards CON slaughter was the proper veneration of the sacred beasts, made plblically palatable by Gandhi through Gandhi is quick to suggest "rrcdel dairy fanns an appeal to Hindu religious sentiment. It and great profitable national institu­ was a mark of Gandhi's ethical agility that tions."[?] he could take a religious notion that usually implied narr~ess and prejudice, and turn it It is clear that whatever other ethical into a concept of progress and harIJOny. and personal reasons Gandhi may have had for speaking kindly of the CON, it had the prac­ tical effect of stirring Hindu sympathies Ethical Bases for eo.. Protection towards scientific dairy techniques. As he Md done on many other occasions, Gandhi was '!be econcmic and p:>litical importance of arousing religious passions in a way that Gandhi's CON should not, however, deter us would effect social change, in this case, fran proceeding apace and reaJgIlizing its econanic change. ethical symbolism. There are two levels of ethical significance: the obvious linkages, Gandhi's interests in the CON also had which Gandhi made explicitly, and those less p:>litical significance, especially in the obvious ethical inferences which we i.rnpJte to context of Hindu-Muslim relations. The Mus­ Gandhi. lims, after all, were the people in India lIOst liable to slaughter CXJWS for beef and Am:mg the obvious ethical elements, the by-products, and public sentiment anong Hin­ =cept of ahimsa, non-violence, loans IIDSt dus for a ban on CON slaughter has always had praninent. Gandhi OCIlIll){l1y would alternate a double edge: the p:>sitive virtues of ve­ paragra:fX1g on CON protection with paragra:fX1g nerating the CON and the negative aspect of on the concept of ahimsa, in an alIJOst litur­ protecting the CON fran its natural enemy, gical litany. '!bere is ancient precedent for the Muslim butcher. It is when Hindu-Muslim that connection, for although there does not tensions are at their IJOst taut that the appear to be evidence that the concept of CON issue of CON protection is IJOst visible and protection emerged at the same time in an­ lIOst visibly dangerous. cient India as that of non-violence, the two concepts certainly appear to develop, but­ I-bst of Gandhi's wrilings about the CON tressed by each other, during the first cen­ were in the early 1920's and in the mid-40's, turies of the Christian era. According to w. two m:::m:mts when Hindu-Muslim relations were Norrran Br~, "the idea of Ahimsa and the In critical. the 20's, the issue centered doctrine of the sanctity of the CON slowly around. the restoration of the Khilafat and gain status together. •• roughly about the ~ '!HE SPEX::IES 12 5th century to the 4th century AD." [10] and many cows. Gandhi persistently uses the singular form, as Irrlians frequently do, in What is distinctive about Gandhi's ap­ referring to the cow. And yet, of course, proach is that ahimsa is interpreted rather there are thousands of cows in Irrlia, each of broadly, to incorporate the ethical concept whan partakes in sore way in a generic sa­ of the unity of all life, and the fX)sitive credness. To harm anyone cow is to lay a injooction to love one's fellow being. Ac­ hand on the cosmic Mother. cording to Gandhi, "the cow merely stands as a symbol, and protection of the cow is the Moreover, not just the cow itself, but least [one] is expected to tmdertake." [11] one's relationship to it, is a resolution of Reverence towards the cow "takes the human the tension, a holistic act. 'ilie cow, after being beyond his species. •• the cow to lIE all, is a dtnnb animal, a thing which produces means the entire sub-human world."[12] For doog and pulls plows; and yet it is imputed Gandhi, cow reverence was a way of expanding to be also a close relative: our very one's consciousness, of gaining an identity mother.
