We Are Not Your Real Parents: Telling Causal from Confounded Using MDL

Total Page:16

File Type:pdf, Size:1020Kb

We Are Not Your Real Parents: Telling Causal from Confounded Using MDL We Are Not Your Real Parents: Telling Causal from Confounded using MDL David Kaltenpoth◦ Jilles Vreeken• Abstract K P Z + K P X Z + K P Y Z , will be lower than the ¹ ¹ ºº ¹ ¹ j ºº ¹ ¹ j ºº Given data over variables X ; :::; Xm;Y we consider the problem complexity corresponding to the model where X causes Y , ¹ 1 º of nding out whether X jointly causes Y or whether they are all K P Z + K P X + K P Y X . As we obviously do not confounded by an unobserved latent variable Z. To do so, we take an ¹ ¹ ºº ¹ ¹ ºº ¹ ¹ j ºº have access to P Z , we propose to estimate it using latent information-theoretic approach based on Kolmogorov complexity. ¹ º In a nutshell, we follow the postulate that rst encoding the true factor modelling. Second, as Kolmogorov complexity is not cause, and then the eects given that cause, results in a shorter computable, we use the Minimum Description Length (MDL) description than any other encoding of the observed variables. e ideal score is not computable, and hence we have to ap- principle as a well-founded approach to approximate it from proximate it. We propose to do so using the Minimum Description above. is is the method that we develop in this paper. Length (MDL) principle. We compare the MDL scores under the In particular, we consider the seing where given a models where X causes Y and where there exists a latent variables sample over the joint distribution P X;Y of continuous- Z confounding both X and Y and show our scores are consistent. To ¹ º nd potential confounders we propose using latent factor modeling, valued univariate or multivariate random variable X = in particular, probabilistic PCA (PPCA). X ;:::; X , and a continuous-valued scalar Y . Although it Empirical evaluation on both synthetic and real-world data ¹ 1 mº shows that our method, CoCa, performs very well—even when has received lile aention so far, we are not the rst to study the true generating process of the data is far from the assumptions this problem. Recently, Janzing and Scholkopf¨ [9, 10] showed made by the models we use. Moreover, it is robust as its accuracy how to measure the “structural strength of confounding” goes hand in hand with its condence. for linear models using resp. spectral analysis [9] and ICA [10]. Rather than implicitly measuring the signicance, 1 Introduction we explicitly model the hidden confounder Z via probabilistic Causal inference from observational data, i.e. inferring PCA. While this means our approach is also linear in nature, cause and eect from data that was not collected through it gives us the advantage that we can fairly compare the randomized controlled trials, is one of the most challenging scores for the models X Y and X Z Y , allowing us ! ! and important problems in statistics [21]. One of the to dene a reliable condence measure. main assumptions in causal inference is that of causal rough extensive empirical evaluation on synthetic suciency. at is, to make sensible statements on the causal and real-world data, we show that our method, CoCa, short relationship between two statistically dependent random for Confounded-or-Causal, performs well in practice. is variables X and Y , it is assumed that there exists no hidden includes seings where the modelling assumptions hold, confounder Z that causes both X and Y. In practice this but also in adversarial seings where they do not. We assumption is oen violated—we seldom know all factors show that CoCa beats both baselines as well as the recent that could be relevant, nor do we measure everything—and proposals mentioned above. Importantly, we observe that hence existing methods are prone to spurious inferences. our condence score strongly correlates with accuracy. at arXiv:1901.06950v1 [cs.LG] 21 Jan 2019 In this paper, we study the problem of inferring whether is, for those cases where we observe a large dierence X andY are causally related, or, are more likely jointly caused between the scores for causal resp. confounded, we can by an unobserved confounding variable Z. To do so, we trust CoCa to provide highly accurate inferences. build upon the algorithmic Markov condition (AMC) [8]. e main contributions of this paper are as follows, we is recent postulate states that the simplest—measured (a) extend the AMC with latent factor models, and propose in terms of Kolmogorov complexity—factorization of the to instantiate it via probabilistic