"Tabula" of Cebes

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

The Salmasius-Elichmann edition of the "Tabula" of Cebes The Harvard community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters Citation Lutz, Cora E. 1979. The Salmasius-Elichmann edition of the "Tabula" of Cebes. Harvard Library Bulletin XXVVII (2), April 1979: 165-171. Citable link https://nrs.harvard.edu/URN-3:HUL.INSTREPOS:37363664 Terms of Use This article was downloaded from Harvard University’s DASH repository, and is made available under the terms and conditions applicable to Other Posted Material, as set forth at http:// nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos:dash.current.terms-of- use#LAA Tl1e Sal111asius- Elichma1111Edition of tl1e Tabula of Cebes Corfl E. Lutz LA UDE DE SAUMAISE ( 1588-165 3) is genera11y kno,vn for a bad error jn judgment, \vhcn, in 1 649, at the instigation of Charles II~ he ,vrote a L.-'1tindefense of King Charles I.1 1,.his -- n1ight have receded into the limbo of comparable n1istakcs ,vhich do not affect the course of history, if John J\1lilton had not \vrit- ten a rcfut~tion of such bitterness and vchen1ence that the incident re~u 1t e d in the v ir tu a 1annihilation of Sa.u 1naise. Salmasius, as he ,vas kno,vn to .i\1ilton2nd is still kno,vn to the schol- arly ,vorld, \Vas the n1ost distinguished cla~-sicistof his generation 111 Europe. A native of Burgundy, he ,vas educated in Paris andin Iicidcl- berg, and eventually served as Professor of Latin at Leyden. Iiis chief in tcrest , vas in t cxtual criticism as I1c strove to produce good and -ac- cura t c texts of son1c of the Greek and Latin authors and to provide adequate commentaries on others. His greatest achievement ,vas his commentary on Solinus' Polyhistor, a vast con1pcndiun1 of natural his- tory largc1)· taken fron1 Pliny. Other classical texts \vhich he edited or commented upon include Florus' ,vork on Roman history and \Tirru- vius' /Je Arcbitectura. Tllrough a curious set of circumstanccs 1 Salmasius gained the ap- preciation of classical scholnrs b)' an act of devotion to the 1nc111oryof his friend and personal physician, Dr. Johannes Elichtnann ( 1600- 16 3 9) . This cn1inent scientist and lingu ist1 ,vho is said to have kno-\vn sjxrcen languages,,vas particu1arl)• interested in Arabic and Persian be- cause he ,vishcd to understand the achicvcn1ents of the Arabic ,vorJd 1 De{en1fo regfo, pro Carolo lt rege Anglinc (Leyd(;n? l650). j Iohannjs J\-tiltonis Def e1nio pro j)Ojntlo .:znglicanotcont1'a Claudii ano11j•Jui, tdias Sab11a;ii,,Defe11sioneu1 regimn (Paris, I 6j 1), Jn thE: Defenrio secunda ( ! 654), ~·Elton says,, uy t tl 1ere arc those who e \'-C n pl ace th c respo ns ihi1i ty for his death on me and 1 on those l, arbs of n1ine, too keen Iy s h-Jrpene d. - Co uzpl et e Prose JV orks of Jo bn Afilton (N~,V" l-lavc-n, u;.,ll6)1 I\T1 559, Harvard University - Houghton Library / Harvard University. Harvard Library bulletin. Cambridge, Mass., Harvard University Library. Volume XXVII, Number 2 (April 1979) Harvnrd Library Bulletin in medicine.3 In the course of his studies he can1c upon an Arabic 1nann- script containing a paraphrase of the Greek text of the Tabula of Cebesj along \yjth that of Theophrastus' Golden Verses.