Recommended publications
  • Do “Prey Species” Hide Their Pain? Implications for Ethical Care and Use of Laboratory Animals
    Journal of Applied Animal Ethics Research 2 (2020) 216–236 brill.com/jaae Do “Prey Species” Hide Their Pain? Implications for Ethical Care and Use of Laboratory Animals Larry Carbone Independent scholar; 351 Buena Vista Ave #703E, San Francisco, CA 94117, USA [email protected] Abstract Accurate pain evaluation is essential for ethical review of laboratory animal use. Warnings that “prey species hide their pain,” encourage careful accurate pain assess- ment. In this article, I review relevant literature on prey species’ pain manifestation through the lens of the applied ethics of animal welfare oversight. If dogs are the spe- cies whose pain is most reliably diagnosed, I argue that it is not their diet as predator or prey but rather because dogs and humans can develop trusting relationships and because people invest time and effort in canine pain diagnosis. Pain diagnosis for all animals may improve when humans foster a trusting relationship with animals and invest time into multimodal pain evaluations. Where this is not practical, as with large cohorts of laboratory mice, committees must regard with skepticism assurances that animals “appear” pain-free on experiments, requiring thorough literature searches and sophisticated pain assessments during pilot work. Keywords laboratory animal ‒ pain ‒ animal welfare ‒ ethics ‒ animal behavior 1 Introduction As a veterinarian with an interest in laboratory animal pain management, I have read articles and reviewed manuscripts on how to diagnose a mouse in pain. The challenge, some authors warn, is that mice and other “prey species” © LARRY CARBONE, 2020 | doi:10.1163/25889567-bja10001 This is an open access article distributed under the terms of the CC BY 4.0Downloaded license.
    [Show full text]
  • Abolitionist Animal Rights: Critical Comparisons and Challenges Within the Animal Rights Movement
    WellBeing International WBI Studies Repository 11-2012 Abolitionist Animal Rights: Critical Comparisons and Challenges Within the Animal Rights Movement Corey Lee Wrenn Colorado State University, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://www.wellbeingintlstudiesrepository.org/anirmov Part of the Animal Studies Commons, Civic and Community Engagement Commons, and the Politics and Social Change Commons Recommended Citation Wrenn, C. (2012). Abolitionist animal rights: critical comparisons and challenges within the animal rights movement. Interface, 4(2), 438-458. This material is brought to you for free and open access by WellBeing International. It has been accepted for inclusion by an authorized administrator of the WBI Studies Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Interface: a journal for and about social movements Article Volume 4 (2): 438 - 458 (November 2012) Wrenn, Abolitionist Animal Rights Abolitionist animal rights: critical comparisons and challenges within the animal rights movement Corey Wrenn Abstract The abolitionist movement is an emergent and radical approach to nonhuman animal rights. Calling for a complete cessation in nonhuman animal use through the abolishing of property status for nonhuman animals and an adoption of veganism and nonviolence, this approach stands in stark contrast to mainstream approaches such as humane production and welfare reform. This paper describes the goals and stances of abolitionism; the basic debate between abolitionism and other nonhuman animal rights movements; and the current state, challenges, and future prospects for abolitionism. It is argued that abolitionism, as developed by Francione, is the only morally consistent approach for taking the interests of nonhuman animals seriously.
    [Show full text]
  • A Philosophical Approach to Animal Rights and Welfare in the Tourism Sector Ebru Günlü Küçükaltana,*, S
    PEER-REVIEWED 2019, 1(1): 4-14 https://toleho.anadolu.edu.tr/ FACULTY OF TOURISM A Philosophical Approach to Animal Rights and Welfare in the Tourism Sector Ebru Günlü Küçükaltana,*, S. Emre Dilekb aDepartment of Tourism Administration, Faculty of Business Administration, Dokuz Eylul University, Izmir, Turkey. bSchool of Tourism and Hotel Management, Batman University, Batman, Turkey. ARTICLE INFO ABSTRACT Keywords: Although studies on animal rights and welfare in the field of tourism have begun to emerge in recent years, the subject is still new. In this context, a philosophical approach to animal rights and welfare in the tourism sector is put forward Animal Rights in this study. Concepts commonly used in animal rights and welfare debates, such as moral status, animal love, animal Animal Welfare hatred, speciesism, anthropocentrism, ecocentrism are explained and are then discussed in the context of the tourism Animal Ethics sector on the philosophical basis of what tourism means for commodified animals. Various proposals are developed Tourism for how changes can be made to grant animals in the tourism sector a moral status, both in theory and in practice. 1. Introduction perceptions regarding that animals are kinds of beings Despite never fully succeeding, man has throughout (DeGrazia, 2002). On the basis of this interaction, concepts of history tried to control and dominate nature; the effects animal love (theriophily) and animal hate (misothery) come of this for both humans and non-human beings have been into prominence in the ongoing debate on animal ethics. discussed from different angles in order to further strengthen The epistemological questioning of these two concepts the central position of humans in the cognizable world.