PCA, joint distribution coincides with the true causal model. (b) dene a consistent and easily computable MDL-score Simply put, this means that if Z causes both X and Y the to instantiate the framework in practice, complexity of the factorization according to this model, (c) provide extensive evaluation on synthetic and real data, including comparisons to the state-of-the-art. ◦Max Planck Institute for Informatics and Saarland University, is paper is structured as usual. In Sec. 2 we introduce Saarbrucken,¨ Germany. [email protected] basic concepts of causal inference, and hidden confounders. •Helmholtz Center for Information Security and Max Planck Institute for Informatics, Saarbrucken,¨ Germany. [email protected] We formalize our information theoretic approach to inferring causal or confounded in Sec. 3. We discuss related work in factorize the joint distribution over the measured variables, Sec. 4, and present the experiments in Sec. 5. Finally, we wrap up with discussion and conclusions in Sec. 6. 2 Causal Inference and Confounding m Ö In this work, we consider the seing where we are given P X ;:::; X = P X PA : ¹ 1 mº ¹ i j i º n samples from the joint distribution P X;Y over two i=1 ¹ º statistically dependent continuous-valued random variables at is, we can write it as a product of the marginal Y Y X and . We require to be a scalar, i.e. univariate, but distributions of each Xi conditioned on its true causal parents allow X = X ;:::; Xm to be of arbitrary dimensionality, ¹ 1 º PAi . is is referred to as the causal Markov condition, and i.e. univariate or multivariate. Our task is to determine implies that, under all of the above assumptions, we can have whether it is more likely that X jointly cause Y , or that a hope of reconstructing the causal graph from a sample from there exists an unobserved random variable Z = Z ;:::; Z ¹ 1 k º the joint distribution. that is the cause of both X and Y. Before we detail our approach, we introduce some basic notions, and explain why 2.2 Crude Solutions at Do Not Work Based on the the straightforward solution does not work. above, many methods have been proposed to infer causal relationships from a dataset. We give a high level overview 2.1 Basic Setup It is impossible to do causal inference of the state of the art in Sec. 4. Here, we continue to discuss from observational data without making assumptions [21]. why it is dicult to determine whether a given pair X;Y at is, we can only reason about what we should observe in is confounded or not, and in particular, why traditional the data if we were to change the causal model, if we assume approaches based on probability theory or (conditional) (properties of) a causal model in the rst place. independence, do not suce. A core assumption in causal inference is that the data To see this, let us rst suppose that X causes Y , and was drawn from a probabilistic graphical model, a casual there are is no hidden confounder Z. We then have P X;Y = ¹ º directed acyclic graph (DAG). To have a ghting chance to P X P Y X , and X Y . Now, let us suppose instead that Z ¹ º ¹ j º 6?? recover this causal graph G from observational data, we have causes X and Y, i.e. X Z Y . en we would have ! to make two further assumptions. e rst, and in practice P X;Y; Z = P Z P X Z P Y Z , and, importantly, while ¹ º ¹ º ¹ j º ¹ j º most troublesome is that of causal suciency. is assump- X Y Z, we still observe X Y , and hence cannot ?? j 6?? tion is satised if we have measured all common causes of determine causal or confounded on that alone. all measured variables. is is related to Reichenbach’s prin- Moreover, as we are only given a sample over P X;Y ¹ º ciple of common cause [25], which states that if we nd that for which X Y holds, but know nothing about Z or P Z , 6?? ¹ º two random variables X and Y are statistically dependent, we cannot directly measure X Y Z. A simple approach denoted as X Y , there are three possible explanations. Ei- ?? jˆ ˆ 6?? would be to see if we can generate a Z such that X Y Z; ther X causes Y , X Y , or, the other way around, Y causes ?? j ! for example through sampling or optimization. However, X, X Y , or there is a third variable Z that causes both X ˆ as we have to assign n values for Z, this means we have and Y, X Z Y . In order to determine the laer case, ! n degrees of freedom, and it easy to see that under these we need to have measured Z. conditions it is always possible to generate a Zˆ that achieves e second additional assumption we have to make is this independence, even when there was no confounding Z.