~ The Arabic para- phrase ,vas the ,vork of a ]earned scholar, Ahn1ud ibn 1'vluhan1n1adibn 1\'1iska,vayh( d. lo 3o), ,vho also compiled a collection of lf' ise Sayings and ,vrote a number of treatises on ethical philosophy nnd history ..ti From this Arabic manuscript, Dr. FJichmann prepared an edition of the Tabula of Ce bes ,vith his o,vn Latin translation ,vhich he intended to have prin red along ,vith the Greek The short dialogue is an alicgory of human life, a kind of Pilgrini's Progress,in ,vhich a group of youthsi visiting a temple of Saturn~ sec a strange votive taolet depict~ ing a complex scene \Vhich is interpreted to thcn1 by an Old J\-1anas a representation of the journey of life. It ,vas reputed to have been the ,vork of Cebes the Theban, friend of Socrates, ,vho i~ n1cntioncd by· Plato in the I'baedo,and later by Diogenes I_}acrtiusand Aulus Gellius. After Elichmann's early death, Salmasius bad this ,vork pr1nted -and also E]ichn1ann's ArabicJ J....atin. and Greek vcrsjons of the Anrea Car- 1nhiaof Pythagoras. Prefaced hy an extensive Introduction by· Sal- rnasius,the book ,vas pub1ishedby· I. I\1-aircin Leyden in r640.ij Copies are no, v preserved as treasores in a nu rnber of rare book Iibra ri es, in- eluding Houghton.. · Salmasius ,v3s the ideal person to prepare· EHchmann 's edition for publication. Since he himself \Vas an experienced Arabic scho]ar, he \vent over the text very carefuHy~comparing jt with the Greek. He found, as Elichmann had said, tha.t the Arabic text represented a para- phrase of a Greek manuscript considerably older than those jn exis- tence in his time. To account for numerous inaccuracies ~nd ~ctua.1 errors in the Arabic, he suggests that this ,va.s not surprising since :eL. G. l\1ichaud1 Riogn1p1JieUniversellc, A'11ttcnneet Afoderne (Paris! 1880 ), XIIl 1 14-15, and N e-ue lJeutscbe 11iograpbii?(Berlin, 1959 ), IV, 440. 4 Rijksur1i,·ers-itcit.Bihliotheca Acaden1iae Lugduno-Batav:-lc, Catt1logtH todictan arabicorun1, IV, 19r,. n. r93-3, · 0 i\t Stcinschneider 1 Die rtrahircben Vhersetzungen aus den Griechiscben ( Graz.1 J960), pp. 43~44. App3rently Elichn1~no did not 1<now th~ :.unhor of the paraphrase. See Praef atio, pp s _and 31. Tabula Cebetit 1 Graece, Arnbicet Laiiuet Item Aure.1 Can-11inaPJ·tl1agorae cum parap hrasi Ara b~ca, A ucto re Io han nc EU chman no, l\1.D. Cum Praef ad one Cl. Sal- m asii. L ugd uni Ih ta von11nt Typ is Io h annis 1\·1aire Cl:; I=- C XL. In another vo lu1nc printed i r1the s:ame y.e~I', this occurs as a third volume bound in \\'"ith s~1rn ~s i us' ed i~ tion of Simplidus' Co1JnJ1entary on the E11cbiridian of Epictetus, and a second vol- u ntc of S:aln1asiusi no tcs on th is te.xt. Harvard University - Houghton Library / Harvard University. Harvard Library bulletin. Cambridge, Mass., Harvard University Library. Volume XXVII, Number 2 (April 1979) Sal111asius~Elicb1ni1J~11_Edition of _t(JeTabula of C ebes 1 6 7 Arabic scholars learned Greek fro1n Greek-speaking people "'ho lived many centuries after the classical pcrjod and in lands far removed from ancient Grcece. 1 Apparently the notes and cornmentary ,vhich Elich- mann had expected to publish \Vith the triple texts \Vere not a,Tailablc, so Sal1n a si us himscl f cxa1nincd the text in dctai 1 and furnish cd no tcs on the textual problems he encountered. In scores of instances of ques- tionable rcadingsr he cited cxarnplcs of the classical Greek usage and the findings of the lcxicographcrs. 