    [Show full text]
  • Minds Without Spines: Evolutionarily Inclusive Animal Ethics
    Animal Sentience 2020.329: Mikhalevich & Powell on Invertebrate Minds Call for Commentary: Animal Sentience publishes Open Peer Commentary on all accepted target articles. Target articles are peer-reviewed. Commentaries are editorially reviewed. There are submitted commentaries as well as invited commentaries. Commentaries appear as soon as they have been reviewed, revised and accepted. Target article authors may respond to their commentaries individually or in a joint response to multiple commentaries. INSTRUCTIONS FOR COMMENTATORS Minds without spines: Evolutionarily inclusive animal ethics Irina Mikhalevich Department of Philosophy, Rochester Institute of Technology Russell Powell Department of Philosophy, Boston University Abstract: Invertebrate animals are frequently lumped into a single category and denied welfare protections despite their considerable cognitive, behavioral, and evolutionary diversity. Some ethical and policy inroads have been made for cephalopod molluscs and crustaceans, but the vast majority of arthropods, including the insects, remain excluded from moral consideration. We argue that this exclusion is unwarranted given the existing evidence. Anachronistic readings of evolution, which view invertebrates as lower in the scala naturae, continue to influence public policy and common morality. The assumption that small brains are unlikely to support cognition or sentience likewise persists, despite growing evidence that arthropods have converged on cognitive functions comparable to those found in vertebrates. The exclusion of invertebrates is also motivated by cognitive-affective biases that covertly influence moral judgment, as well as a flawed balancing of scientific uncertainty against moral risk. All these factors shape moral attitudes toward basal vertebrates too, but they are particularly acute in the arthropod context. Moral consistency dictates that the same standards of evidence and risk management that justify policy protections for vertebrates also support extending moral consideration to certain invertebrates.
    [Show full text]
  • The “Babe” Vegetarians: Bioethics, Animal Minds and Moral Methodology
    WellBeing International WBI Studies Repository 2009 The “Babe” Vegetarians: Bioethics, Animal Minds and Moral Methodology Nathan Nobis Morehouse College Follow this and additional works at: https://www.wellbeingintlstudiesrepository.org/acwp_sata Part of the Animal Studies Commons, Other Anthropology Commons, and the Other Nutrition Commons Recommended Citation Nobis, N. (2009). The "Babe" vegetarians: bioethics, animal minds and moral methodology. In S. Shapshay (Ed.), Bioethics at the movies. Baltimore : Johns Hopkins University Press. (pp. 56-73). This material is brought to you for free and open access by WellBeing International. It has been accepted for inclusion by an authorized administrator of the WBI Studies Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. The “Babe” Vegetarians: Bioethics, Animal Minds and Moral Methodology Nathan Nobis Morehouse College [email protected] “The fact is that animals that don't seem to have a purpose really do have a purpose. The Bosses have to eat. It's probably the most noble purpose of all, when you come to think about it.” – Cat, “Babe” "The animals of the world exist for their own reasons. They were not made for humans any more than black people were made for white, or women created for men." – Alice Walker 1. Animal Ethics as Bioethics According to bioethicist Paul Thompson, “When Van Rensselaer Potter coined the term ‘bioethics’ in 1970, he intended for it to include subjects ranging from human to environmental health, including not only the familiar medical ethics questions . but also questions about humanity's place in the biosphere” (Thompson, 2004). These latter questions include ethical concerns about our use of animals: morally, should animals be on our plates? Should humans eat animals? The fields of animal and agricultural ethics address these questions.