Recommended publications
  • Causal Inference with Information Fields
    Causal Inference with Information Fields Benjamin Heymann Michel De Lara Criteo AI Lab, Paris, France CERMICS, École des Ponts, Marne-la-Vallée, France [email protected] [email protected] Jean-Philippe Chancelier CERMICS, École des Ponts, Marne-la-Vallée, France [email protected] Abstract Inferring the potential consequences of an unobserved event is a fundamental scientific question. To this end, Pearl’s celebrated do-calculus provides a set of inference rules to derive an interventional probability from an observational one. In this framework, the primitive causal relations are encoded as functional dependencies in a Structural Causal Model (SCM), which maps into a Directed Acyclic Graph (DAG) in the absence of cycles. In this paper, by contrast, we capture causality without reference to graphs or functional dependencies, but with information fields. The three rules of do-calculus reduce to a unique sufficient condition for conditional independence: the topological separation, which presents some theoretical and practical advantages over the d-separation. With this unique rule, we can deal with systems that cannot be represented with DAGs, for instance systems with cycles and/or ‘spurious’ edges. We provide an example that cannot be handled – to the extent of our knowledge – with the tools of the current literature. 1 Introduction As the world shifts toward more and more data-driven decision-making, causal inference is taking more space in applied sciences, statistics and machine learning. This is because it allows for better, more robust decision-making, and provides a way to interpret the data that goes beyond correlation Pearl and Mackenzie [2018].
    [Show full text]
  • Automating Path Analysis for Building Causal Models from Data
    From: AAAI Technical Report WS-93-02. Compilation copyright © 1993, AAAI (www.aaai.org). All rights reserved. AutomatingPath Analysis for Building Causal Models from Data: First Results and Open Problems Paul R. Cohen Lisa BaUesteros AdamCarlson Robert St.Amant Experimental KnowledgeSystems Laboratory Department of Computer Science University of Massachusetts, Amherst [email protected]@cs.umass.edu [email protected] [email protected] Abstract mathematical basis than path analysis; they rely on evidence of nonindependence, a weaker criterion than Path analysis is a generalization of multiple linear regres- path analysis, which relies on evidence of correlation. sion that builds modelswith causal interpretations. It is Thosealgorithms will be discussed in a later section. an exploratory or discovery procedure for finding causal structure in correlational data. Recently, we have applied Wedeveloped the path analysis algorithm to help us path analysis to the problem of building models of AI discover causal explanations of how a complex AI programs, which are generally complex and poorly planning system works. The system, called Phoenix understood. For example, we built by hand a path- [Cohenet al., 89], simulates forest fires and the activities analytic causal model of the behavior of the Phoenix of agents such as bulldozers and helicopters. One agent, planner. Path analysis has a huge search space, however. called the fireboss, plans howthe others, whichare semi- If one measures N parameters of a system, then one can autonomous,should fight the fire; but things inevitably go build O(2N2) causal mbdels relating these parameters. wrong,winds shift, plans fail, bulldozers run out of gas, For this reason, we have developed an algorithm that and the fireboss soon has a crisis on its hands.