8 In making his comparisons hcr,vecn the Arabic and the Greek) he depended not sole!y upon the readings from the Greek 1nanuscript used by Elichmann, but he also included those found in other Greek manuscripts to ,vhich he had access.g; II is com men ts .are not Iimi ted to linguistic questions, ,but h c g ivcs his 1n- tcr pr cta tion of the setting of the dialognc~ the participant.s1 the 1neaning of the allegory, and the value of its instruction. Besides .serving as a high tribute to the· 111cn1oryof his friend and tcstin1onial to his rc1narkablc achievements in con1parative linguis- tics/0 the edition of the triple text of the Tabula rightly seen1~d to Sa.hn~siusto constitute a significant ~dvancc in the study of this little book ,vhich had a remarkah]c impact upon scholars fron:i the time of the Renaissance into the eighteenth century·. Briefly, the history· of the text before Elichmann'.s tin1e is this. Apparently the dialogue composed hy· the Thehan Cebcs, frjend of Socr,ates.,,v:1s lostJ but in the first century of our era, a short composition of the same namet ,vritten in simple, classical Greek~ made its appcar~ncc and ,vas n1cntioned by J..,.ucianand TcrtuHian, ,,,.ho considered it the originaL It is preserved in thirteen Greek manuscriptstonly t,vo of ,vhich ,vcrc copied before the fifteenth centut)T· In addition to the jntrinsic appeal of the lively dialogue) the interest of the hu1nanists in the Platonic School n1ay account in :son1e degree for the \vidc popularity of the Tahu!«. It \Vas first trans]ated 1 Sal1nasiu~'I'raef ~tio covcr.s 3 3 unnulnbc.rcd pages. llis rcnr.irks on the faulty kno,vkdgc of GrQck by the A:r~hic scho1~rs occurs on p1gcs 7 and 8 of my nun1bcr- in g. On p~gcs 6 and 9 he note~ :.:1.n instance of a s trio us error '-V hen the Arabic calls the niai(l hltcrlocuwr of the di~loguc. 1-3:cr~dcs instead of the Old l'vlan. s 14 pages of the Praefntio arn given to a consideration of individual words and phrascs of the dial o guc. Praefraloi p, 14. 10 On page 4 of the Fraefatio, Salinasius dfacusses Elich1nann's theory of the rela- tionship of the Persian and Arabic 1angua gcs ,vi th Gre ck, -a.nd a l:so the common an- c:e~try of these and the GE:rrn-an languages.
Recommended publications
  • From Hades to the Stars: Empedocles on the Cosmic Habitats of Soul', Classical Antiquity, Vol
    Edinburgh Research Explorer From Hades to the stars Citation for published version: Trepanier, S 2017, 'From Hades to the stars: Empedocles on the cosmic habitats of soul', Classical Antiquity, vol. 36, no. 1, pp. 130-182. https://doi.org/10.1525/ca.2017.36.1.130 Digital Object Identifier (DOI): 10.1525/ca.2017.36.1.130 Link: Link to publication record in Edinburgh Research Explorer Document Version: Publisher's PDF, also known as Version of record Published In: Classical Antiquity Publisher Rights Statement: Published as Trépanier, S. 2017. From Hades to the Stars: Empedocles on the Cosmic Habitats of Soul, Classical Antiquity, Vol. 36 No. 1, April 2017; (pp. 130-182) DOI: 10.1525/ca.2017.36.1.130. © 2017 by the Regents of the University of California. Authorization to copy this content beyond fair use (as specified in Sections 107 and 108 of the U. S. Copyright Law) for internal or personal use, or the internal or personal use of specific clients, is granted by the Regents of the University of California for libraries and other users, provided that they are registered with and pay the specified fee via Rightslink® or directly with the Copyright Clearance Center. General rights Copyright for the publications made accessible via the Edinburgh Research Explorer is retained by the author(s) and / or other copyright owners and it is a condition of accessing these publications that users recognise and abide by the legal requirements associated with these rights. Take down policy The University of Edinburgh has made every reasonable effort to ensure that Edinburgh Research Explorer content complies with UK legislation.