    [Show full text]
  • AS-662-W Animal Welfare and Animal Rights: Ethics, Science and Explanations
    Animal Sciences www.purdue.edu/ansc AS-662-W Animal welfare and animal rights: Ethics, science and explanations Author: Introduction To understand what animal welfare Marisa Erasmus, is, it is helpful to examine some Department of Animal welfare has received a definitions. In 1986, Dr. Donald Animal Sciences, considerable amount of attention Broom defined animal welfare as the Purdue University in recent years and remains an ability of an animal to cope with its important issue in animal agriculture. environment and living conditions. But what is it? How we treat and care Since then, organizations such as for animals? While it is true that the the American Veterinary Medical manner in which we treat animals Association (AVMA, 2017) and World does affect their welfare, animal Organization for Animal Health welfare is not defined as the treatment (OIE, 2020) have incorporated this an animal receives. Rather, animal explanation into their definitions of welfare refers to how an animal is animal welfare. coping with its environment and living conditions. Animal welfare can vary Most people who have a basic from poor to good, along a continuum. understanding of animal welfare This means that animal welfare is are familiar with the Five Freedoms not absolute, but can vary and range (1. Freedom from hunger and thirst. along a scale. Animal welfare changes 2. Freedom from discomfort. 3. over time, and in some cases from Freedom from pain, injury or disease. moment to moment. AS-662-W Animal welfare and animal rights: Ethics, science and explanations. 4. Freedom to express normal behavior. 5. Freedom measures that can be studied, measured and from fear and distress.
    [Show full text]
  • Eating Insects – a Solution Or Another Step in the Wrong Direction? Paper Mickey Gjerris, Helena Röcklinsberg & Christian Gamborg
    EurSafe News VOLUME 21 NO. 3 DECEMBER 2019 Dear EurSafe members, It is my great pleasure to present to you the last EurSafe Newsletter of 2019. Culturally and philosophically based rankings of animals as ‘higher’ or ‘lower’ have taken many forms: More or less like humans, larger or smaller, more or less intelligent etc. Most of EurSafe these rankings have historically speaking left insects in the realm of least important or, indeed, of no importance. This dogma has for various reasons been challenged recently and the CONTENTS present newsletter includes two contributions on the matter of insects in agricultural and food ethics. Eating insects Paper by Mickey Gjerris, Helena In their paper called ‘Eating insects – a solution or another step in the Röcklinsberg & Christian Gamborg | 3 wrong direction?’, Mickey Gjerris, Helena Röcklinsberg and Christian Gamborg address the dilemmas of farming insects for human con- Insects as sustainable feed for a circular economy sumption. Going through both anthropocentric and non-anthropo- Paper by Bernice Bovenkerk, Marcel centric concerns, the authors conclude that replacing conventional Dicke and Marcel Verweij | 8 animal protein with insect protein could solve a number of current ethical problems. However, they caution against a rapid change to in- Animal Experimentation sect farming for human food since there are some “ethical questions Book review by Samuel Camenzind | that need to be examined before even more species are domesticized 10 to serve human needs and preferences with no or little regard for their ethical demands on us.” Victoria Braithwaite Obituary by Bernice Bovenkerk | 12 The second contribution on insect ethics is a report on a four-year | project on insects for feed.