    [Show full text]
  • Week 2: Causal Inference
    Week 2: Causal Inference Marcelo Coca Perraillon University of Colorado Anschutz Medical Campus Health Services Research Methods I HSMP 7607 2020 These slides are part of a forthcoming book to be published by Cambridge University Press. For more information, go to perraillon.com/PLH. This material is copyrighted. Please see the entire copyright notice on the book's website. 1 Outline Correlation and causation Potential outcomes and counterfactuals Defining causal effects The fundamental problem of causal inference Solving the fundamental problem of causal inference: a) Randomization b) Statistical adjustment c) Other methods The ignorable treatment assignment assumption Stable Unit Treatment Value Assumption (SUTVA) Assignment mechanism 2 Big picture We are going to review the basic framework for understanding causal inference This is a fairly new area of research, although some of the statistical methods have been used for over a century The \new" part is the development of a mathematical notation and framework to understand and define causal effects This new framework has many advantages over the traditional way of understanding causality. For me, the biggest advantage is that we can talk about causal effects without having to use a specific statistical model (design versus estimation) In econometrics, the usual way of understanding causal inference is linked to the linear model (OLS, \general" linear model) { the zero conditional mean assumption in Wooldridge: whether the additive error term in the linear model, i , is correlated with the
    [Show full text]
  • Causal Inference and Data Fusion in Econometrics∗
    TECHNICAL REPORT R-51 First version: Dec, 2019 Last revision: March, 2021 Causal Inference and Data Fusion in Econometrics∗ Paul Hunermund¨ Elias Bareinboim Copenhagen Business School Columbia University [email protected] [email protected] Learning about cause and effect is arguably the main goal in applied economet- rics. In practice, the validity of these causal inferences is contingent on a number of critical assumptions regarding the type of data that has been collected and the substantive knowledge that is available about the phenomenon under investiga- tion. For instance, unobserved confounding factors threaten the internal validity of estimates, data availability is often limited to non-random, selection-biased sam- ples, causal effects need to be learned from surrogate experiments with imperfect compliance, and causal knowledge has to be extrapolated across structurally hetero- geneous populations. A powerful causal inference framework is required in order to tackle all of these challenges, which plague essentially any data analysis to varying degrees. Building on the structural approach to causality introduced by Haavelmo (1943) and the graph-theoretic framework proposed by Pearl (1995), the artificial intelligence (AI) literature has developed a wide array of techniques for causal learn- ing that allow to leverage information from various imperfect, heterogeneous, and biased data sources (Bareinboim and Pearl, 2016). In this paper, we discuss recent advances made in this literature that have the potential to contribute to econo- metric methodology along three broad dimensions. First, they provide a unified and comprehensive framework for causal inference, in which the above-mentioned problems can be addressed in full generality.
    [Show full text]
  • Path Analysis in Mplus: a Tutorial Using a Conceptual Model of Psychological and Behavioral Antecedents of Bulimic Symptoms in Young Adults
    ¦ 2019 Vol. 15 no. 1 Path ANALYSIS IN Mplus: A TUTORIAL USING A CONCEPTUAL MODEL OF PSYCHOLOGICAL AND BEHAVIORAL ANTECEDENTS OF BULIMIC SYMPTOMS IN YOUNG ADULTS Kheana Barbeau a, B, KaYLA Boileau A, FATIMA Sarr A & KEVIN Smith A A School OF Psychology, University OF Ottawa AbstrACT ACTING Editor Path ANALYSIS IS A WIDELY USED MULTIVARIATE TECHNIQUE TO CONSTRUCT CONCEPTUAL MODELS OF psychological, cognitive, AND BEHAVIORAL phenomena. Although CAUSATION CANNOT BE INFERRED BY Roland PfiSTER (Uni- VERSIT¨AT Wurzburg)¨ USING THIS technique, RESEARCHERS UTILIZE PATH ANALYSIS TO PORTRAY POSSIBLE CAUSAL LINKAGES BETWEEN Reviewers OBSERVABLE CONSTRUCTS IN ORDER TO BETTER UNDERSTAND THE PROCESSES AND MECHANISMS BEHIND A GIVEN phenomenon. The OBJECTIVES OF THIS TUTORIAL ARE TO PROVIDE AN OVERVIEW OF PATH analysis, step-by- One ANONYMOUS re- VIEWER STEP INSTRUCTIONS FOR CONDUCTING PATH ANALYSIS IN Mplus, AND GUIDELINES AND TOOLS FOR RESEARCHERS TO CONSTRUCT AND EVALUATE PATH MODELS IN THEIR RESPECTIVE fiELDS OF STUDY. These OBJECTIVES WILL BE MET BY USING DATA TO GENERATE A CONCEPTUAL MODEL OF THE psychological, cognitive, AND BEHAVIORAL ANTECEDENTS OF BULIMIC SYMPTOMS IN A SAMPLE OF YOUNG adults. KEYWORDS TOOLS Path analysis; Tutorial; Eating Disorders. Mplus. B [email protected] KB: 0000-0001-5596-6214; KB: 0000-0002-1132-5789; FS:NA; KS:NA 10.20982/tqmp.15.1.p038 Introduction QUESTIONS AND IS COMMONLY EMPLOYED FOR GENERATING AND EVALUATING CAUSAL models. This TUTORIAL AIMS TO PROVIDE ba- Path ANALYSIS (also KNOWN AS CAUSAL modeling) IS A multi- SIC KNOWLEDGE IN EMPLOYING AND INTERPRETING PATH models, VARIATE STATISTICAL TECHNIQUE THAT IS OFTEN USED TO DETERMINE GUIDELINES FOR CREATING PATH models, AND UTILIZING Mplus TO IF A PARTICULAR A PRIORI CAUSAL MODEL fiTS A RESEARCHER’S DATA CONDUCT PATH analysis.