    [Show full text]
  • The Minotaur in Phaedo's Labyrinth: Philosophy's Necessary Myth
    Trinity College Trinity College Digital Repository Trinity Publications (Newspapers, Yearbooks, The Trinity Papers (2011 - present) Catalogs, etc.) 2016 The Minotaur in Phaedo’s Labyrinth: Philosophy’s Necessary Myth Gregory Convertito Trinity College, Hartford Connecticut Follow this and additional works at: https://digitalrepository.trincoll.edu/trinitypapers Part of the Classical Literature and Philology Commons Recommended Citation Convertito, Gregory, "The Minotaur in Phaedo’s Labyrinth: Philosophy’s Necessary Myth". The Trinity Papers (2011 - present) (2016). Trinity College Digital Repository, Hartford, CT. https://digitalrepository.trincoll.edu/trinitypapers/43 The Minotaur in Phaedo’s Labyrinth: Philosophy’s Necessary Myth Gregory Convertito Plato’s Phaedo is a confusing dialogue. It takes place after the Apology and the Crito, on Socrates’s last night before his execution; Socrates has been waiting in prison for a long time due to an Athenian law barring executions during the annual ritual to celebrate Theseus’s mythical victory over the Minotaur. This story of the death of Socrates is embedded in a narration by Phaedo himself, who is relating the story to Echecrates. Socrates, after discussing the soul, the self, immortality, and death with Simmias and Cebes, Pythagorean acquaintances who have come to visit him, drinks the φαρμακον and dies. The myth of the Minotaur—a monster which has the body of a man and the head of a bull—is explicitly invoked in the text, which structurally mirrors this myth. Each has a monster, fourteen characters, and a thread which leads out of a labyrinth. In the myth, Theseus and the others are taken into the labyrinth wherein the Minotaur resides as tribute, as dictated by the Delphic Oracle, and the princess Ariadne gives Theseus a ball of thread to attach to the entrance, so he may find his way out again.
    [Show full text]
  • Teleology in the ​Phaedo's Biographical Account
    4 Teleology in the Phaedo’s Biographical Account ​ ​ José Manuel Osorio The aim of this paper is to clarify the first section of Socrates's biographical account (the 1 so-called first sailing) in Phaedo (96a-99d). ​ Specifically, the aim is to have a better ​ ​ ​ understanding regarding the teleological argument about the intellect in Socrates's speech. This is a complex and difficult passage which has been subjected to a series of what, in my view, are contradictory interpretations. Broadly speaking, it is possible to distinguish two very different groups of interpretations of the teleological arguments in the first part of the biographical section. In the first interpretation, scholars looking for the roots of the teleological arguments of the Timaeus arrive at the conclusion that they lie in the Phaedo. For this group of scholars, Plato ​ ​ ​ ​ employs a teleological argument in Socrates’s biographical account in the Phaedo, although it is ​ ​ 2 considered to be in schematic form when compared to the one employed in the Timaeus. ​ In the ​ ​ second interpretation, scholars focusing exclusively on the Phaedo’s biographical passage argue ​ ​ ​ 3 ​ that teleological arguments are not used by Plato in the Phaedo ​ since Socrates said in the first ​ ​ part of the biographical passage that he was completely incapable of finding a teleological cause (99c-d).4 ​ The upshot is this: studies of the Phaedo support the thesis that teleology is not present in ​ ​ the dialogue, while studies of the Timaeus support the opposite, namely, that in Socrates’s ​ ​ biographical account teleology is present. So there seems to be a contradiction in the literature about the place of teleology in the Phaedo.
    [Show full text]
  • An Interpretation of Platoʼs Ideas and Criticism of Parmenides According to Peanoʼs Ideography
    Athens Journal of Humanities & Arts - Volume 5, Issue 1 – Pages 13-28 An Interpretation of Platoʼs Ideas and Criticism of Parmenides according to Peanoʼs Ideography By Giuseppe Boscarino Anyone who studies the Platonic work finds great difficulty in interpreting the precise meaning of his ontological terms, which are most often enveloped in an obscure and mystical language. Aristotle already emphasized the allegorical and poetic meaning of the platonic terms "imitation" and "participation," related to the sensible things, "copies" of the "ideas." I have asked myself then the following question: Is there a rational and logical nucleus within the mystical and mythological shell of Platonism? Studying the mathematical ideography of Peano, a great logician, mathematician and contemporary linguist, elicited the following question: can we make an ideographic translation of Platoʼs ontological terms in the same way Peano did for aspects of Euclidʼs work? We demonstrate a possible valid, rational, and logical nucleus of certain Platonic nomenclature beyond the mists of certain metaphysical interpretation, while also showing Platoʼs criticism of Parmenides to be invalid in the light of Peanoʼs ideography. Difficulty in the Interpretation of Platonic Theory in Educational and Historiographical Processes Many students have experienced the darkness, ambiguity and vagueness of philosophical language in the study of the history of philosophy. This turns into difficulty whenever the teacher has to explain to young students the thoughts of a philosopher, using the most limpid and clear language possible. Thus, texts on the history of philosophy instead of helping young people to escape from imprecise, vague and primitive ways of reasoning, rather accentuate this aspect, exposing the thinking of philosophers in even more obscure and ambiguous ways than seen in the original source.