    [Show full text]
  • Ethic for Animals
    WellBeing International WBI Studies Repository 10-2012 A ‘‘Practical’’ Ethic for Animals David Fraser University of British Columbia, [email protected] Follow this and additional works at: https://www.wellbeingintlstudiesrepository.org/ethawel Part of the Animal Studies Commons, Ethics and Political Philosophy Commons, and the Nature and Society Relations Commons Recommended Citation Fraser, D. (2012). A “practical” ethic for animals. Journal of agricultural and environmental ethics, 25(5), 721-746. This material is brought to you for free and open access by WellBeing International. It has been accepted for inclusion by an authorized administrator of the WBI Studies Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. A ‘‘Practical’’ Ethic for Animals David Fraser University of British Columbia KEYWORDS animals, animal ethics, animal welfare, conservation, ethics, environmental ethics ABSTRACT Drawing on the features of ‘‘practical philosophy’’ described by Toulmin (1990), a ‘‘practical’’ ethic for animals would be rooted in knowledge of how people affect animals, and would provide guidance on the diverse ethical concerns that arise. Human activities affect animals in four broad ways: (1) keeping animals, for example, on farms and as companions, (2) causing intentional harm to animals, for example through slaughter and hunting, (3) causing direct but unintended harm to animals, for example by cropping practices and vehicle collisions, and (4) harming animals indirectly by disturbing life- sustaining processes and balances of nature, for example by habitat destruction and climate change. The four types of activities raise different ethical concerns including suffering, injury, deprivation, and death (of individuals), decline of populations, disruption of ecological systems containing animals, and extinction of species.
    [Show full text]
  • Identifying and Preventing Pain in Animals
    WellBeing International WBI Studies Repository 10-2006 Identifying and Preventing Pain in Animals Daniel M. Weary University of British Columbia Lee Niel University of British Columbia Frances C. Flower University of British Columbia David Fraser University of British Columbia Follow this and additional works at: https://www.wellbeingintlstudiesrepository.org/assawel Part of the Animal Studies Commons, Other Animal Sciences Commons, and the Other Anthropology Commons Recommended Citation Weary, D. M., Niel, L., Flower, F. C., & Fraser, D. (2006). Identifying and preventing pain in animals. Applied animal behaviour science, 100(1), 64-76. This material is brought to you for free and open access by WellBeing International. It has been accepted for inclusion by an authorized administrator of the WBI Studies Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. Identifying and Preventing Pain in Animals Daniel M. Weary, Lee Niel, Frances C. Flower, David Fraser University of British Columbia KEYWORDS pain assessment, pain prevention, animal welfare ABSTRACT Animals are routinely subjected to painful procedures, such as tail docking for puppies, castration for piglets, dehorning for dairy calves, and surgery for laboratory rats. Disease and injury, such as tumours in mice and sole ulcers on the feet of dairy cows, may also cause pain. In this paper we describe some of the ways in which the pain that animals experience can be recognized and quantified. We also describe ways in which pain can be avoided or reduced, by reconsidering how procedures are performed and whether they are actually required. Ultimately, reducing the pain that animals experience will require scientific innovation paired with changed cultural values, and willingness to address regulatory, technological and economic constraints.
    [Show full text]
  • Wild Animal Suffering Is Intractable
    DRAFT – do not quote or circulate without permission Please note: This is the penultimate draft of a paper forthcoming in the Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics. Please refer to the published version. The Online First version is available at http://bit.ly/2CQFjOD . Wild animal suffering is intractable Nicolas Delon and Duncan Purves1 Abstract Most people believe that suffering is intrinsically bad. In conjunction with facts about our world and plausible moral principles, this yields a pro tanto obligation to reduce suffering. This is the intuitive starting point for the moral argument in favor of interventions to prevent wild animal suffering (WAS). If we accept the moral principle that we ought, pro tanto, to reduce the suffering of all sentient creatures, and we recognize the prevalence of suffering in the wild then we seem committed to the existence of such a pro tanto obligation. Of course, competing values such as the aesthetic, scientific or moral values of species, biodiversity, naturalness or wildness, might be relevant to the all-things-considered case for or against intervention. Still, many argue that, even if we were to give some weight to such values, no plausible theory could resist the conclusion that WAS is overridingly important. This article is concerned with large-scale interventions to prevent WAS and their tractability and the deep epistemic problem they raise. We concede that suffering gives us a reason to prevent it where it occurs, but we argue that the nature of ecosystems leaves us with no reason to predict that interventions would reduce, rather than exacerbate, suffering.