    [Show full text]
  • STATS 361: Causal Inference
    STATS 361: Causal Inference Stefan Wager Stanford University Spring 2020 Contents 1 Randomized Controlled Trials 2 2 Unconfoundedness and the Propensity Score 9 3 Efficient Treatment Effect Estimation via Augmented IPW 18 4 Estimating Treatment Heterogeneity 27 5 Regression Discontinuity Designs 35 6 Finite Sample Inference in RDDs 43 7 Balancing Estimators 52 8 Methods for Panel Data 61 9 Instrumental Variables Regression 68 10 Local Average Treatment Effects 74 11 Policy Learning 83 12 Evaluating Dynamic Policies 91 13 Structural Equation Modeling 99 14 Adaptive Experiments 107 1 Lecture 1 Randomized Controlled Trials Randomized controlled trials (RCTs) form the foundation of statistical causal inference. When available, evidence drawn from RCTs is often considered gold statistical evidence; and even when RCTs cannot be run for ethical or practical reasons, the quality of observational studies is often assessed in terms of how well the observational study approximates an RCT. Today's lecture is about estimation of average treatment effects in RCTs in terms of the potential outcomes model, and discusses the role of regression adjustments for causal effect estimation. The average treatment effect is iden- tified entirely via randomization (or, by design of the experiment). Regression adjustments may be used to decrease variance, but regression modeling plays no role in defining the average treatment effect. The average treatment effect We define the causal effect of a treatment via potential outcomes. For a binary treatment w 2 f0; 1g, we define potential outcomes Yi(1) and Yi(0) corresponding to the outcome the i-th subject would have experienced had they respectively received the treatment or not.
    [Show full text]
  • Basic Concepts of Statistical Inference for Causal Effects in Experiments and Observational Studies
    Basic Concepts of Statistical Inference for Causal Effects in Experiments and Observational Studies Donald B. Rubin Department of Statistics Harvard University The following material is a summary of the course materials used in Quantitative Reasoning (QR) 33, taught by Donald B. Rubin at Harvard University. Prepared with assistance from Samantha Cook, Elizabeth Stuart, and Jim Greiner. c 2004, Donald B. Rubin Last update: 22 August 2005 1 0-1.2 The perspective on causal inference taken in this course is often referred to as the “Rubin Causal Model” (e.g., Holland, 1986) to distinguish it from other commonly used perspectives such as those based on regression or relative risk models. Three primary features distinguish the Rubin Causal Model: 1. Potential outcomes define causal effects in all cases: randomized experiments and observational studies Break from the tradition before the 1970’s • Key assumptions, such as stability (SUTVA) can be stated formally • 2. Model for the assignment mechanism must be explicated for all forms of inference Assignment mechanism process for creating missing data in the potential outcomes • Allows possible dependence of process on potential outcomes, i.e., confounded designs • Randomized experiments a special case whose benefits for causal inference can be formally stated • 3. The framework allows specification of a joint distribution of the potential outcomes Framework can thus accommodate both assignment-mechanism-based (randomization-based or design- • based) methods and predictive (model-based or Bayesian) methods of causal inference One unified perspective for distinct methods of causal inference instead of two separate perspectives, • one traditionally used for randomized experiment, the other traditionally used for observational studies Creates a firm foundation for methods for dealing with complications such as noncompliance and dropout, • which are especially flexible from a Bayesian perspective 2 0-1.1 Basic Concepts of Statistical Inference for Causal Effects in Experiments and Observational Studies I.