    [Show full text]
  • Meet the Philosophers of Ancient Greece
    Meet the Philosophers of Ancient Greece Everything You Always Wanted to Know About Ancient Greek Philosophy but didn’t Know Who to Ask Edited by Patricia F. O’Grady MEET THE PHILOSOPHERS OF ANCIENT GREECE Dedicated to the memory of Panagiotis, a humble man, who found pleasure when reading about the philosophers of Ancient Greece Meet the Philosophers of Ancient Greece Everything you always wanted to know about Ancient Greek philosophy but didn’t know who to ask Edited by PATRICIA F. O’GRADY Flinders University of South Australia © Patricia F. O’Grady 2005 All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise without the prior permission of the publisher. Patricia F. O’Grady has asserted her right under the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act, 1988, to be identi.ed as the editor of this work. Published by Ashgate Publishing Limited Ashgate Publishing Company Wey Court East Suite 420 Union Road 101 Cherry Street Farnham Burlington Surrey, GU9 7PT VT 05401-4405 England USA Ashgate website: http://www.ashgate.com British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data Meet the philosophers of ancient Greece: everything you always wanted to know about ancient Greek philosophy but didn’t know who to ask 1. Philosophy, Ancient 2. Philosophers – Greece 3. Greece – Intellectual life – To 146 B.C. I. O’Grady, Patricia F. 180 Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Meet the philosophers of ancient Greece: everything you always wanted to know about ancient Greek philosophy but didn’t know who to ask / Patricia F.
    [Show full text]
  • Immortality in Empedocles
    View metadata, citation and similar papers at core.ac.uk brought to you by CORE provided by St Andrews Research Repository apeiron 2016; aop Alex Long* Immortality in Empedocles DOI 10.1515/apeiron-2015-0054 Abstract: The paper examines Empedocles’ attributions of immortality. I argue that Empedocles does not withhold immortality from the gods but rather has an unorthodox conception of what immortality is. Immortality does not mean, or imply, endless duration. A god’s immortality is its continuity, as one and the same organism, over a long but finite period. This conception of divine immor- tality then influences Empedocles’ other attributions of immortality, each of which marks a contrast with discontinuity, real or apparent. The nature of this contrast varies from context to context, and there is considerable heterogeneity in the list of immortal items. On the other hand, the attribution of immortality never implies that the item is completely changeless. Keywords: empedocles, immortality, gods, theology Empedocles identifies himself as a daimôn (B115) and elsewhere as a god (B112), but his account of the cosmic cycle suggests that daimones and gods, or at least some gods, do not last forever. Despite claiming to have attained godhood he does not believe that his existence will continue endlessly into the future. It is natural to contrast Empedocles’ eschatology with the account of the soul that Socrates eventually vindicates in Plato’s Phaedo,1 according to which the soul will never perish, whatever else may befall it. How is the contrast between Empedocles and Plato best expressed? We may find it natural to say that Empedoclean gods, unlike Platonic souls, are “mortal”, not “immortal”.
    [Show full text]
  • The Attunement Theory of the Soul in the Phaedo Naoya Iwata
    Naoya Iwata: The Attunement Theory of the Soul The Attunement Theory of the Soul in the Phaedo Naoya Iwata 0. Introduction At Phaedo 86b7–c2 Plato makes Simmias, one of Socrates’ main interlocutors in the dialogue, present the theory that the soul is the ‘blend’ (κρᾶσις) and ‘attunement’ (ἁρμονία) of the hot, cold, dry, wet and certain other such things that make taut and hold together the body.1 According to this theory, when those things are properly and proportionately held together, the soul exists as a sort of attunement; when, on the other hand, they are improperly and disproportionately loosened or tautened because of illness or for some other reasons, the soul perishes at once, just like other sorts of attunement. Simmias thus casts serious doubt upon Socrates’ previous arguments in the dialogue that the soul is immortal. Who originated this attunement theory of the soul is a historical conundrum: there is no reliable evidence for identifying its authorship. Among the older thinkers, however, there is one attribution that receives some support from ancient writers: the Pythagoreans, especially Philolaus. For example, Plotinus, Olympiodorus and Philoponus discuss the view that the soul is an attunement by reference to the Pythagoreans;2 Macrobius, more specifically, reports that Pythagoras and Philolaus said that the soul was an attunement. 3 However, Plotinus and Philoponus, presumably bearing in mind Plato’s arguments against the attunement theory in the Phaedo, takes pains to distinguish the Pythagorean attunement theory from the one Simmias introduces in our passage, that the soul is the attunement of bodily elements.