    [Show full text]
  • Vegetarianism and Animal Ethics in Contemporary Buddhism
    Journal of Buddhist Ethics ISSN 1076–9005 http://blogs.dickinson.edu/buddhistethics Volume 24, 2017 Vegetarianism and Animal Ethics in Contemporary Buddhism Reviewed by Amy Defibaugh Temple University [email protected] Copyright Notice: Digital copies of this work may be made and distributed provided no change is made and no alteration is made to the content. Reproduction in any other format, with the exception of a single copy for private study, requires the written permission of the author. All enquiries to: [email protected]. A Review of Vegetarianism and Animal Ethics in Contemporary Buddhism Amy Defibaugh 1 Vegetarianism and Animal Ethics in Contemporary Buddhism. By James J. Stewart. London: Routledge, 2015, ISBN 1138802166 (hardback), $128.94. In Vegetarianism and Animal Ethics in Contemporary Buddhism, James Stew- art situates his ethnography of contemporary Buddhist practice in Sri Lanka as a site for the formation of a form of modern Theravādin Bud- dhism. Stewart highlights many different Sinhalese Buddhist perspec- tives, both lay and monastic, to shed light on how Buddhists view issues of animal welfare, vegetarianism, and other dietary ethics. Stewart ar- gues that the lived reality of Buddhist traditions for Sinhalese Buddhists is complex and encompasses a variety of voices and practices. Along the- se lines of inquiry, Stewart’s work is positioned within the study of “popular religion,” and valuable in understanding the practices and be- liefs that play out and are lived out on the ground, in the streets, and at times contradictory to canonical Buddhist doctrine. Pointing specifically to the ethical discussions surrounding animal welfare and vegetarian- ism, the author problematizes and disrupts their assumed Buddhist en- dorsement.
    [Show full text]
  • Animal Rights and Food : Beyond Regan, Beyond Vegan
    This is a repository copy of Animal rights and food : beyond Regan, beyond vegan. White Rose Research Online URL for this paper: http://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/157942/ Version: Accepted Version Book Section: Milburn, J. orcid.org/0000-0003-0638-8555 (2016) Animal rights and food : beyond Regan, beyond vegan. In: Rawlinson, M. and Ward, C., (eds.) The Routledge Handbook of Food Ethics. Routledge . ISBN 9781138809130 https://doi.org/10.4324/9781315745503 This is an Accepted Manuscript of a book chapter published by Routledge in The Routledge Handbook of Food Ethics on 1st July 2016, available online: https://www.routledge.com/The-Routledge-Handbook-of-Food-Ethics/Rawlinson-Ward/p/bo ok/9781138809130 Reuse Items deposited in White Rose Research Online are protected by copyright, with all rights reserved unless indicated otherwise. They may be downloaded and/or printed for private study, or other acts as permitted by national copyright laws. The publisher or other rights holders may allow further reproduction and re-use of the full text version. This is indicated by the licence information on the White Rose Research Online record for the item. Takedown If you consider content in White Rose Research Online to be in breach of UK law, please notify us by emailing [email protected] including the URL of the record and the reason for the withdrawal request. [email protected] https://eprints.whiterose.ac.uk/ Animal Rights and Food: Beyond Regan, Beyond Vegan Josh Milburn This is a draft version of a paper appearing in The Routledge Handbook of Food Ethics, edited by Mary C.
    [Show full text]