    [Show full text]
  • Causal and Path Model Analysis of the Organizational Characteristics of Civil Defense System Simon Wen-Lon Tai Iowa State University
    Iowa State University Capstones, Theses and Retrospective Theses and Dissertations Dissertations 1972 Causal and path model analysis of the organizational characteristics of civil defense system Simon Wen-Lon Tai Iowa State University Follow this and additional works at: https://lib.dr.iastate.edu/rtd Part of the Sociology Commons Recommended Citation Tai, Simon Wen-Lon, "Causal and path model analysis of the organizational characteristics of civil defense system " (1972). Retrospective Theses and Dissertations. 5280. https://lib.dr.iastate.edu/rtd/5280 This Dissertation is brought to you for free and open access by the Iowa State University Capstones, Theses and Dissertations at Iowa State University Digital Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion in Retrospective Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of Iowa State University Digital Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected]. INFORMATION TO USERS This dissertation was produced from a microfilm copy of the original document. While the most advanced technological means to photograph and reproduce this document have been used, the quality is heavily dependent upon the quality of the original submitted. The following explanation of techniques is provided to help you understand markings or patterns which may appear on this reproduction. 1. The sign or "target" for pages apparently lacking from the document photographed is "Missing Page(s)". If it was possible to obtain the missing page(s) or section, they are spliced into the film along with adjacent pages. This may have necessitated cutting thru an image and duplicating adjacent pages to insure you complete continuity. 2. When an image on the film is obliterated with a large round black mark, it is an indication that the photographer suspected that the copy may have moved during exposure and thus cause a blurred image.
    [Show full text]
  • Generalized Correlations and Kernel Causality Using R Package Generalcorr
    Generalized Correlations and Kernel Causality Using R Package generalCorr Hrishikesh D. Vinod* October 3, 2017 Abstract Karl Pearson developed the correlation coefficient r(X,Y) in 1890's. Vinod (2014) develops new generalized correlation coefficients so that when r∗(Y X) > r∗(X Y) then X is the \kernel cause" of Y. Vinod (2015a) arguesj that kernelj causality amounts to model selection be- tween two kernel regressions, E(Y X) = g1(X) and E(X Y) = g2(Y) and reports simulations favoring kernelj causality. An Rj software pack- age called `generalCorr' (at www.r-project.org) computes general- ized correlations, partial correlations and plausible causal paths. This paper describes various R functions in the package, using examples to describe them. We are proposing an alternative quantification to extensive causality apparatus of Pearl (2010) and additive-noise type methods in Mooij et al. (2014), who seem to offer no R implementa- tions. My methods applied to certain public benchmark data report a 70-75% success rate. We also describe how to use the package to assess endogeneity of regressors. Keywords: generalized measure of correlation, non-parametric regres- sion, partial correlation, observational data, endogeneity. *Vinod: Professor of Economics, Fordham University, Bronx, New York, USA 104 58. E-mail: [email protected]. A version of this paper was presented at American Statistical Association's Conference on Statistical Practice (CSP) on Feb. 19, 2016, in San Diego, California, and also at the 11-th Greater New York Metro Area Econometrics Colloquium, Johns Hopkins University, Baltimore, Maryland, on March 5, 2016. I thank Dr Pierre Marie Windal of Paris for pointing out an error in partial correlation coefficients.