    [Show full text]
  • Overturning the Paradigm of Identity with Gilles Deleuze's Differential
    A Thesis entitled Difference Over Identity: Overturning the Paradigm of Identity With Gilles Deleuze’s Differential Ontology by Matthew G. Eckel Submitted to the Graduate Faculty as partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Master of Arts Degree in Philosophy Dr. Ammon Allred, Committee Chair Dr. Benjamin Grazzini, Committee Member Dr. Benjamin Pryor, Committee Member Dr. Patricia R. Komuniecki, Dean College of Graduate Studies The University of Toledo May 2014 An Abstract of Difference Over Identity: Overturning the Paradigm of Identity With Gilles Deleuze’s Differential Ontology by Matthew G. Eckel Submitted to the Graduate Faculty as partial fulfillment of the requirements for the Master of Arts Degree in Philosophy The University of Toledo May 2014 Taking Gilles Deleuze to be a philosopher who is most concerned with articulating a ‘philosophy of difference’, Deleuze’s thought represents a fundamental shift in the history of philosophy, a shift which asserts ontological difference as independent of any prior ontological identity, even going as far as suggesting that identity is only possible when grounded by difference. Deleuze reconstructs a ‘minor’ history of philosophy, mobilizing thinkers from Spinoza and Nietzsche to Duns Scotus and Bergson, in his attempt to assert that philosophy has always been, underneath its canonical manifestations, a project concerned with ontology, and that ontological difference deserves the kind of philosophical attention, and privilege, which ontological identity has been given since Aristotle.
    [Show full text]
  • Illinois Classical Studies
    UNIVERSITY OF ILLINOIS LIBRARY AT URBANA-CHAMPAIGN CLASSICS The Minimum Fee for NOTICE: Return or renew all Library Materialsl each Lost Book is $50.00. for The person charging this material is responsible it was withdrawn its return to the Ubrary from which below. on or before the Latest Date stamped are reasons for discipli- TheM, mutilation, and underlining of books from the University. nary action and may result in dismissal 333-8400 To renew call Telephone Center, URBANA-CHAMPAIGN UNIVERSITY OF ILLINOIS LIBRARY AT L161—O-1096 <2.<-K S^f-T? ILLINOIS CLASSICAL STUDIES VOLUME XI. 1 &2 SPRING/FALL 1986 J. K. Newman, Editor ISSN 0363-1 923 ILLINOIS CLASSICAL STUDIES VOLUME XI 1986 J. K. Newman, Editor Patet omnibus Veritas; nondum est occupata; multum ex ilia etiam futuris relictum est. Sen. Epp. 33. 11 SCHOLARS PRESS ISSN 0363-1923 ILLINOIS CLASSICAL STUDIES VOLUME XI Problems of Greek Philosophy ©1986 The Board of Trustees University of Illinois Copies of the journal may be ordered from: Scholars Press Customer Services P.O. Box 6525 Ithaca, New York 14851 Printed in the U.S.A. ADVISORY EDITORIAL COMMITTEE John J. Bateman David F. Bright Howard Jacobson Miroslav Marcovich Responsible Editor: J. K. Newman The Editor welcomes contributions, which should not normally exceed twenty double-spaced typed pages, on any topic relevant to the elucidation of classical antiquity, its transmission or influence. Con- sistent with the maintenance of scholarly rigor, contributions are especially appropriate which deal with major questions of interpre- tation, or which are likely to interest a wider academic audience.
    [Show full text]
  • The Concept of Presocratic Philosophy Its Origin, Development
    © Copyright, Princeton University Press. No part of this book may be distributed, posted, or reproduced in any form by digital or mechanical means without prior written permission of the publisher. CHAPTER 1 ~ Presocratics: Ancient Antecedents The term “PresOcratIc” Is a modern creatIOn. The earlI- est attestation discovered so far is found in a manual of the univer- sal history of philosophy published in 1788 by J.- A. Eberhard (the addressee of a famous letter by Kant): one section is entitled “Pre- socratic Philosophy” (“vorsokratische Philosophie”).1 But the idea that there is a major caesura between Socrates and what preceded him goes back to Antiquity. In order to understand the modern debates that have developed around the Presocratics, it is indispensable to go back to these ancient Presocratics, whom by convention I pro- pose to designate “pre- Socratics” (in lowercase, and with a hyphen), in order to distinguish them from the “Presocratics,” the historio- graphical category to whose creation they contributed but under which they cannot be entirely subsumed. Even if undeniable simi- larities make the ancient “pre- Socratics” the natural ancestors of our modern Presocratics, the differences between the two groups are in fact not less significant, in particular with regard to the stakes involved in both of them. Antiquity knew of two ways to conceive of the dividing line be- tween what preceded Socrates and what followed him: either Soc- rates abandoned a philosophy of nature for the sake of a philosophy of man (this is the perspective that I shall call Socratic- Ciceronian, which also includes Xenophon), or he passed from a philosophy of things to a philosophy of the concept (this is the Platonic- Aristotelian tradition).
    [Show full text]
  • Notes on Plato's Phaedo
    Sean Hannan The Examined Life Autumn 2015 Notes on Plato’s Phaedo 1. Background a. The Phaedo tells the story of Socrates’ final days. Taking place after the events depicted in the Euthyphro, Apology, and Crito, this dialogue serves as his swansong. b. Whereas the Apology had a fairly straightforward structure, consisting mainly of Socrates’ monologues to the citizens of Athens (with a bit of back-and-forth with Meletus thrown in), the Phaedo is a full-blown dialogue. In fact, it operates as a dialogue on multiple levels. First we have the framing dialogue, which consists of the eponymous main character Phaedo’s account of Socrates’ final words, which he gives to Echecrates and others on his way home from Athens. Then we have the dialogue recounted by Phaedo, which takes place between Socrates and those who were with him in his final hours. c. First, let’s take a closer look at the framing dialogue. Phaedo (the character) is on his way back from Athens after attending the trial and execution of Socrates. As he approaches his hometown of Elis in the Peloponnese, he runs into a group of Pythagoreans, the most vocal of which is Echecrates. These men are dubbed ‘Pythagoreans’ because they follow the teachings of Pythagoras. While most of us are familiar with his theorem, Pythagoras had much more to say on the topics of philosophy and mathematics. For our purposes here, we should only note these Pythagoreans would’ve been especially open to the mathematical examples Phaedo tells them Socrates made use of in his final conversation—e.g., the difference between odd and even numbers, etc.
    [Show full text]
  • EK Schreiber
    E.K. Schreiber Rare Books List of 16th- 18th-Century Books And a Remarkable Early 15th-Century MS Document 285 Central Park West . New York, NY 10024 Telephone: (212) 873-3180; (212) 873-3181 Email: [email protected] Web: www.ekslibris.com ***Visitors by Appointment Only*** E.K. Schreiber. New York, NY 10024. (212) 873-3180 [email protected] ______________________________________________________________________________________ 1. AESCHYLUS. [Greek] Αἰσχύλου τραγωδιάι Ζ ... σχολία εἰς τὰς αὐτὰς τραγωδίας. Aeschyli Tragoediae VII. (Ed. P. Vettori & H. Estienne). [Geneva]: Henri Estienne, 1557. $5,600 4to (leaf size: 244 x 170 mm), [4] leaves, 397 (numbered 395: with 2 unnumbered pages [fol. n2] between pp. 138 and 139) pp., [1] blank leaf. Greek type; Estienne device [Schreiber 15] on title. 18th-century white calf, double gilt fillet round sides, brown morocco label on spine titled in gilt; all edges gilt; copy ruled in red throughout; on the front paste-down is the engraved armorial bookplate of Robert Shafto, Esq., of Benwell; on the rear paste-down is the engraved armorial bookplate of William Adair, Esq.; old, unobtrusive ownership signature on title; binding somewhat soiled; overall a fine, wide-margined copy. First complete edition of the tragedies of the first dramatist of Western civilization. This edition is important for including the editio princeps of Agamemnon, the greatest Aeschylean tragedy, and one of the greatest masterpieces of Western dramatic literature. The three previous editions (the Aldine of 1518, and Robortello's and Turnèbe's editions of 1552) had all been based on a manuscript tradition exhibiting a lacuna of more than two-thirds of Agamemnon.
    [Show full text]