    [Show full text]
  • Elements of Causal Inference
    Elements of Causal Inference Foundations and Learning Algorithms Adaptive Computation and Machine Learning Francis Bach, Editor Christopher Bishop, David Heckerman, Michael Jordan, and Michael Kearns, As- sociate Editors A complete list of books published in The Adaptive Computation and Machine Learning series appears at the back of this book. Elements of Causal Inference Foundations and Learning Algorithms Jonas Peters, Dominik Janzing, and Bernhard Scholkopf¨ The MIT Press Cambridge, Massachusetts London, England c 2017 Massachusetts Institute of Technology This work is licensed to the public under a Creative Commons Attribution- Non- Commercial-NoDerivatives 4.0 license (international): http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/ All rights reserved except as licensed pursuant to the Creative Commons license identified above. Any reproduction or other use not licensed as above, by any electronic or mechanical means (including but not limited to photocopying, public distribution, online display, and digital information storage and retrieval) requires permission in writing from the publisher. This book was set in LaTeX by the authors. Printed and bound in the United States of America. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Names: Peters, Jonas. j Janzing, Dominik. j Scholkopf,¨ Bernhard. Title: Elements of causal inference : foundations and learning algorithms / Jonas Peters, Dominik Janzing, and Bernhard Scholkopf.¨ Description: Cambridge, MA : MIT Press, 2017. j Series: Adaptive computation and machine learning series
    [Show full text]
  • The Book of Why Presentation Transcription
    “The Book of Why” For Epidemiologists Prof. George Davey Smith and Prof. Judea Pearl UCLA May 29, 2019 Start: 3:20 Finish: 46:07 Thanks again for the invite to UCLA. I would first like to ask, and you’ve got to not be influenced by the fact that Judea is here... I want to see who have got ‘The Book of Why’? So that is the majority of people. Keep those hands up, people are holding them up .. they want to get it signed. Who has read any of it? Who has read it all the way through? Okay so, some hands have gone down. Okay, so I have structured this around talking about ’The Book of Why’ from the perspective of an empirical researcher. Also I would imagine some of you who haven’t read ‘The Book of Why’, students might also know the primer that Judea and colleagues wrote as well. So if you have read either of them then this is fine. (Slide 2) I’m going to outline as I see it the value of DAG theory to epidemiology. I’m also going to say a bit about the reality of use of DAGs in epidemiology, some of which has come from my experience of having to read a very large number of papers as the editor of the International Journal of Epidemiology. We were getting 1000 papers a year by the time I was worn out, well Shah Ebrahim and I (there were two of us co-editing it, with a team including Karen Michaels as associate editors).
    [Show full text]
  • Tutorial: Causal Model Search
    Tutorial: Causal Model Search Richard Scheines Carnegie Mellon University Peter Spirtes, Clark Glymour, Joe Ramsey, others 1 Goals 1) Convey rudiments of graphical causal models 2) Basic working knowledge of Tetrad IV 2 Tetrad: Complete Causal Modeling Tool 3 Tetrad 1) Main website: http://www.phil.cmu.edu/projects/tetrad/ 2) Download: http://www.phil.cmu.edu/projects/tetrad/current.html 3) Data files: workshop.new.files.zip in www.phil.cmu.edu/projects/tetrad_download/download/workshop/Data/ 4) Download from Data directory: • tw.txt • Charity.txt • Optional: • estimation1.tet, estimation2.tet • search1.tet, search2.tet, search3.tet 4 Outline 1) Motivation 2) Representing/Modeling Causal Systems 3) Estimation and Model fit 4) Causal Model Search 5 Statistical Causal Models: Goals 1) Policy, Law, and Science: How can we use data to answer a) subjunctive questions (effects of future policy interventions), or b) counterfactual questions (what would have happened had things been done differently (law)? c) scientific questions (what mechanisms run the world) 2) Rumsfeld Problem: Do we know what we do and don’t know: Can we tell when there is or is not enough information in the data to answer causal questions? 6 Causal Inference Requires More than Probability Prediction from Observation ≠ Prediction from Intervention P(Lung Cancer 1960 = y | Tar-stained fingers 1950 = no) ≠ P(Lung Cancer 1960 = y | Tar-stained fingers 1950set = no) In general: P(Y=y | X=x, Z=z) ≠ P(Y=y | Xset=x, Z=z) Causal Prediction vs. Statistical Prediction: Non-experimental data P(Y,X,Z) P(Y=y | X=x, Z=z) (observational study) P(Y=y | X =x, Z=z) Background Knowledge Causal Structure set 7 Causal Search Causal Search: 1.
    [Show full text]